MPhil Seminar: Evaluating OT - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 32
About This Presentation
Title:

MPhil Seminar: Evaluating OT

Description:

Evidence for extraction of generalizations from the lexicon ... ROTB and Lexicon Optimization ' ... Lexicon Optimization (Inkelas 1994, based on P&S 1993/2002:209) ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:92
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 33
Provided by: bert61
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: MPhil Seminar: Evaluating OT


1
MPhil Seminar Evaluating OT
  • Constraint

2
Overview
  • Two attacks on constraints
  • OTROTB-LO no constraints on URs
  • Reiss, NoBanana no surface (or other)
    constraints
  • Basic problem
  • Can one extract generalizations from surface
    (especially static/non-alternating) patterns?
  • Evidence for extraction of generalizations from
    the lexicon
  • Best-known case goed stage of L1 acquisition
  • Also Ohala, Pierrehumbert, Hayes, etc. on
    statistical knowledge
  • Marcus et al. 1999, Guasti 2002, Kuhl 2004 on
    child language infants are able to perform
    statistical analysis over pre-lexical
    representations, e.g. compute distributional
    regularities and find the most frequent word
    shapes.
  • Claims
  • Humans form phonological generalizations over
    their lexicons, often best modelled as MSCs or
    surface constraints
  • Often statistical in origin, but may be
    deterministic
  • OTROTB-LO wrongly predicts this to be impossible
    and creates other problems

3
Where are linguistic generalizations captured?
lexicon/underlying representation
Hale and Reiss only here (no constraints)
MSCs
OT
rules
DP
transformations
(GEN no generalizations) constraints on GEN?
constraints
Control constraints (? ineffability, Tonkawa
CCC...)
surface representation
4
Morpheme Structure Constraints
  • Initially employed to capture static phonological
    generalizations about morpheme structure, as
    opposed to alternations being captured by rules
  • Root Harmony (Kiparsky 1968)
  • C0 V?atr C0 V?atr C0 (Akan and Wolof, K
    1994351)
  • Japanese all post-nasal obstruents must be
    voiced in native words
  • tombo dragonfly (tompo)
  • mi-te seeing vs. šin-de dying
  • Can be modeled as an OT output constraint NT
  • (though Ito, Mester, and Padgett 1995819 call it
    an MSC)

See Kenstowicz and Kisseberth 1979425-433,
Kenstowicz 1994351-3, 524-8 for discussion
5
Early arguments for MSCs
  • Halle 1959, 1962, Chomsky and Halle 1968, etc.
  • account for native speakers intuitions of what
    constitutes a well-formed word in their language

6
Esper 1925
  • Method
  • Ss learn names of 16 objects, each having one of
    four different shapes and one of four different
    colors
  • Ss trained on 14 object-name associations but
    tested on 16 to see if they generalize what they
    learned
  • 3 experimental conditions
  • names presented to Group 1
  • naslig, sownlig, nasdeg, sowndeg, where nas- and
    sown- coded color and -lig and -deg coded shape
  • Since these names consisted of two phonologically
    legal morphemes, this group could simplify their
    task by learning not 16 names but 8 morphemes (if
    they could discover them) plus the simple rule
    that the color morpheme preceded the shape
    morpheme in each name.
  • Names presented to Group 2
  • bi-morphemic names, as with Group 1
  • unlike group 1, the morphemes were not
    phonologically legal for English, e.g., nulgen,
    nuzgub, pelgen, pezgub (where nu- and pe- were
    color morphemes and -lgen and -zgub were shape
    morphemes, the latter two violating English
    morpheme structure constraints)
  • Names presented to Group 3 (a control group)
  • names with no morphemic structure
  • no recourse but to learn 16 idiosyncratic names
  • Results
  • As expected, group 1 learned their names much
    faster and more accurately than group 3.
  • Performance of Group 2 was similar to (and
    marginally worse than) that of group 3
  • Analysis of the errors of group 2, including how
    they generalized what theyd learned to the two
    object-name associations excluded from the
    training session, revealed that they tried to
    make phonologically legal morphemes from the
    ill-formed ones. 
  • Demonstrates (i) psychological reality of MSCs
    (ii) ability to conduct morphological analysis
  • Problems

7
Arguments against MSCs
  • Duplication Problem (Kisseberth 1970 et seqq.)
  • Japanese MSC NT for tompo and rule for šin-de
    vs. mi-te
  • there is good reason to doubt the basic
    assumptionthat the harmony found in roots and
    affixes is the product of two separate
    grammatical mechanisms a morpheme structure
    condition and a feature-changing ruleit implies
    the existence of i languages in which all the
    suffixes systematically harmonize to the root but
    the roots show no restrictions on vowel
    combinations or in which the opposite state of
    affairs holds (i.e. ii the root vowels
    harmonize but affixes fail to alternate). (K
    1994353)
  • this formal similarity and functional redundancy
    between MSCs and rules is a significant liability
    of the classic theory. If MSCs and rules really
    are distinct components of linguistic theory,
    then they should be cleanly differentiated in
    form and function, but they are not. (McCarthy
    1998)
  • This stance makes maximal use of theoretical
    resources already required, avoiding the loss of
    generalization entailed by adding further
    language-particular apparatus devoted to input
    selection. (In this we pursue ideas implicit in
    Stampe 1969, 1973/79, and deal with Kisseberths
    grammar/lexicon duplication problem by having
    no duplication.) (P and S 1993/2002209)
  • Wellformedness judgements
  • MSCs predict that speakers can only make ternary
    distinctions in well-formedness, whereas speakers
    in fact make scalar judgements (Greenberg and
    Jenkins 1964, Ohala Ohala 1986242 see
    Pierrehumbert 2003 for literature review).

(i) ? Turkish (Kaun and Harrison 1999)
(ii) ? Marash (Vaux 1998)
8
Faulty conception of MSCs I
  • Kie Zuraw presents typical OT misconception that
    MSCs are required to capture any surface-true
    generalization
  • http//www.linguistics.ucla.edu/people/zuraw/200A_
    2004/11SurfaceConstraints.pdf
  • Zuraws take on DP analysis of these data
  • MSC for green etc.
  • rule for old man etc.
  • She sees this as Duplication Problem (!)
  • Actual DP analysis (assuming new loans are
    exempt)
  • Single rule for both green and old man etc.
  • Not subject to DEC

9
Faulty conception of MSCs II
  • McCarthy 1998
  • According to the premises of classic generative
    phonology, final devoicing in L is a result of a
    phonological rule. In L, though, devoicing is
    attributed to a morpheme structure constraint
    (MSC), the name given to restrictions on
    underlying representations.
  • BV in the absence of evidence from loanwords,
    language games, etc. showing that the lack of
    final D in URs is the product of an active MSC
    (which McCarthy doesnt provide), such cases
    actually involve Stampean Occultation
  • Suppose some rule consistently replaces the
    structure /A/ by B. Finding no surface As,
    language learners will not be tempted to set up
    underlying /A/s in the lexicon, positing only
    underlying /B/s instead. In this way, /B/ hides
    or occults /A/, obtaining the same descriptive
    effect as an anti-/A/ MSC without invoking any
    actual restrictions on the lexicon. McCarthy
    19981
  • Here
  • A voiced stop
  • B voiceless stop

10
Faulty conception of MSCs III
  • Under the thesis of richness of the base, OT
    does not countenance morpheme structure
    constraints. This paper shows that some phenomena
    that have been attributed to morpheme structure
    constraints can be analyzed with constraints that
    forbid alternations within paradigms.

Given what Ive already proposed, how do you
think we should deal with Dialect B?
11
ROTB and Lexicon Optimization
  • OT attributes linguistic generalizations to the
    grammar, not the lexicon...this thesis is called
    richness of the base inputs are unrestricted,
    but the grammar is responsible for mapping all
    inputs onto pronounceable forms of the language.
    (McCarthy 200353)
  • if the grammar yields an inventory with only
    unvoiced obstruents, no segments in lexical forms
    will contain voice without sonorant even
    though all feature combinations are universally
    available as inputs. (Smolensky 1996)
  • Lexicon Optimization (Inkelas 1994, based on PS
    1993/2002209)
  • Given a grammar G and a set S S1, S2, ... Si
    of surface phonetic forms for a morpheme M,
    suppose that there is a set of inputs I I1,
    I2, ... Ij, each of whose members has a set of
    surface realizations equivalent to S. There is
    some Ii ? I such that the mapping between Ii and
    the members of S is the most harmonic with
    respect to G, i.e. incurs the fewest marks for
    the highest ranked constraints. The learner
    should choose Ii as the underlying representation
    for M. (Inkelas 1994)

12
ROTB and Lexicon Optimization
  • Turkish final devoicing (to be discussed in more
    detail later)
  • v?th watt v?th? watt-accusative
  • th?th taste th?d? taste-accusative
  • One can force UR ? SR by having alternations in
    the paradigm (PS 1993/2002210, Inkelas 19947),
    but if there is no evidence for alternations
    (e.g. with a nonce word), ROTB-LO (wrongly)
    predicts UR SR.

LO cases
/v?th/ Voice ? ?Coda MaxF DepF
?v?th v?th?
v?th v?d? !
v?d v?d? !
guruph Voice ? ?Coda MaxF DepF
? /gruph/
/grub/ !
/th?d/ Voice ? ?Coda MaxF DepF
th?th th?th? !
?th?th th?d?
th?d th?d? !
thjub Voice ? ?Coda MaxF DepF
/thyph/ !
? /thyb/
13
Response to response to MSCs
  • The duplication argument, which is the heart of
    the attack on MSCs, only holds ceteris paribus,
    but in fact all else is not equal
  • ROTB-LO incorrectly predicts the nonexistence of
    productive lexical generalizations utilized by
    speakers in constructing underlying
    representations.
  • ROTB-LO incorrectly predicts (assuming universal
    markedness constraint hierarchies cf. Prince and
    Smolensky 1993, Steriade 199942, Lombardi 2003)
    the absence of languages containing the marked
    but not the unmarked member of a phonemic
    opposition
  • Cf. Russian has palatalized /cj/ but not plain
    /c/
  • ROTB-LO incorrectly predicts conformity of URs to
    surface phonotactics
  • ROTB-LO incorrectly requires full spec. in
    non-alternating cases
  • ROTB-LO requires stipulation that certain GEN
    alterations (e.g. syllabification) are invisible
    to Faith and Ident constraints

14
Deneutralization
  • Predictions for picking UR from ambiguous input
  • OTROTB-LO pick transparent UR
  • Hayes 1995 pick base form as UR whether or not
    there are alternations
  • Gallistel 2003 When animals and humans have to
    solve problems with incomplete knowledge, they
    use stochastic/probabilistic models
  • NB deterministic generalization may be spawned
    from statistical knowledge
  • In a language with 60 s and 40 t, s may be
    picked 60 or 100 of the time choice may be
    arbitrary with insufficiently skewed statistics,
    e.g. with pigeons
  • Type 1 (structure-preserving)
  • English final /r/
  • Several nonrhotic Englishes productively assign
    final /r/ to all low-vowel-final roots (Mohanan
    1985, Stampe 1991, Harris 1994)
  • English backformation wrt Velar Softening
    (Pierrehumbert 2002)
  • 2 subjects backformed e.g. hovacity ? hovak,
    33 and 75 of the time
  • Devoicing languages (German, Russian, Polish
    Turkish, Lac Simon, Dutch)
  • Korean word-final t ? /s/
  • Japanese ? ? /g/ (Ito, McCarthy)
  • Type 2 (non-structure-preserving)
  • English flapping
  • sporadic for some antidote for anecdote,
    calisthentics, etc.
  • systematic SNs flap ? /t/

15
Korean borrowing of Coda t
  • Korean word-final t ? /t, th, t, c, ch, c,
    s, s/
  • Surface word-final postvocalic t in loans and
    nonce words invariably assigned to /s/ (Martin
    1992, Kang 1998, Hayes 1998, Iverson Lee 2004)
  • supermarket ? nom. sup?makhet, dat.
    sup?makhese
  • OTROTB-LO wrongly predicts assignment to /t/
  • basic problem OTROTB-LO does not allow for
    statistical generalizing over the lexicon to play
    a role in the construction of URs
  • What appears to be involved in the Korean case is
    that speakers know that surface word-final ts
    most often come from underlying /s/ in their
    native lexicon, and they therefore assign new
    words to the same pattern.

16
Turkish final voice
source voiced UR hits voiceless UR hits
E tube tübü 147 tüpü 6330
E club kulübü 145,000 kulüpü 7
klübü 35,300 klüpü 4
E/F group(e) gurubu 18,000 gurupu 17 (0.1)
grubu 327,000 grupu 448 (0.1)
F principe prensibi 16,600 prensipi 76
NB these override voice specification in source
language
  • All polysyllabic forms that have a voiceless
    obstruent when final have a voiced one when
    suffixed (Lewis 196711)
  • The converse has now developed for monosyllables
    (Inkelas, Pycha, and Sprouse 2004)
  • TELL 19 monosylls with final voiced stop 145
    with voiceless current MSC plausibly extracted
    from this

17
Lac Simon Algonquian
  • underlying voicing contrast
  • rule of initial obstruent devoicing
  • all new stem-initial obstruents ? underlyingly
    voiced (Nykiel and Nykiel 1979, Kaye 1979,
    Iverson 1983).
  • French banane banan ? LSA panan banana,
    but n?banan?m my banana
  • English coffee ? LSA kofike he makes
    coffee, but nigofike I make coffee

segment UR SR w/ devoicing SR w/o devoicing
a. /g/ /gazot?m/ kazot?m he hides n?-gazot?m I hide
b. /k/ /kat/ n?-kat my leg
not n?-gat note that the same 1st person
prefix conditions the voiced allophone in (a)
NB the relevant frequency facts for Lac Simon are
not known.
18
Statistical knowledge
  • The basic problem
  • OTROTB-LO does not allow for generalizations
    extracted from statistical properties of the
    lexicon to play a role in the grammar
  • Counterevidence (cf. Skousen 1989)
  • Greenberg and Jenkins 1964, Ohala and Ohala 1986,
    Frisch, Large, and Pisoni 2000, Hay,
    Pierrehumbert, and Beckman 2004, etc. etc. on the
    well-formedness of English nonce words
  • Hayes 1995 on Turkish
  • Pierrehumbert 2002 on English velar softening
  • Polish speakers assign masculine gender to all
    consonant-final words and feminine gender to all
    a-final words (Baran 2000)
  • Statistical knowledge ? (categorical?) linguistic
    generalizations
  • All other things being equal, the cognitive
    system prefers generalizations which yield more
    information about the outcome over those which
    yield less. (Pierrehumbert 2002)
  • speakers extend morphological patterns based on
    abstract structural properties, of a kind
    appropriately described with rules (Albright and
    Hayes 2003)

19
More deterministic
  • German chooses -s as its productive plural,
    though it isnt most frequent (though frequency
    does affect its productivityBybee 1995)
  • Moreton 1999
  • English speakers aware of MSC banning final lax
    vowels
  • phonotactic knowledge consists of categorical,
    rule-like prohibitions, rather than emerging from
    statistical properties of the lexicon
  • Inkelas, Pycha, and Sprouse 2004 on Turkish voice
    alternations not conditioned by lexical
    neighborhood density or frequency
  • mono- vs. polysyllabicity is best predictor of
    (non-)alternation

20
Underlying ?-structure
  • CV-language learners will never insert into the
    lexicon any underlying forms that violate the
    (surface) syllable structure constraints of their
    language (PS 2002210)
  • Problem Turkish and other languages that do not
    postulate underlying epenthesis, even though
    doing so does not conform to their surface
    syllable canon
  • vakith time acc. vakth-i (lt Arabic wakt)
  • istop stop acc. istop-u
  • (not istob-u, the expected polysyllabic
    treatment)

21
ROTB-LO requires full specification in
non-alternating cases
  • OTROTB-LO requires that all non-alternating
    surface forms have fully specified lexical
    entries
  • Disproven by Kaun and Harrison 1999 with respect
    to root-internal harmony in Tuvan, Finnish, and
    Turkish
  • After application of relevant language games,
    harmonic roots re-harmonize but disharmonic roots
    dont
  • Cf. Krämer 2004 for German glottal stop insertion
    and English laxing
  • (He argues that LO actually cant decide between
    fully specified and underspecified form as UR,
    since identity constraints are stipulated to not
    penalize underspecified URs)

22
Stipulation
  • Incorporating ROTB into OT requires stipulating
    that GEN be able to alter inputs in ways that are
    invisible to faithfulness constraints (McCarthy
    200238) and Ident constraints (Krämer 2004).
  • McCarthy 200238 this is the only way to account
    for the universal non-contrastiveness of certain
    phonological distinctions
  • syllabification of tautomorphemic sequences is
    never contrastive, e.g. hab.la vs. ha.bla
  • A necessary condition for ensuring that
    syllabification is never contrastive is that
    syllabification is faithfulness-free, so an
    unsyllabified input like /maba/ or a syllabified
    input like /mab.a/ will be associated by GEN with
    all of the following fully faithful and fully
    syllabified candidates m.a.b.a, ma.b.a, m.a.ba,
    m.aba, m.ab.a, ma.ba, mab.a, maba. Many of these
    candidates are sure losers for markedness
    reasons, such as the absurd monosyllable maba.
    But they are still fully faithful in the sense
    that they incur no faithfulness violations.

23
ROTB doesnt follow from OT architecture
  • IO constraints allow reference to input forms
  • ? OT has the power to evaluate I constraints
    (constraints on inputs without reference to
    corresponding outputs)
  • in fact, these are less computationally complex
    than IO constraints
  • DsI no monosyllabic URs ending in
    voiced obstruent
  • NB I constraints dont do any work in IO
    mappings only involved in UR construction

thjub DsI Voice ? ?Coda MaxF DepF
? /thyph/
/thyb/ !
24
Summary of OTROTB-LO problems
  1. Incorrectly predicts the nonexistence of MSCs
  2. Incorrectly predicts the absence of languages
    containing the marked but not the unmarked member
    of a phonemic opposition
  3. Incorrectly predicts conformity of URs to surface
    phonotactics
  4. Incorrectly requires full specification in
    non-alternating cases
  5. Stipulates invisibility to Faith and Ident
    constraints

25
Solution
  • The problems presented here are resolved
    straightforwardly by assuming that humans can
    extract generalizations from the structure of
    their lexicon.
  • NB generalizations can be extracted in the
    absence of alternations (cf. Dell et al. 2000),
    e.g. from statistical knowledge
  • This move is consistent with what we know about
    human and primate cognition
  • Pierrehumbert 2002, 2003, etc. on statistical
    knowledge in phonology
  • Marcus et al. 1999, Guasti 2002, etc. on child
    language
  • Kirkham et al. 2002 on vision in infants
  • Ramus et al. 2000 and Hauser et al. 2002 on
    primates
  • Grounded in the fundamental linguistic tenet that
    extracting generalizations is the heart of
    grammar construction.

26
Surface constraints
  • Dell et al. and Goldrick 2004 on speech errors
    (as we saw in the speech errors lecture)
  • NB implies that humans can learn constraints on
    representations in the absence of alternations
    (cf. English learning of h and engma distribution)

27
Identity constraints and ineffability (Control
constraints)
  • schm reduplication
  • Q19 Schmuck
  • Ø (70), shluck (8), schnuck (5), schmuck (4),
    fluck (3), shpuck (1), fuck, smuck, shfuck,
    shvuck, schmluck, shnook
  • Q20 Schmooze
  • Ø (59), shnooze (10), shmooze (4), flooze (4),
    shpooze (4), shlooze (3), shm?mooze, commooze,
    shplooze, mooze, wooze
  • Q22 Schmidt
  • Ø (66), shlidt (4), shpidt (4), shmidt (3),
    shnidt (3), flidt (2), vlidt, smidt, midt
  • morpheme sequencing
  • lightninging
  • German Berlin-er person from Berlin vs.
    Münster-aner (Münster-er)
  • Lenin-akan-yan vs. Lenin-akan-akan

28
Conclusions
  • Humans can and do extract constraints (both
    surface and underlying) from phonological and
    morphological data (both alternating and static)
  • Important component of animal cognition cf.
    conditioning studies
  • NB at least some constraints are inviolable
  • Theories attacking such constraints (especially
    OT) misunderstand use of MSCs and ignore much of
    the relevant data.

29
References I
  • Booij, Geert. 1999. Morpheme structure
    constraints and the phonotactics of Dutch. In
    Harry van der Hulst Nancy Ritter (eds.) The
    Syllable. Views and Facts. Berlin/New York
    Mouton de Gruyter, 53-68.
  • Christdas, P. 1986. Morpheme Structure
    Constraints and Underspecification. Paper
    presented at the annual meeting of the Linguistic
    Society of America, New York, NY.
  • Dell, Gary, K. Reed, D. Adams, and A. Mejer.
    2000. Speech errors, phonotactic constraints, and
    implicit learning a study of the role of
    experience in language production. Journal of
    Experimental Psychology (LMC) 26.61355-1367.
  • Dinnsen, Daniel and Laura McGarrity. 2004. On the
    nature of alternations in phonological
    acquisition. Studies in Phonetics, Phonology,
    Morphology 1123-42.
  • Esper, Erwin. 1925. A technique for the
    experimental investigation of associative
    interference in artificial linguistic material.
    Language Monographs, no. 1.
  • Goldrick, Matthew. 2004. Phonological features
    and phonotactic constraints in speech production.
    Journal of Memory Language 51.4586.
  • Greenberg and Jenkins 1964. they derive
    well-formedness judgements from comparison to
    forms in the lexicon, not MSCs
  • Halle, Morris. 1959. The Sound Pattern of
    Russian. The Hague Mouton.
  • Hauser, Marc, Daniel Weiss, and Gary Marcus.
    2002. Rule learning by cotton-top tamarins.
    Cognition 86B15-22.
  • Hayes, Bruce. 1998. On the Richness of Paradigms,
    and the Insufficiency of Underlying
    Representations in Accounting for them. Lecture
    presented at Stanford University.
    http//www.linguistics.ucla.edu/people/hayes/talks
    /RichnessOfParadigms.pdf
  • Inkelas, Sharon. 1994. The Consequences of
    Optimization for Underspecification. In NELS 25.
    287-302.
  • Itô, Junko, and Armin Mester. 1999. On the
    Sources of Opacity in German. Coda Processes in
    German. Manuscript, UCSC and responded to in van
    Oostendorp paper
  • Iverson, Greg. 1983. Voice Alternations in Lac
    Simon Algonquin. Journal of Linguistics
    19161-164.
  • Iverson, Greg. 2004. Deriving the Derived
    Environment Constraint in Non-Derivational
    Phonology. Studies in Phonetics, Phonology and
    Morphology 111-23.
  • Katamba, Francis and Larry Hyman. 1991. Nasality
    and morpheme structure constraints in Luganda.
    Africanistische Arbeitspapiere 25. 175-211.
  • Kaun, Abigail. 1998. Input constraints in Tamil.
    Paper presented at CLS 34, April 17, 1998.
  • Kaun, Abigail and David Harrison. 1999.
    Pattern-Responsive underspecification. In
    Proceedings of the 30th Conference of the North
    Eastern Linguistics Society.
  • Kawasaki, H. 1982. An acoustical basis for
    universal constraints on sound sequences.
    Doctoral dissertation, University of California,
    Berkeley.
  • Kaye, Jonathan. 1979. On the alleged correlation
    of markedness and rule function. In D. Dinnsen
    (ed.) Current Approaches to Phonological Theory,
    pp. 272-280, Indiana University Press,
    Bloomington.

30
References II
  • McCarthy, John. 1998. Morpheme structure
    constraints and paradigm occultation. In M.
    Catherine Gruber, Derrick Higgins, Kenneth Olson
    and Tamra Wysocki (eds.) CLS 32, Part 2 The
    Panels. Chicago, IL Chicago Linguistic Society.
    123-150.
  • McCarthy, John. 2003. Comparative markedness
    short version. Theoretical Linguistics (to
    appear).
  • McCarthy, John. 2003. Richness of the Base and
    the determination of underlying representations.
    Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
  • Mester, Armin. 1992. Morpheme structure
    constraints. Topic article in International
    Encyclopedia of Linguistics, by W. Bright, Oxford
    University Press, Vol. 3, pp. 3-4.
  • Moreton, Elliott. 1999. Evidence for Phonotactic
    Grammar in Speech Perception. Proceedings of the
    14th Annual International Congress of Phonetic
    Sciences, San Francisco.
  • Napoli, Donna Jo and Jeff Wu. 2003. Morpheme
    structure constraints on two-handed signs in
    American Sign Language Notions of symmetry. Sign
    Language Linguistics 6.2123205.
  • Nykiel, J. and B. Nykiel. 1979. Loan words and
    abstract phonotactic constraints. Canadian
    Journal of Linguistics 2471-93.
  • Ohala, John, and Manjari Ohala. 1986. Testing
    hypotheses regarding the psychological
    manifestation of morpheme structure constraints.
    In J. J. Ohala, J. J. Jaeger (eds.),
    Experimental phonology, 239-52. San Diego
    Academic Press.
  • Paradis, Carole Jean Franois Prunet (1993). On
    the validity of morpheme structure constraints.
    In Carole Paradis Darlene LaCharit (1993).
    235-256.
  • Pierrehumbert, Janet. 2003. Probabilistic
    phonology discrimation and robustness. In R.
    Bod, J. Hay and S. Jannedy (eds.), 2002.
    Probability Theory in Linguistics. Cambridge MIT
    Press.
  • Port, Robert. 1981. Linguistic timing factors
    in combination. Journal of the Acoustical
    Society of America 69262-74.
  • Port, Robert and Penny Crawford. 1989.
    Incomplete neutralization and pragmatics in
    German. Journal of Phonetics 17257-82.
  • Ramus, Frank, Marc Hauser, Cory Miller, Dylan
    Morris, and Jacques Mehler. 2000. Language
    discrimination by human newborns and by
    cotton-top tamarin monkeys. Science 288349-51.
  • Redford, Michael. 2000. The question of Inputs in
    OT A constraint-based, computational model of
    English meter. Manuscript, Leiden University.
  • Reiss, Charles. 2000. Optimality Theory from a
    Cognitive Science Perspective. The Linguistic
    Review.
  • Saffran, Jenny, Richard Aslin, and Elissa
    Newport. 1996. Statistical learning by
    8-month-old infants. Science 2741926-28.
  • Scobbie, J., John Coleman, and S. Bird. 1996. Key
    Aspects of Declarative Phonology.
  • Skousen, Royal. 1989. Analogical modeling of
    language. Dordrecht Kluwer.
  • Smolensky, Paul. 1996. The Initial State and
    Richness of the Base in Optimality Theory.
    Technical Report, JHU CogSci 96 4.

31
Ambiguity and animal wug tests
Gallistel, C. 2003. Conditioning from an
information processing perspective. Behavioural
Processes 61.31234 1-13.
32
(No Transcript)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com