March 10: Quantificational Notions - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 27
About This Presentation
Title:

March 10: Quantificational Notions

Description:

Our partial interpretation may not include some predicates or ... Mx: x is a mammal. The antecedent is true on this interpretation but the consequent is false. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:20
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 28
Provided by: Lyn878
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: March 10: Quantificational Notions


1
March 10 Quantificational Notions
  • Interpretations Every interpretation interprets
    every individual constant, predicate, and
    sentence letter of PL. Our partial interpretation
    may not include some predicates or individual
    constants, but it does interpret them.
  • Lx, Lxy, Lxyz, Lwxyz
  • a, b, c, d, a1, b2
  • Full interpretations are infinitely long as PL
    includes an infinite of predicates, an infinite
    of individual constants, an infinite of
    sentence letters and an infinite of UDs.

2
March 10 Quantificational Notions
  • We use the concept of an interpretation to
    specify the quantificational counterparts of
    truth-functional concepts.
  • Individual sentences of PL fall into 1 of 3
    categories
  • A sentence P of PL is quantificationally true IFF
    P is true on every interpretation.
  • A sentence P of PL is quantificationally false
    IFF P is false on every interpretation.
  • A sentence P is quantificationally indeterminate
    IFF P is neither quantificationally true nor
    quantificationally false.

3
March 10 Quantificational Notions
  • A sentence P of PL is quantificationally true IFF
    P is true on every interpretation.
  • How could we demonstrate that some sentence P is
    quantificationally true given that we cannot
    check all of the infinite interpretations of that
    sentence? We cannot do it with all sentences, but
    we can do it for some using reasoning.
  • Consider for example
  • (?y) (Cy v Cy)

4
  • (?y) (Cy v Cy)
  • We may reason as follows
  • Because the sentence is existentially quantified,
    it is true on an interpretation just in case at
    least one member of the UD satisfies the
    conditions specified by Cy v Cy that is, if
    at least one member of the UD either is C or is
    not C.
  • Without knowing what the interpretation of C is,
    we know that every member of a UD satisfies this
    condition for every interpretation interprets
    C, and every member of the UD is or is not in the
    extension of C.
  • And because, by definition, every interpretation
    has a nonempty set as its UD, then the UD for any
    interpretation has at least one member and hence
    at least one member that satisfies the open
    sentence. So the sentence is quanticationally
    true.

5
  • In general, to show that some sentence P is
    quantificationally true, we may use reasoning to
    show that no matter what the UD is and no matter
    how the individual constants, predicates, and
    sentence letters are interpreted, the sentence
    always turns out to be true. So consider
  • (?x) (?y) Bxy ? (?y) ( ?x) Bxy
  • Whatever the UD and however B is interpreted, we
    know that the antecedent is either true or false.
    If it is true, so is the consequent. If the
    antecedent is false, the sentence is true. So the
    sentence is quantificationally true.

6
  • A sentence P is quantificationally false IFF P is
    false on every interpretation.
  • (?x) Bx (?z) Bz
  • is quantificationally false.
  • If an interpretation makes the left conjunct
    true, then it makes the right conjunct false. If
    it makes the left conjunct false, then the
    sentence is false.
  • As every interpretation includes B as a
    predicate, and however it interprets it, it
    cannot be the case that every member of the UD is
    in the extension of B but one member is not.

7
  • It is not always as easy to demonstrate that a
    sentence is quantificationally true or that it is
    quantificationally false.
  • But we can often show that a sentence is not
    quantificationally true by showing that it is
    false on at least one interpretation.
  • (?x) (Wx ? Mx) ? (?x) Mx
  • 1. UD the set of all living things
  • Wx x is a whale
  • Mx x is a mammal
  • The antecedent is true on this interpretation but
    the consequent is false.

8
  • We can often show that a sentence is not
    quantificationally false by showing that it is
    true on at least one interpretation.
  • (?x) (?y) (Syx ? Sxy)
  • 2. UD the set of positive integers
  • Sxy x is smaller than y
  • IF There is a positive integer x such that all
    positive integers are smaller than x
  • The antecedent is false on this interpretation
    (as no positive integer is smaller than 1), so
    the sentence is true on this interpretation, and
    so the sentence is not quantificationally false.

9
  • We can often show that a sentence is not
    quantificationally false by showing that it is
    true on at least one interpretation.
  • (?x) Ex (?x ) Ex
  • 3. UD the set of positive integers
  • Ex x is even
  • Or consider
  • (Ga (?y) Gy)
  • To construct an interpretation on which this
    sentence is true (and thus not quantificationally
    false), we must construct an interpretation on
    which Ga (?y) Gy is false. And that means
    making one or the other of the conjuncts false.

10
  • (Ga (?y) Gy)
  • We must construct an interpretation on which Ga
    (?y) Gy is false. And that means making one or
    the other of the conjuncts false.
  • 4. UD Set of positive integers
  • Gx x is even
  • a 2
  • Here the left conjunct is false and so is the
    conjunction

11
  • Again, we can show a sentence is not
    quantificationally true, or that it is not
    quantificationally false, by constructing a
    single interpretation that demonstrates this.
  • But we cannot construct a single interpretation
    that will demonstrate that a sentence is
    quantificationally true or that it is
    quantificationally false. For some sentences, we
    can arrive at such a conclusion by reasoning but
    for many, we cannot.

12
  • A sentence P of PL is quantificationally
    indeterminate IFF P is neither quantificationally
    true nor quantificationally false.
  • We show that a sentence is quantificationally
    indeterminate by constructing two
    interpretations one on which it is true (to show
    that it is not quantificationally false) and one
    on which it is false (to show that it is not
    quantificationally true).

13
  • A sentence P of PL is quantificationally
    indeterminate IFF P is neither quantificationally
    true not quantificationally false.
  • We showed, using interpretation 4, that the
    following sentence is not quantificationally
    false by finding an interpretation on which it is
    true (Ga (?y) Gy). Now we need an
    interpretation on which it is false to show that
    it is also not quantificationally true.
  • This means we need an interpretation on which Ga
    (?y) Gy is true.

14
  • This means we need an interpretation on which Ga
    (?y) Gy is true.
  • 5. UD set of positive integers
  • Gx x is odd
  • a 2
  • On this interpretation, Ga is true (for 2 is not
    odd) and (?y) Gy) is true (for there is at least
    one odd positive integer). So the conjunction is
    true, and its negation is false.
  • Interpretations 4 and 5 demonstrate that the
    sentence (Ga (?y) Gy is quantificationally
    indeterminate.

15
  • Finding an interpretation on which a sentence is
    true or on which it is false takes some
    ingenuity.
  • Determine if the sentence is one whose
    quantificational status can be settled by an
    interpretation or can be settled by reasoning (or
    by neither).
  • Guidelines Examine the kind of sentence it is.
  • If it is a truth-functional compound, use the
    truth conditions for that kind of compound.
  • If the sentence is universally quantified, then
    the sentence is true IFF the condition specified
    after the quantifier is satisfied by all members
    of the UD you choose.

16
  • If the sentence is existentially quantified, then
    it will be true IFF the condition specified after
    the quantifier is satisfied by at least one
    member of the UD.
  • Sometimes, the desired interpretation can not be
    found. For example
  • If a sentence is quantificationally true, there
    is no interpretation on which it is false, and
    any attempt to construct an interpretation on
    which the sentence is false will fail.
  • The same point holds for quantificationally false
    sentences.
  • A set of positive integers is always a good
    choice for your UD as you construct
    interpretations.

17
Quantificational notions
  • An argument of PL is quantificationally valid IFF
    there is no interpretation on which every premise
    is true and the conclusion is false.
  • An argument of PL is quantificationally invalid
    IFF the argument is not quantificationally valid.

18
  • (?x) (Fx v Gx)
  • (?x) Fx
  • ------------------
  • (?x) Gx
  • is quantificationally valid.
  • Suppose that on some interpretation both premises
    are true. If the first premise is true, then some
    member x of the UD is either F or G.
  • If the second premise is true, then no member of
    the UD is F. Therefore, because the member that
    is either F or G is not F, it must be G. Thus
    (?x) Gx will be true on any such interpretation.

19
  • Demonstrating that an argument is not
    guantificationally valid find an interpretation
    in which all of its premises are true and its
    conclusion is false. Consider
  • (?x) (?y) Fy ? Fx
  • (?y) Fy
  • -----------------------
  • (?x) Fx
  • We can make the first premise true by
    interpreting F so that at least one member of the
    UD is in its extension for then that object
    will satisfy the condition specified by (?y) Fy
    ? Fx beause it will satisfy its consequent.

20
  • (?x) (?y) Fy ? Fx
  • (?y) Fy
  • -----------------------
  • (?x) Fx
  • The second premise will be true if at least one
    member of the UD is not in the extension of F. So
    F will have some, but not all, members of the UD
    in its extension. And because some members will
    be in the extension, the conclusion will be
    false.
  • 6 UD set of positive integers
  • Fx x is odd.

21
  • Again, there are asymmetries in what we can
    prove.
  • We can prove an argument is valid only on
    specific interpretations, not all possible
    interpretations, although some we can prove are
    valid by reasoning.
  • But we can prove an argument is
    quantificationally invalid by finding a single
    interpretation on which it is not valid (as to be
    quantificationally valid, an argument must be
    such that there is no interpretation on which all
    its premises are true and its conclusion is
    false).

22
  • Again, there are asymmetries in what we can
    prove.
  • We can also prove an argument is not
    quantificationally invalid by finding an
    interpretation on which it is valid.
  • Quantificational equivalency
  • Sentences P and Q are quantificationally
    equivalent IFF there is no interpretation on
    which P and Q have different truth values.
  • The following are quantificationally equivalent
  • (?x) Fx ? Ga
  • (?x) (Fx ? Ga)

23
  • (?x) Fx ? Ga
  • (?x) (Fx ? Ga)
  • We reason as follows
  • Suppose that (?x) Fx ? Ga is true on some
    interpretation. Then (?x) Fx is either true or
    false on this interpretation.
  • If (?x) Fx is true, then so is Ga. But then since
    Ga is true, every object x in the UD is such that
    if x is F, then a is G. So (?x) (Fx ? Ga) is true.

24
  • (?x) Fx ? Ga
  • (?x) (Fx ? Ga)
  • If (?x) Fx is false, then every object x in the
    UD is such that if x is F (which we assume here
    it is not), then a is G and the whole sentence is
    true. Again, (?x) (Fx ? Ga) is also true on
    that interpretation.

25
  • (?x) Fx ? Ga
  • (?x) (Fx ? Ga)
  • Now suppose that (?x) Fx ? Ga is false on some
    interpretation.
  • Then (?x) Fx is true and Ga is false. But if (?x)
    Fx is true, then some object x in the UD is in
    the extension of F. This object does not satisfy
    the condition that if it is F (which it is), then
    a is G (which it is not on our present
    assumption). So (?x) (Fx ? Ga) is false if (?x)
    Fx ? Ga is false.
  • Taken together with the result that if one is
    true, so is the other, we have demonstrated that
    the 2 sentences are quantificationally equivalent.

26
Quantificational consistency
  • A set of sentences of PL is quantificationally
    consistent IFF there is at least one
    interpretation on which all the members of the
    set are true.
  • A set of sentences of PL is quantificationally
    inconsistent IFF the set is not
    quantificationally consistent.
  • The set (?x) Bax, Bba v (?x) Bax is
    quantificationally consistent.

27
  • (?x) Bax, Bba v (?x) Bax
  • 7. UD set of possible integers
  • Bxy x is less than or equal to y
  • a 1
  • b 2
  • On this interpretation (?x) Bax is true since 1
    is less than or equal to every positive integer.
  • So, too, Bba is true since 2 is neither less
    than nor equal to 1, so Bba v (?x) Bax is true
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com