KNOWLEDGE AND ACTION IN RATIONAL DELIBERATION - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 36
About This Presentation
Title:

KNOWLEDGE AND ACTION IN RATIONAL DELIBERATION

Description:

Bounded Procedural Rationality. In this paper it is shown how knowledge can lead to a rational decision for action or inaction based on argumentation process called ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:40
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 37
Provided by: dougwalto
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: KNOWLEDGE AND ACTION IN RATIONAL DELIBERATION


1
KNOWLEDGE AND ACTION IN RATIONAL DELIBERATION
  • Douglas Walton
  • CRRAR
  • 7th Conference on Analytic Philosophy in China,
    Shanghai, Oct. 30, 2011

2
Bounded Procedural Rationality
  • In this paper it is shown how knowledge can lead
    to a rational decision for action or inaction
    based on argumentation process called
    deliberation.
  • The viewpoint adopted is one of bounded
    procedural rationality based on a notion of
    defeasible knowledge.
  • The problem confronted is that decision-making
    about real-world problems needs to be made under
    conditions of uncertainty, and even apparent
    inconsistency where there is both pro and contra
    evidence for a conclusion to be decided.

3
Argumentation Methods
  • It is just in this kind of case that methods of
    argumentation are especially useful.
  • Argumentation can be defined as a procedure to
    identify, analyze and evaluate the arguments on
    both sides of a claim, and to use the evidence
    that is collected by this procedure to determine
    whether to accept the claim or not.
  • It is also a part of argumentation methodology
    that setting a burden of proof on each side by
    determining what kind of arguments are relevant,
    and what standards of proof should be required,
    is an essential requirements of the procedure.

4
First Example
  • Lets consider the case of the student who is
    writing an essay. He is collecting all kinds of
    knowledge from books and periodicals, but he has
    a strict deadline for finishing the assignment.
  • This problem is to determine when he should stop
    searching for new knowledge and attempt to write
    the essay. The longer he delays writing in order
    to search for new knowledge, the better the essay
    will be. But if he delays too long, he will not
    have enough time to properly write the essay, and
    the result will be that the essay will not be
    very good.
  • The general problem in many comparable cases of
    this kind is one of when to terminate the process
    of deliberation and close off the collecting of
    new knowledge.

5
Second Example
  • Another kind of example can also be cited. In
    July 2010, scientists found a way of altering the
    DNA of mosquitoes that shortens their lifespan so
    that malarial parasites to not have enough time
    to grow to maturity. This discovery gives the
    scientists the possibility of releasing a
    malaria-proof mosquito into the wild, thereby
    eliminating mosquitoes that can cause malaria.
    Right now malaria kills about one million people
    every year.
  • However, there is a problem. Altering the DNA of
    mosquitoes might make them better carriers of
    other diseases.
  • This proposal cannot be carried out for another
    ten years, and even then, there may be no way to
    know what the consequences are.
  • Once the malaria-proof mosquito is produced by
    the scientists, even though we can study the
    problem and collect knowledge about it, we will
    never know what all the side-effects will be
    until we release the new mosquitoes into the
    wild.
  • R. M. Schneidermann, God lives in a Lab in
    Arizona, Newsweek, August 9, 2010, 8.

6
Aquinas Poses the Problem
  • Aquinas asked the question, May deliberation go
    on endlessly? and answered it in his Summa
    Theologiae in Question 14, Article 6 quoted from
    (Blackfriars Edition, 155)
  •  
  • 1. Yes, apparently, for it is about the
    particular things which are the concern of
    practical knowledge. These are infinite.
    Accordingly no term is to be set to the inquiry
    of deliberation about them.
  • 2. Further, we have to weigh up not only what has
    to be done, but also how to clear away the
    obstacles. Now any number of objections to any
    particular course of action can be put up and
    knocked down in our mind. Therefore there is no
    stop to our questioning about how to deal with
    them.
  • 3. Moreover, the inquiry instituted by
    demonstrative science does not lead back
    indefinitely, but arrives at self-evident
    principles which are altogether certain. Such
    certainty, however, cannot be found in contingent
    and individual facts, which are variable and
    uncertain. Deliberation, therefore, goes on
    endlessly.

7
The Closed World Assumption
  • The closed world assumption is the inference
    drawn that any positive fact not specified in a
    given database may be assumed to be false, on the
    basis that all of the relevant knowledge has been
    specified (Reiter, 1987).
  • Consider the familiar example (Reiter 1980, 69)
    of scanning an airline monitor. Lets say that no
    direct flight is listed from Windsor to Shanghai.
    The closed world assumption is that all the
    relevant data on flights leaving from Windsor at
    this time are listed on the monitor on the
    airport website.
  • So if a direct Windsor to Shanghai flight is not
    listed, it is reasonable to draw the conclusion
    that no such flight is available. In this
    situation, the closed world assumption is
    reasonable to invoke, because we have good reason
    to assume that the knowledge base is complete.

8
Another Example
  • The official listing of baseball statistics about
    hits, home runs and so forth, is known to not
    only be complete for the major-league baseball
    teams, but also highly reliable, because there
    are many fans who are passionate about keeping
    baseball statistics, and who would immediately
    challenge any error they might find in the
    baseball statistics knowledge base.
  • So if we were to look in the database and see
    that some information about some home runs
    alleged to be hit in 1936 was not in it, we could
    very confidently invoke the closed world
    assumption to draw the conclusion that there were
    no such home runs hit that year.

9
Scheme for Practical Reasoning
  • Major Premise I have a goal G.
  • Minor Premise Carrying out action A is a means
    to realize G.
  • Conclusion I ought (practically speaking) to
    carry out action A.
  • The first-person singular pronoun I in the
    scheme for practical reasoning above represents
    an agent. An agent is an entity that has goals
    and knowledge about its circumstances, can take
    action in its circumstances based on this
    knowledge, and can also see the consequences of
    its actions so that it can correct them through
    feedback.

10
Critical Questions Matching Scheme
  • CQ1 What other goals do I have that should be
    considered that might conflict with G?
  • CQ2 What alternative actions to my bringing
    about A that would also bring about G should be
    considered?
  • CQ3 Among bringing about A and these alternative
    actions, which is arguably the most efficient?
  • CQ4 What grounds are there for arguing that it
    is practically possible for me to bring about A?
  • CQ5 What consequences of my bringing about A
    should also be taken into account?

11
How to Use Critical Questions
  • These five basic critical questions for practical
    reasoning are not complete.
  • As shown in (Walton 1990), each of these five
    critical questions has critical sub-questions.
  • The five basic critical questions are meant as
    devices to help a critic or student of critical
    thinking find weak points in an argument of this
    type that can be challenged or cast into doubt.

12
Value-based Practical Reasoning
  • Value-based practical reasoning (Atkinson,
    Bench-Capon and McBurney, 2006) is made up of two
    more basic schemes, the one for practical
    reasoning and the one for argument from values
    (Bench-Capon, 2003). The argumentation scheme for
    value-based practical reasoning has this form
    (Atkinson, Bench-Capon and McBurney, 2006).
  •  
  • Scheme for Value-based Practical Reasoning
  •  
  • In the current circumstances R
  • we should perform action A
  • to achieve New Circumstances S
  • which will realize some goal G
  • which will promote some value V.

13
Questioning versus Arguing
  • Asking the critical question C5 needs to be
    backed up with some evidence of what the negative
    consequences are before an argument based on
    practical reasoning is refuted.
  • When this happens, the asking of this critical
    question can also be analyzed as a
    counter-argument.
  • Argument from negative consequences cites the
    consequences of a proposed course of action as a
    reason against taking that course of action.
  • This argument also has a positive form in which
    positive consequences of an action are cited as a
    reason for carrying out the action.

14
Argument from Consequences
  • Scheme for Argument from Positive Consequences
  •  
  • Major Premise Its having good consequences is a
    reason for doing something.
  • Minor Premise If A is brought about, good
    consequences will plausibly occur.
  • Conclusion A should be brought about.
  •  
  • Scheme for Argument from Negative Consequences
  •  
  • Major Premise Its having good consequences is a
    reason for not doing something.
  • Minor Premise If A is brought about, then bad
    consequences will occur.
  • Conclusion A should not be brought about.

15
The Carneades System
  • The Carneades Argumentation System uses
    argumentation schemes and critical questions for
    argument analysis and evaluation (Gordon, 2010).
  • Carneades is a computational model consisting of
    mathematical structures and functions on them
    (Gordon, Prakken and Walton, 2007).
  • Carneades models the structure of arguments, the
    acceptability of statements, and burdens of
    proof.
  • Carneades has an open source graphical user
    interface (http//carneades.github.com/ ).

16
Tweety Example
17
Wiki Example 1
18
Problem with Critical Questions
  • It would be very nice if the five critical
    questions for practical reasoning could be
    represented as additional premises of the
    argumentation scheme. Then we could represent the
    critical questions as implicit assumptions of the
    argument when we analyze the argument using an
    argument diagram of the standard kind.
  • However, there is a problem. With some critical
    questions, simply asking the question is enough
    to defeat the original argument, whereas with
    other critical questions, merely asking the
    critical question is not enough to defeat the
    argument. In order to defeat the argument some
    evidence has to be given to back up the critical
    question.

19
Solution to the Problem
  • To solve this problem, the Carneades system
    offers two ways of responding the asking of a
    critical question by distinguishing three types
    of premises in argumentation scheme, called
    ordinary premises, assumptions and exceptions
    (Walton and Gordon, 2009).
  • Ordinary premises are explicitly stated premises
    of the argumentation scheme. They are assumed to
    hold tentatively, but if challenged they may have
    to be given up.
  • Assumptions, like ordinary premises, are assumed
    to be true.
  • Exceptions are assumed not to hold, and therefore
    they do not defeat an argument unless backed up
    by evidence to support them.

20
Carneades Map of Practical Reasoning
21
Evaluating Arguments
  • Based on this method of representing the critical
    questions of an argumentation scheme by
    representing them as different kinds of premises
    of scheme, Carneades has a computational method
    for evaluating arguments (Gordon and Walton,
    2006).
  • At each stage of the argumentation process, an
    effective method (decision procedure) is used for
    testing whether the conclusion of an argument is
    acceptable or not, given knowledge about whether
    its premises are acceptable or not.
  • The assumptions represent undisputed facts, the
    current consensus of the participants, or the
    commitments or beliefs of some agent, depending
    on the task.
  • The evaluation of the given argument may depend
    on the proof standard applicable to the
    proposition at issue, and on the dialogue
    procedure the argument is embedded in.

22
Dialogue Models
  • Dialogue models have rules on how participants
    should ideally speak and respond in order to
    achieve a common conversational goal.
  • Dialogue models of argumentation (Walton and
    Krabbe, 1995) have proved their usefulness in
    argumentation studies, artificial intelligence,
    and multi-agent systems (Bench-Capon, 2003
    Prakken, 2005).
  • Walton and Krabbe (1995) identified six primary
    types of dialogue information-seeking dialogue,
    inquiry, deliberation, persuasion dialogue,
    negotiation and eristic (quarrelsome) dialogue.

23
Formal Dialogue Systems
  • A dialogue is generally a group activity with
    multiple participants, but in the simplest case
    there are only two parties called the proponent
    and the respondent.
  • A dialogue is defined in the Carneades model as
    an ordered 3-tuple ltO, A, Cgt where O is the
    opening stage, A is the argumentation stage, and
    C is the closing stage (Gordon and Walton, 2009,
    5).
  • Dialogue protocols regulate the types of moves
    that are allowed and how a participant must
    respond to a previous move made by the other
    party (Walton and Krabbe, 1995).
  • So far, Carneades has not provided protocols for
    deliberation dialogues, but there is a formal
    model.

24
Deliberation Dialogue
  • The initial situation of deliberation is the need
    for action arising out of a choice between
    alternative competing courses of action.
  • The collective goal of this type of dialogue is
    for the participants to collectively decide on
    what is the best available proposal for action
    that has been put forward for the group at the
    proposal stage, once that stage has been reached.
  • Once that stage has been reached, the
    participants evaluate the proposals in a process
    in which each party puts forward its own
    proposals and critically evaluates the competing
    proposals put forward by others.
  • There is also a prior inform stage where the
    facts collected and shared among the
    participants.
  • In a successful deliberation, the strengths and
    weaknesses of each proposal are brought out by
    the discussion, and this evidence is used to
    judge which proposal is the one that should be
    selected to move forward with.

25
8 Stages of Deliberation Dialogue
  • Open In this stage a governing question is
    raised about what is to be done. A governing
    question, like Where shall we go for dinner this
    evening? is posed.
  • Inform This stage includes discussion of
    desirable goals, values, constraints on possible
    actions, evaluation criteria for proposals, and
    determination of relevant facts.
  • Propose Proposals cite possible action-options
    relevant to the governing question
  • Consider This stage concerns commenting on the
    proposals from various perspectives.
  • Revise Goals, constraints, perspectives, and
    action-options are revised in light of comments
    presented and information gathering as well as
    fact-checking.
  • Recommend A proposal for action is recommended
    for acceptance or non-acceptance by each
    participant.
  • Confirm The participants can confirm acceptance
    of the recommended proposal according to some
    procedure they have agreed on.
  • Close The termination of the dialogue takes
    place.
  • (Hitchcock, McBurney and Parsons, 2007)

26
Judging a Deliberation Dialogue
27
Scientific Inquiry and Truth
  • According to the traditional view the conclusion
    of an inquiry has to be drawn by the deductive
    chain of reasoning from a set of premises that
    are absolutely certain.
  • Any scientific inquiry might lead to a conclusion
    which might need to be revised in the future
    (Peirce, 1931, 2.75). Popper called this
    falsifiability.
  • Peirce wrote that many things are substantially
    certain (Peirce 1931, 1.152), but that this is
    different from the kind of absolute certainty
    that implies truth.
  • On his view truth is an important motivation for
    scientists to have as the ultimate goal of
    scientific research, but he argued that that
    truth can only be arrived at beyond all doubt by
    an inquiry that would take an infinite amount of
    time.

28
Fallibilism of Peirce and Popper
  • On their view, knowledge does not imply truth. In
    other words, it is not a requirement for
    proposition to be part of knowledge that it be
    true, at least in any sense requiring that it
    will not turn out to be false in the future.
  • On this view, called fallibilism, scientific
    knowledge is defeasible, meaning that even though
    a proposition is accepted as knowledge, it might
    be defeated in the future by enough evidence
    casting doubt on it, or even showing that it is
    false, so that it needs to be retracted.

29
Defeasible Knowledge
  • Peirce described the process of inquiry as one in
    which different participants set out with
    conflicting views, but are led through a process
    of marshalling and testing evidence to accepting
    the same conclusion. This convergence takes place
    as a successful inquiry moves to completion.
  • According to (Walton, 2010) Peircean belief is
    characterized as a settled state we do not wish
    to change. Once fixed, it is something we cling
    tenaciously to. It is an indication of a habit,
    and a matter of degree.
  • It puts us into a condition so we act in a
    certain way in the future, and it guides our
    desires and shapes our actions.
  • On this view, defeasible knowledge is a species
    of belief that is fixed firmly by a scientific
    discipline through process of inquiry that tests
    the belief as a hypothesis against all the pro
    and contra evidence that can be collected and is
    relevant to proving or disproving it.

30
Proof Standards
  • The following four standards of proof are used in
    the Carneades Argumentation System (Gordon and
    Walton, 2009).
  • Scintilla of Evidence (SE) is met if there is at
    least one applicable argument for a claim.
  • Preponderance of the Evidence (PE) is met if SE
    is satisfied and the maximum weight assigned to
    an applicable pro argument (for the claim) is
    greater than the maximum weight of an applicable
    con argument (against the claim).
  • Clear and Convincing Evidence (CCE), is met if PE
    is satisfied, the maximum weight of applicable
    pro arguments exceeds some threshold a, and the
    difference between the maximum weight of the
    applicable pro arguments and the maximum weight
    of the applicable con arguments exceeds some
    threshold ß.
  • Beyond Reasonable Doubt (BRD) is met if CCE is
    satisfied and the maximum weight of the
    applicable con arguments is less than some
    threshold ?.

31
The Mosquitoes Example
  • The collection of knowledge phase will only be
    reached at some point after ten years. At this
    point there will have to be deliberations that
    many organizations will take part in, including
    the World Health Organization, which will need to
    develop rules for testing genetically modified
    mosquitoes.
  • However, even at this point, it is possible to
    see how the argumentation structure of the
    deliberation in this case takes a pro and contra
    argument form based on argumentation schemes.

32
Carneades Map of Mosquitoes Argumentation
33
Evaluation of Mosquitoes Case
  • This method of moving forward with an evaluating
    deliberation requires taking fully into account
    evidence obtained from scientific inquiry into
    the circumstances of the case.
  • On this model, the factual basis of evidence from
    the scientific inquiry is part of what is
    required to assess the depth of assessment of the
    proposals made in the deliberation dialogue.
  • The dialogue should only be closed when this
    depth of assessment by argumentation has met the
    standard of evidence set for this deliberation
    dialogue.
  • At some point the cost in lives due to malaria
    will require that the decision be made one way or
    the other, provided that the alternative of doing
    nothing continues to result in highly significant
    loss of human lives.

34
Conclusion
  • The paper has shown how a rational decision on
    what to do depends on an evaluation of the pro
    and contra arguments for each proposal, once all
    the proposals have been stated.
  • It has also shown that this decision depends on
    how well informed these proposals are, based on
    the scientific and factual evidence concerning
    the circumstances of the case.
  • To provide a method for making these decisions,
    the paper has utilized formal dialectical models
    of deliberation dialogue and inquiry dialogue,
    showing how the latter type of dialogue is
    embedded in the former.

35
3 Problems for Further Research
  • The first is to devise computational
    argumentation tools to measure the depth of
    argumentation behind a proposal that has been
    discussed in a deliberation dialogue by the
    closing stage.
  • The second is to show how knowledge is
    transferred from inquiry dialogue to deliberation
    dialogue, typically using the argumentation
    scheme for argument from expert opinion.
  • The third is to apply the methods of this paper
    to a more detailed example of deliberation using
    knowledge obtained from scientific inquiry.

36
References
  • Aquinas, T. (1970), Summa Theologiae, vol. 17.
    Trans. Thomas Gilby, Blackfriars Edition, New
    York, McGraw-Hill.
  • Atkinson, K., Bench-Capon, T. and McBurney, P.
    (2006). Computational Representation of Practical
    Argument, Synthese, 152, 157-206.
  • Bench-Capon, T. (2003). Persuasion in Practical
    Argument Using Value-basedArgumentation
    Frameworks, Journal of Logic and Computation, 13,
    429-448.
  • Cooke, E. (2006). Peirces Pragmatic Theory of
    Inquiry Fallibilism and Indeterminacy. London
    Continuum.
  • Gordon, T. F. (2010). The Carneades Argumentation
    Support System, Dialectics, Dialogue and
    Argumentation, ed. C. Reed and C. W. Tindale,
    London College Publications.
  • Gordon, T. F. and Walton, D. (2009). Proof
    Burdens and Standards. Argumentation and
    Artificial Intelligence, ed. I. Rahwan and G.
    Simari. Berlin Springer, 239-260.
  • Gordon, T. F., Prakken, H. and Walton, D. (2007).
    The Carneades Model of Argument and Burden of
    Proof, Artificial Intelligence, 171, 875-896.
  • Hitchcock, D. McBurney, P. and Parsons, S.
    (2007). The Eightfold Way of Deliberation
    Dialogue, International Journal of Intelligent
    Systems, 22(1), 9513.
  • Peirce, C. S. (1984), Writings of Charles S.
    Peirce A Chronological Edition, vol. 2. Ed. E.
    C. Moore. Bloomington Indiana University Press.
  • Popper, K. (1972). Objective Knowledge An
    Evolutionary Approach. Oxford Oxford University
    Press, 1972.
  • Prakken, H. (2005). Coherence and Flexibility in
    Dialogue Games for Argumentation. Journal of
    Logic and Computation 15, 1009-1040.
  • Reiter, R. (1980). A Logic for Default Reasoning,
    Artificial Intelligence, 13, 81-132.
  • Reiter, R. (1987). Nonmonotonic Reasoning. Annual
    Review of Computer Science 2 147-186.
  • Walton, D. (2010). A Dialogue Model of Belief,
    Argument and Computation, 1, 23-46.
  • Walton, D. (2007). Dialog Theory for Critical
    Argumentation. Amsterdam Benjamins.
  • Walton, D. and Krabbe, E. C. W. (1995).
    Commitment in Dialogue Basic Concepts of
    Interpersonal Reasoning. Albany State University
    of New York Press.
  • Walton, D. and Gordon, T. F. (2005). Critical
    Questions in Computational Models of Legal
    Argument, Argumentation in Artificial
    Intelligence and Law, IAAIL Workshop Series, ed.
    Dunne, P. E. and T. Bench-Capon, Nijmegen, Wolf
    Legal Publishers, 103-111.
  • Walton, D., Reed, C. and Macagno, F. (2008).
    Argumentation Schemes. Cambridge Cambridge
    University Press.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com