Title: Grice on Meaning
1Grice on Meaning
2Communication
- Communication is primarily a matter of a speaker
seeking either to inform a hearer of something or
to enjoin some action upon him - where enjoin
should be construed broadly to include not only
commanding, but requesting, advising, etc. - This is not to deny that language has other uses
that will be one my main points once we complete
our study of communicative behavior.
3Grice Meaning (1957) Preliminaries
- Grice presents his first attempts to say exactly
what meaning is. It ought to be possible, he
suggests, to explicate the meaning of an
expression (or any other sign) in terms of what
its users do with it, i.e. in terms of what its
users (could/would/should) mean by it on
particular occasions of use.
4Two main ideas
- 1. The most basic notion of meaning is that of
an utterer U meaning something by doing something
on a particular occasion. All other notions of
meaning are to be treated as derivative and
explicated in terms of the more basic notion. - As Grice puts it it is necessary to
distinguish between a notion of meaning which is
relativized to the users of words or expressions
and one that is not so relativizedof the two
notions the unrelativized notion is posterior to,
and has to be understood in terms of, the
relativized notion what words mean is a matter
of what people mean by them.
5- 2. The locution by uttering x, U meant that p
can be analyzed in terms of complex
audience-directed intentions on the part of U. - What U means by producing x on a given occasion
is a function of what U intends, in a complex
way, to get across to his audience. The basic
idea in Meaning is, roughly, that for an
indicative-type utterance, the locution by
uttering x, U meant that p is true iff U uttered
x intending to produce in audience A the belief
that p by means of As recognition of Us
intention.
6Central to Grices Analysis of meaning
- Attempt to analyze or explicate meaning in terms
of (for him) more basic notions such as
intention, belief, desire, and recognition. - The analysis of locutions of the forms X did Y
intentionally, X caused Y, X is true, X
entails Y, X is red, and so on, has been
regarded by many philosophers as a central task
of philosophy. There are a number of different
views about the exact aims and proper methods of
analysis. - Grices conception appears to have a reductive
and explicative flavor in that it appears to be
his view that locutions of the forms by uttering
X, U meant that p, X means p, and by
uttering X, U said that p can be wholly
explicated without appealing to semantical
concepts.
7- Grice seeks to explain what it is for someone or
something to mean something (but not in a sense
of mean found in sentences such as those spots
mean measles, that buzz means someone is at the
door, or that groan means Bill is in pain.). - He starts out with what people mean rather than
with what this or that expression, sign, or
action means. - His plan is to analyze utterers meaning in terms
of complex audience directed intentions of the
utterer, and to analyze utterance-type meaning
(e.g., sentence and word meaning) in terms of
utterers meaning.
8Elaborate Basic Analysis
- Variety of Sentences which employ the verb to
mean - 1. He meant to tell her.
- 2. Music means a lot to me.
- 3. This time I really mean it.
- 4. Spots mean measles.
- 5. By uttering Its raining he meant that its
raining.
9- In (1), where the verb is followed by an
adverbial occurrence of an infinite, it can be
replaced with intends - In (2), where it is followed by an adverbial
quantity, it can be replaced with matters. - In (3), where it is followed by a pronoun, it can
be replaced by serious and sincere about.
10- (4) and (5) look replaceable by nothing other
than trivial variants of means as in 'signify. - (4) is not concerned with language or
communication. The use of means in (5) can but
need not concern language but always
communication. - Grice distinguishes natural (4) meaning from
non-natural (5) meaning.
11Observations about the two uses
- Natural 'x means that p' entails that p. If
those spots on your face mean that you have
measles, then you have measles. - Non-natural 'x means that p' does not entail
that p. If you mean that its raining with your
utterance of its raining it does not follow
that it is raining. - N We cannot argue from the sentence 'Those spots
mean measles' to any conclusion about what was
meant those spots. Its not as if nature meant to
convey that you had measles by those spots. - NN We can argue from a sentence like Its
raining' to a conclusion about what was meant by
those words. - Look at Grice (1957) for more disanalogies.
12Goal to give an analysis of non-natural meaning
- 1. Utterance x meansnn something
- But what about (2)?
- 2. Speaker S meansnn something
- (1) and (2) are themselves ambiguous
134 readings
- 1a. X meansnn something (on a particular
occasion). - 1b. X meansnn (timeless) something.
- Draw type/token distinction.
- 2a. S meansnn something by x (on a particular
occasion). - 2b. S meansnn (timeless) something by x.
144 more readings whole utterance or parts?
- 1a. X (a whole utterance) meansnn something (on
a particular occasion) - 1a'. A (an utterance part) meansnn something (on
a particular occasion). - 1b. X (a whole utterance) meansnn (timeless)
something - 1b'. A (an utterance part) meansnn (timeless)
something. - Grice first we analyze whole utterance because
not all utterances are structured flag-waving,
whistling, nods, hand-waving, etc. - Grice second we analyze an utterance on a
particular occasion rather than timeless
15We analyze 1a/2a before 1b/2b
- Final target S means something on a particular
occasion by x (Grice, 1957) - Question what are we trying to accomplish with
an analysis? Reduction? If not that, then what?
Explication? Whats that?
16Stevensons Causal Proposal
- For x to mean something, x must have (roughly)
a tendency to produce in an audience some
attitude (cognitive or otherwise) and a tendency,
in the case of a speaker, to be produced by that
attitude, these tendencies being dependent on "an
elaborate process of conditioning attending the
use of the sign in communication. (Grice 1957,
p.379, quoting C.L. Stevenson) - Problems? Tuxedo and dance we are talking about
communication and not merely info. - Other counter-example J is athlete -gt J is
tall
17Analysis I
- Grices first proposal 'S means something by
uttering x' is true iff S uttered x intending to
induce a response in some audience (and to say
what the response is is to say what S means) - (Well focus on belief/assertion/indicatives for
now but of course the response might be an
action/command/imperative, e.g.)
18Counter-Example to I
- A may leave Bs handkerchief by the scene of a
crime in order to induce in the detective on the
case the response of believing that B was the
criminal. Yet leaving the handkerchief does not
mean that B was the criminal. (Grice, 1957, pp.
381-382) - Why not? The case leaves out any communication
between A and the detective. - To see why, compare this case with the one where
A unintentionally drops it while leaving the
crime scene. In both cases the detective will
come to believe B did it (relying on the same
evidence) - Use the photograph vs. drawing case intentions
of shower irrelevant in first case but not in
second. - Difference between inferring from an action what
might be so from that action communicating what
is so to you.
19Analysis II Fix up of I
- II. S meant something by uttering x iff S uttered
x intending - A. that Ss utterance of x produce a certain
response r in a certain audience A B. that A
recognizes Ss intention. - Solves last problemdo you see that?
20Counter-Example to II
- Herod presents Salome with Johns head on a
platter, intending her to have the response to
believing that John is dead and intending also
that she recognize that he intends her to believe
John is dead. - So both conditions in II are satisifed.
- Yet his action does not nn-mean this. It doesnt
nn-mean anything. - Whats missing is a communicative link between H
and S. He is not trying to communicate that J is
dead hes showing her that he is.
21Elaboration of problems with II
- S comes to have the belief that J is dead because
she sees his severed head. - The connection between Hs intention and Ss
response is incidental. - What we need is a connection between the
audiences recognition of the speakers intention
and the response the audience is intended to
have. - We need some assurance that the the response is
dependent upon the recognition of the speakers
intention otherwise, theres no difference
between letting or getting someone know or think
something and telling her that it is so.
22Fix up II Analysis III
- III. S meant something by uttering x iff S
uttered x intending - a. that Ss utterance of x produce a certain
response, r, in a certain audience A - b. that A recognize Ss intention (a) and
- c. that As recognition of Ss intention (a)
function as As reason for r. (note reason for
response, not just a cause)
23Grices Strategy
- The difference between a mere sound or mark and
an act of communication is this - when there is communication, agents with
appropriate audience-directed beliefs and
intentions produce the sounds. - To this end, Grice requires the audiences
response be occasioned by a recognition of
speaker intentions.
24Three general problems with (III)
- (i) The first clause problem.
- (ii) The third clause problem.
- (iii) The analysis is too weak.
25The first clause problem
- Grice provides a number of examples in which it
would be correct to say that U means that p but
incorrect to say that U intends A to believe that
p. - Suppose U is answering an examination question
and says The Battle of Waterloo was fought in
1815. Here U meant that the Battle of Waterloo
was fought in 1815 but U did not intend the
examiner to think that The Battle of Waterloo was
fought in 1815 (typically, U will be under the
impression that the examiner already knows the
answer).
26Grices Response to first clause problem
- Grice suggests that clause (a) in III be changed
to (a) - III. S meant that p by uttering x iff S uttered x
intending - a. that Ss utterance of x produce a belief in A
that p - a. That Ss utterance of x produce a belief in
A that S thinks that p.
27Still worries with a?
- The suggested revision is that it does not fit in
well with the commonly held view that the primary
purpose of communication is the transfer of
information about the world on the revised
account, the primary purpose seems to be the
transfer of information about ones mental
states. - Even if the proposed revision does constitute an
improvement, it does not weaken the analysis to
let in cases of reminding. Suppose S knows that A
thinks that p but needs reminding. So S does
something by which he means that p. Not only does
it seem incorrect to say that S intends A to
think that p S knows that A already thinks that
pit also seems incorrect to say that S intends
A to think S thinks that p (S may know that A
already thinks S thinks that p).
28Deeper problem with II?
- Does Grice pay too much attention to examples in
which S intends to induce in A some propositional
attitude or other, and so, has Grice mistakenly
taken a particular type of intention that does in
fact accompany many utterancesthe subintention
specified in clause (a)to be an essential
ingredient of communicative behavior? There are
many cases of meaning involving linguistic (or
otherwise conventional) utterances in which S
does not seek to induce in an audience any
propositional (or affective) attitude. - It is not at all clear what attitude I M-intend
to impart when making a promise by uttering a
sentence of the form I promise to f. - Sometimes I dont care whether I am believed or
not I just feel it is my duty to speak up. - Only an egocentric author intends me to believe
that p because he has said so
29One last effort
- These are genuine difficulties for Grices
analysis as it stands, and they suggest that the
specification of the type of response mentioned
in IIIa needs to be weakened to something like
the following - (a) A actively to entertain the
belief/thought/proposition that p. - Of course, in many cases S also intends A to go
on to believe that p, but this fact would not
enter into the analysis of utterers meaning.
30(ii) The third clause problem.
- The original motivation for clause (b) is
perfectly clear. It is not enough, Grice points
out, for S to mean that p, that S utter x
intending A to think that p. Recall, S might
leave Bs handkerchief near the scene of the
murder with the intention of getting the
detective (actively) to entertain the thought
that B is the murderer. But there is no
temptation to say that by leaving the
handkerchief, S meant that B is the murderer.
Hence clause (b), which requires S to intend A to
recognize the intention specified in the first
clause (however stated). But what about IIIc?
31- Grice wants IIIc in order to filter out cases in
which some natural feature of the utterance in
question makes it completely obvious that p.
Recall He is worried by cases like (a) Herod
presents Salome with the head of John the Baptist
on a charger (b) in response to an invitation to
play squash, Bill displays his bandaged leg. - According to Grice, we do not want to say that
Herod meant that John the Baptist was dead nor
do we want to say that Bill meant that his leg
was bandaged (though we might want to say that he
meant that he could not play squash, or even that
he had a bad leg).
32The analysis is too weak
- Suppose A, a friend of mine, is about to buy a
house. I think the house is rat-infested, but I
dont want to mention this outright to A so I let
rats loose in the house knowing that A is
watching me. I know that A does not know that I
know that he is watching me do this. I know A
will not take the presence of my rats to be
natural evidence that the house is rat-infested
but I do know, indeed I intend, that A will take
my letting rats loose in the house as grounds for
thinking that I intend to induce in him the
belief that the house is rat-infested. Conditions
III(a)-(c) above are fulfilled. But surely it is
not correct to say that by letting rats loose in
the house I mean that the house is rat-infested.
33Fix up
- The problem is that in this example my intentions
are not, as Strawson puts it, wholly overt. One
possible remedy involves adding a fourth clause - (d) A to recognize that U intends (b).
- But as Strawson points out, with enough ingenuity
the same sort of - counterexample can still be generated, and then
we need a fifth clause, then a sixth, and so on.
At the end of Utterers Meaning and Intentions,
and again at the end of Meaning Revisited,
Grice proposes a way out of blocking an infinite
regress by adding a condition that would prohibit
any sneaky intention instead of adding a
fourth (fifth, .. .) clause, the idea is to add a
second part to the entire analysis, the rough
import of which is that S does not intend A to be
deceived about Ss intentions (a)-(c). As long as
S does not have a deceptive intention of this
sort, s is deemed to mean that p.
34Grices final effort
- In view of the earlier discussion of clause
III(c), you might be inclined, then, to take
something like the following as the
characterization of utterers meaning emerging
from - Grices writings
- (IV) By uttering x, S meant that p iff for some
audience A, - (a) S uttered x intending A actively to
entertain the thought that p (or the thought that
S believes that p) - (b) S uttered x intending A to recognize that S
intends A actively to entertain the thought that
p - (c) S does not intend A to be deceived about Ss
intentions (a) and (b).
35Is III sufficient?
- A soldier is captured. He has invaluable info
that his capturers want and so they torture him.
They torture him (a) intending to produce a
response in him of his offering info (b) they
intend that he recognize that this is their
intention and (c) they intend that he offer the
info because he recognizes that they have this
intention. - But it does not seem that their act of torturing
him means that he should offer his information. - Why not?
36Answer
- Because the prisoner can know what his capturers
intention is w/o having to be tortured. The
torture is merely an inducement. - What we need is that the audience came to
recognize the speakers intention at least in
part on the basis of being presented with the
utterance.
37Analysis IV
- S meant something by uttering x iff S uttered x
intending - a. that x have a certain feature f
- b. that A recognize that x has f
- c. that A infer at least in part from the fact
that x is f that S uttered x intending - d. that Ss utterance of x produce response r in
A and - e. that As recognition of Ss intention (d)
should function as partly As reason for having r.
38Key to Analysis IV
- As recognition of the speakers intention is
based on As recognition of some feature of the
utterance. - The relevant features to our concerns are
meaning-bearing features. - Which ones are those?
39Examples of Meaning-Bearing Features
- 1. S utters grr intending A to recognize that
grr has the feature of resembling the sound
that dogs make when they are angry and intending
A to infer that S intends A to believe that S is
angry. - 2. S utters The cat is on the mat intending A
to recognize that this string is an English
sentence that means that the cat is on the mat,
and intending A to infer that S intends A to
believe as much.
40Note
- S intends A to recognize the meaning-bearing
feature of the string only if S believes that A
speaks English or understands certain natural
signs. - In this regard (IV) captures the idea that a
basis for communication between individuals
requires a certain common understanding.
41Counter-examples to sufficiency of IV
- Strawson (1964) Suppose S puts a wet umbrella
in the entrance to your apartment knowing you
will see it there. Indeed, S knows that A sees
him wet the umbrella and put it there and S also
knows that A does not know that S knows A is
watching and so S knows that A will not think
that the umbrella is wet from rain. Still, S
intends that A will take Ss putting the wet
umbrella there as evidence that S intends A to
believe that it is raining. Further, S knows
that A is convinced of Ss reliability and
sincerity. - Strawson says we would not want in this case to
say that Ss putting the wet umbrella there
communicates that it is raining.
42Strawson on his counter-example
- Whats missing is that A is not intended to know
that S knows that A is watching S. - It seems a minimum further condition of his
trying to communicate with A that he S should
not only intend A to recognixe h is intention to
get A to think that it is raining but that he
should also intend A to recognize his intention
to get A to recognize his intention to get A to
think that (Strawson, p. 29).
43Strawsons Analysis V
- V. S meant something by uttering x iff S uttered
x intending - a. that x have a certain feature f
- b. that A recognize that x has f
- c. that A infer at least in part from the fact
that x is f that S uttered x intending - d. that Ss utterance of x produce response r in
A - e. that As recognition of Ss intention (d)
should function as partly As reason for having
r. - f. That A should recognize Ss intention (c).
44Counter-example to V
- S intends to get A to leave the room by singing
Hey Jude. S intends A to recognize that S is
singing Hey Jude and that A should infer from
this that S is singing to get A to leave the
room. (S sings horribly and A is sensitive to
this.) - Further S intends A to recognize Ss intention to
get A to leave, for S wishes to show his contempt
for A. - Also, S intends that A believe that S plans to
get A out by means of his singing S intends that
As reason for leaving will be As recognition of
Ss intention to him to leave. - This satisfies V but is it a case of
communication?
45Moral of Counter-Examples
- Im less interested in intricacies of the
counter-examples than in why they keep arising.
Theres a pattern here. - In each case genuine communication is frustrated
because of an element of deceit. - And just as there is a pattern to the
counter-examples theres a pattern to the
remedies. We keep adding intentions for say, an
analysis invokes n intentions, with a new
counter-example we ask that A recognize Ss n-th
intention in the next analysis. - Each time we do that we are trying to transform a
case of merely getting something across into a
genuine case of communication (by eliminating
deceit).
46Problems with this strategy
- 1. It threatens a regress. In Grices 1969 paper
he suggests we have to stop at a certain point
because speakers cannot have such complex
intentions. Problem is any cut off point leads
to counter-examples. - 2. Another way of thinking of whats going on
here is to notice that we are constantly in a
defensive stance. We are always trying to
eliminate deceit.
47Grices solution
- In the more sophisticated analyses we looked at,
there exist two avenues of communication info
can be passed along either as a result of As
recognition of Ss intention that A recognize the
meaning-bearing feature of Ss utterance or it
can be passed on as a result of As recognition
of some wider intention that S possesses. - In each counter-example S exploits the split in
intentions to deceive A. - Grice tries to force the speakers communicative
intentions into line with the utterances
meaning-bearing features
48Grices new analysis VI
- VI. S meant something by uttering x iff
- (1) S uttered x intending
- a. that x have a certain feature f
- b. that A recognize that x has f
- c. that A infer at least in part from the fact
that x is f that S uttered x intending - d. that Ss utterance of x produce response r in
A - e. that As recognition of Ss intention (d)
should function as partly As reason for having
r. - (2) there is no inference-element E such that S
uttered x intending both - That As determination of r should rely on E and
- That A should think S to intend (a) to be false.
(Grice 1969l, sec. 3)
49Explanation of VI
- (2) is added to rule out deceit.
- He wants to avoid positing an infinity of
backwards looking intentions since that he says
would give us a model that cannot be implement
(by us).