Title: Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory
1Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Theory
- There are heritable variations in traits (i.e.,
either a physical characteristic such as brain
size, height or a psychological characteristic
such as sociability, selfishness, generosity,
aggresiveness and intelligence). - In particular environments some traits contribute
more to an individuals fitness (i.e., survival
and reproduction) than others. - As a result these traits are positively selected
and increase in frequency. In a word, they
become adaptations.
2Basic Assumptions of Evolutionary Psychology
- Human thought, feeling and action reflect
adaptations or traits that evolved over the past
5,000,000 years when the human line separated
from that of chimpanzees and bonobos, our closest
primate relatives. - Adaptations are modular (e.g., vision, language).
But to what extent? How distinct an entity
(e.g., lungs vs jealousy vs sociality)? - Sociality (i.e., group living), is a key human
adaptation. - The costs and benefits associated with our
peculiarly extensive and complex networks of
social relations are the primary source of
selection pressures on humans.
3Humans Compared to Chimpanzees and Bonobos
- What adaptations or traits distinguish humans
form their nearest primate relatives? What do
these adaptations imply about human social
psychology? - Large brains
- Long periods of juvenile dependence
- Extensive parental care including the transfer of
vast amounts of information - Multigenerational bilateral kin networks
4(And thats not all! Theres )
- Habitual bipedal locomotion
- Cryptic or concealed ovulation
- Menopause
- Culture, including language
- Letal competition among kin-based coaltions
- N.B. A few other species exhibit some of these
adaptations. However, only humans possess the
entire set of them in their most complex form.
5The Adaptive Value of a Trait Depends on Its
Contribution to Fitness
- The ultimate and most direct measure of fitness
is the number of healthy offspring or
reproductive success (RS). Thus, a traits
benefits refers to how much it increases RS and
its costs, how much it decreases RS. - We often use less direct or more proximal
measures of fitness that we assume contribute to
RS (e.g., as health, strength, wealth) for
convenience.
6Why Do We Think Group Living Is an Adaptation?
- Because it is universal.
- Because it is typical of species most closely
related by common descent to humans. - Because it has neurophysiological correlates
(e.g., neocortex ratio and social network
density ostracism and activation of pain area
in brain). - Because it has affective correlates (e.g.,
isolation and ostracism are painful and universal
punishments while being liked and respected are
pleasurable and universal rewards). - Beause it has cognitive correlates (e.g., Theory
of Mind cheater-detection modules). - Because bio-economic analyses of fitness (i.e.,
benefits to RS relative to it costs) suggests
living in groups is adaptive.
7Do species most closely related to humans
(chimps and bonobo) live in groups? Yes. Are
chimp groups and bonobo groups similar? No. So
what?
8Are there neurophysiological correlates of group
living? Yes. Neocortex size increases with
group size social complexity.
9Bio-economic Analysis
- In examining sociality as an adaptive strategy
Richard Alexander considers the recurrent
problems faced by groups in the ancestral
environment and compares the hypothetical fitness
costs and benefits of increasing group size
from living with several conspecifics (e.g., in
separate nuclear families), through a few dozen
(e.g., nuclear family coalitions or extended
families), one or two hunderd (hunter-gatherer
groups), to thousands or millions (towns, cities,
clans, tribes and nations).
10The cost/benefit return of increasing groups
size Minimizing home, den or nest site shortages
as an adaptive problem
11The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing disease as an adaptive problem
12The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages (when food is widely
distributed, thus, readily found) as an adaptive
problem
13The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages when food sites are few
and hard to find as an adaptive problem
14The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing food shortages when food is large,
hard to catch animals (prey) as an adaptive
problem
15The cost/benefit return of increasing group size
Minimizing the danger of predation
16- Protection from predation provides the largest
benefit to fitness from living in groups during
most of human evolution. - However, humans have achieve ecological dominance
so that weve not had to fear predation by other
species for the past 15-20,000 years. Even
before then, predation by other species was
minimized at a relatively small group size
compared to the size of human clans, tribes and
nations. - 3. So why do we live in such large groups?!
17If humans are not the prey of other species, do
they still suffer predation?
- Yes, of course! We are our own prey! Predation
by other human groups is likely to have been a
big adaptive problem for our species!! - (N.B. Our overlooking this suggest how the
ecological dominence of modern humans biases our
thinking about the ancestral environment?)
18- For many thousands of years the most
significant predator on group living humans has
been other group living humans. To explain how
this could cause humans live in very large
groups, Alexander proposed the balance of power
model
19The Balance of Power Model
- i. In multi-group environments, the members
felt vulnerability is inversely related to the
relative size of their group. - Felt vulnerability motivates smaller groups to
form coalitions whose size counter-balances or
excedes that of the previously largest group. - As a result, felt vulnerability decreases among
members of the newly formed coalition (and
increases among members of the previously largest
group). - This in turn motivates the latter also to seek
coalition partners which, if successful, motives
the former to seek further coalition partners
etc. Thus, group size spirals upward to some
limit where there is a balance of power that
minimizes feelings of vulnerability and
additional coalitions are too costly or
unavailable.
20Living inKin Groups is Easier to Explain Than
Living in Non-Kin Groups
- The protection function of groups implies
altruism Group members willingly incur large
costs to benefit others (e.g., some will risk
death to protect fellow members from an animal
predator or a raiding group). - Until the second half of the last century the
fact of altruism, was a puzzle. How could such
tendencies evolve if they cause harm to the actor
and should be selected against? In 1964 Hamilton
showed how in his analysis of inclusive fitness
(kin selection).
21A Heuristic for Thinking about Hamiltons Theory
- Imagine you are a gene that contributes to the
trait of intelligence. You know that - An individual is your vehicle carries you
through life. - Intelligence contributes to fitness (increases
RS). - The probability that copies of you exist in
relatives of your vehicle increases with their
degree of relatedness to your vehicle. - Then answer the following question
- What what strategy would you want your vehicle
to follow if your goal is insure that copies of
you continue to exist in future generations?
22Hamiltons Inequality Solves Two Related
Problems Why Living in Kin Groups is Adaptive
and How Altrusim Can be Positively Selected
23(No Transcript)
24(No Transcript)
25(No Transcript)
26(No Transcript)
27(No Transcript)
28(No Transcript)
29Risky Decisions Involving a Large Non-Kin Group,
a Small Non-Kin Group, or My Family
- The next study indicates that when making a risky
decision for a group, the size of the group and
our ties to its members can cause us to behave
seemily irrationally, i.e., compute costs and
benefits in sub-optimal fashion. - In what sense are such behaviors irrational?
- According to behavioral decision theory or
inclusive fitness theory or both? - Does this consider that adaptations are designed
for recurrent problems, not rare events.
30Framing of Choices in the Tversky and Kahneman
(1981) Decision Task
- The decision task
- Imagine that Lodz is preparing for the outbreak
of an unusual disease which is expected to kill
600 people. - Two alternative programs to combat the disease
have been proposed. - Assume that the exact scientific estimates of the
consequences of the programs are as follows
31Positive framing of the Decision Task
- The Certain outcome. If program A is adopted 200
people will be saved. - The Uncertain outcome. If program B is adopted,
there is a one-third probability that 600 people
will be save and a two-third probability that no
people will be saved.
32Negative framing of the Decision Task
- Certain outcome. If program C is adopted, 400
people will die. - Uncertain outcome. If program D is adopted,
there is a one-third probability that nobody will
die and a two-third probability that 600 people
will die.
33Tversky and Kahnemans results
- Under positive framing of the decision people are
risk averse - 72 of their respondents chose the certain
outcome. - 28 of them chose the uncertain or probabilistic
outcome.
34Tversky and Kahnemans results
- Under negative framing people are risk prone
- 22 chose the certain outcome.
- 78 chose the probabilistic or uncertain outcome.
35Peculiar Parameters of theTversky-Kahneman
Decision Task (Wang, 1996 2002)
- The Group is Large and Its Members Have No Ties
to the Respondent. - What Do You Think Would Happen If the Group is
Small and the Decision Makers Ties to the Group
Are Strong?
36Risk Proneness Decreases with Group Size and
Kinship
37Risk Aversion is Sensitive to Survival Rates for
Non-Kin Groups But Not for Kin Groups (Choices
are Positively Framed)
38Decisions about Kin Groups Violate Rational
Choice Preferences Under Positive Framing for
Probabilistic Outcomes When Its Expected Value is
Less than that of the Certain Outcome
Choice Percentage
Non-kin
Kin
Proportion of Group Saved for Certain
(Note In all conditions the probalistic outcome
is 1/3rd chance of saving all group members)
39Members of Kin Groups Are Nice to Each Other
But Not Under All Conditions
- Parental investment hypothesis (derived from
inclusive fitness theory) argues parents should
incur a cost to benefit a child when it
contributes to parents inclusive fitness more
than doing something else with their resources.
If so, what should be predicted (think of the
earlier heuristic) - 1. When parents decide on investing in a male
versus a female offspring? - 2. When parents are rich versus when they are
poor? - 3. When they are step-parents?
40Recall Hamiltons Inequality
- Note that it says under certain conditions
altruism toward kin may actually decrease
inclusive fitness. This happens when - r 0 and/or C gt r B
- As relatedness (r) between donor and recipient
decreases and the cost of altruism (C) increases
the donor should act in an increasingly
unaltruistic manner. The next slides summarizes
research (Wilson Daly, 1998) comparing the
likelihood of child abuse and child homocide,
decidedly unaltruistic acts, in families with two
biological parents and families with one
stepparent (typically the father). It
emphatically supports Hamiltons prediction.
41(No Transcript)
42(No Transcript)
43(No Transcript)
44 However a Violent Father or Brother Did Have
Benefits
- When a relative was murdered, Vikings had the
choice between a revenge murder or accepting
blood money. Berserkers were individuals with a
reputation of being extremely fierce and
dangerous. If a murderer was a berserker (or his
father or brother), the aggrieved relatives of
the victim were significantly more likely to
accept blood money, but to prefer a revenge
killing if the murderer was not a berserker or a
close relative. - In the next slide the plotted variable is the
ratio of observed murders relative to the number
expected on the basis of the proportion of
berserkers or non-berserkers in the population.
Source 34 murders recorded in Njal's Saga.
45(No Transcript)
46Viking berserkers suffered significantly higher
rates of mortality at the hands of their own
community but their behavior benefitted male
members of their families. Therefore,
Berserkers were altruists, yes? (Families of the
three berserkers in the Icelandic Njals Saga
suffered significantly less mortality than the 7
families that did not contain a recognized
berserker.)
120 100 80 60 40 20 01
47Something to Think About
- From the 8th through the 10th century, the
Vikings were the fiercest and most feared group
in Europe, raiding and plundering settlements on
the northern and western coasts of the continent
as well as the interior of eastern Europe. - A dozen centuries later their descendents are the
most peaceful and least feared group in Europe.
48- In light of Hamiltons theory, how could
cooperation among non-kin evolve?
49Non-kin Altruism, Cooperation and Equity Some
Questions for Later
-
- 1. Have the benefits of cooperation
sufficiently outweighed its costs (transaction
costs and opportunity costs) to create selection
pressures on human psychology? - 2. Can large cooperative networks (e.g.,
markets, trading networks) function without
cognitive adaptations that allow participants to
calculate the risks of a transaction? -
50- 3. Are there indirect benefits of non-kin
altruism (e.g., giving money to charity to poor
strangers)? - 4. Are costly acts with no return benefit
(e.g., altruistic punishment in a one-shot
prisoners dilemma game) more a matter of
satisfying a need for equity or fairness than
true altruism? Or a need for vegence? If so,
how would such motives be positively selected?
51Skinnerians and others of their ilk say
Altruism need not assume the operation of
cognitive adaptations like cheater-detection,
empathy or Theory of Mind
- A radical behaviorist demonstrates that helping a
stranger develops and is maintained because it
the act of helping is reinforced by its
consequences. - Hence assumptions about cognitve adaptations are
theoretically unnecessary, a violation of
scientific parsimony.
52- In the following experiment subjects are free to
press a button as quickly as they want to record
the end of a trial. In two conditions this also
turns off a noxious noise piped into a strangers
ears i on every trial (continuous
reinforcment), ii on some randomly selected
trials (partial reinforcement), or iii on none
of the trials (control), where the noise ends
automatically after a fixed interval. The desire
or effort to help is indicated by how quickly the
subject presses the button. - N.B. The stranger is a confederate of the
experimenter and there is no actual noise being
piped into his ears.
53(No Transcript)
54A Question to Ponder
- If humans do persist in helping strangers and if
they do so because the act is intrinsically
reinforcing, where does that leave theories that
assumes complex computations of costs and
benefits plus discounting (e.g., for age, health,
relatedness, etc.) are necessary for the
evolution of such behavior?
55THE STRUGGLE BETWEEN BEHAVIORISTS AND
COGNITIONISTS CONTINUES IS COOPERATION MINDLESS
OR DO YOU NEED COGNITIVE ADAPTATIONS?
- Sidowski Cooperation in essentially
coordinating interpersonal behavior and can be
achieved when individuals are totally unaware
they are interacting with another person. Just
assume the Law of Effect or Win-Stay,
Lose-Change and forget about complex
computations. - Kelly Not true. You need to think, to take the
others perspective and think about what they are
thinking to achieve cooperation. Let me show
you..
56The Sidowski-Kelley Coordination Game
57The results of applying the Win-Stay-Lose-Change
rule when both players, P and O, respond
simultaneously. Note that there are only three
combination of button-press choices possible on
the first trial and from then on the
Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule determines each
players outcomes
58The Three Starting Combinations
- a. P chooses the right button and O the left.
As a result both receive positive outcomes. - b. Both P and O choose the left button. As a
result P receives a positive outcome and O a
negative outcome. (N.B. The case in which both
choose the right button is isomorphic with this
one.) - c. P chooses the left button and O the right.
As a result both receive negative outcomes.
59Win-Stay, Lose-Change Wins An Ambiguous Triumph
for Radical Behavior Theory
60- According the Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule,
cooperation (mutual reward) is inevitable under
conditions of simultaneous responding which turns
out to be the case whether or not P believes O is
another person or a computer. - But see what happens when one simple parameter is
changed, i.e., P and O respond in alternation
rather than simultaneously. Suppose O responds
first and P second. The three starting trials
are as follows (continuing to apply the
Win-Stay-Lose-Change rule as before)
61Win-Stay Doesnt Win An Unambiguous Triumph for
Social Cognition
62- Unless they start out cooperating (a mutually
rewarding exchange), they should never achieve
cooperation according to the Win-Stay-Lose-Change
rule. - But they do achieve cooperation if P knows O is
another person (not, say, a computer). How is
this possible? Well, not by using Skinnerian
reinforcement theory which is inadequate to
explain this effect. We have to go elsewhere
for an explanation. Where? What assumption do
we need to make beyond those of reinforcement
theory to explain how cooperation is possible in
a mutual-fate-control sitution when we know our
outcome depends on another person, a stranger,
and his or her outcome on us?
63- New Assumptions TOM, Foresight and Planning
Cooperative Thinking - To achieve cooperation under these conditions we
foresee having to adjust our strategies and
actions with those of others so as to reconcile
potential conflicts of interests with maximum
benefit or least cost. To do so we represent in
our mind, as best we can,what others intend to do
(their plan or strategy), and what they think we
intend to do (our plan or strategy). - Why?
- In order to decide whether others are
trustworthy. - In order to anticipate and, thus, coordinate each
othersactions, thereby achieving a mutually
beneficial or least costly relationship (e.g.,
reciprocity or division of labor).
64- The most common experimental paradigms for
observing cooperative thinking is the two-person
prisoners dilemma game (PDG) and the n-person
prisoners dilemma game (SDG).
65 The Classic PDG
66The Social Dilemma Game (SDG)
- The SDG is an n-person (n gt 2) PDG. Say, as the
next Table assumes at least 5 out of a group of 7
members have to contribute their endowment a
sum of 5 given them at the beginning of the
experiment to fund a public good. The latter
means that all members will benefit by receiving
10 whether or not they incurred the cost of the
public good, i.e., whether they were a
contributor or a non-contributor. So like all
public goods, all members, contributor and
non-contributors benefit if the group meets the
cost criterion. Do you see why this creates a
conflict of interest similar to that in the PDG?
67- As in the PDG the largest benefit or payoff goes
to defectors (i.e., non-contributors) if there
are enough cooperators (i.e., contributors) to
provide the public good. - The next largest goes to the cooperators if
enough others cooperate to provide the public
good. - The next largest goes to defectors if there are
not enough cooperators to provide the public
good. - And least benefit, the suckers payoff goes to
cooperators when there are too few to provid the
public good.
68- Next we lay out the conditions that define the
standard SDG - It is a non-iterated (one-shot) game.
- Members are strangers.
- Their decisions are completely anonymous.
- There is no contact or discussion prior to,
during or after the decisions. They arrive and
leave the experiment never have seen any member
of their group.
69- Non-standard versions devised to compare with the
standard SDG - Money-back is a norm imposed on the group that
guarantees cooperators will get their money back
if there are two few of them to provide the
public good, ergo, no one gets a suckers payoff
and looses his endowment. - No free-riders is a norm imposed on the group
that guarantees defectors will not benefit more
than cooperators if the public good is provided,
ergo, there is no temptation to defect.
70The standard SDG and variations in Caporeal,
Dawes, Orbell and van de Kragt (1989)
Cooperation requires a minimum number of members
to contribute.
71- Some SDG studies also vary
- Whether or not individuals have a brief
discussion prior to deciding anonymously. - Whether or not the experimenter designated who
was to contribute (but they could still defect
because their decision is anonymous). - Whether or not everybody had to contribute
(called super simple because members did not
have to decide about cooperating but again anyone
could still defect since their decision is
anonymous).
72Rates of Public Goods Provision
73Rates of Contribution when External Authority
Designates the Anonymous Contributors
74Intergroup Cooperation Is Distrust of the Other
the Default for Outgroups (Even Minimal
Outgroups)?
75Reciprocity Knowing and Providing What is Due
Another Uncompelled Equity and Fairness
- 1. Will a person abide by a contract when it
is costly to do so and the person cannot be
punished for defecting? - 2. Will a person punish defectors when it is
costly to do so and it cannot force them to
cooperate? - 3. Will a person expect to receive punishment
as a result of defecting when punishment is
costly to adminsiter and it cannot benefit the
punisher (by compelling cooperation)? - If you say yes to any or all of these
propositions what does it imply about equity and
fairness as an adaptation?
76Employees Contracted and Delivered Effort in
One-Shot (non-repeated) Employer-Employee
Gain (see Gintis, et al., 2003)
Employees Average Effort
Payoff Offer to Employee by Employer
77The Mystery of Altruistic Punishment
- Cooperation can be maintain by punishing
free-riders. - Humans seem designed to punish non-cooperators in
that they do so even when it is costly and there
is no direct return benefit (e.g., in a one-shot
exchange). - If punishment of free-riding is costly and cannot
elicit return benefits from the free-rider, how
can it be postively selected and become an
adaptation? iveEven when it is costly to them and
they do not directly benefit as a result (e.g.,
in a one-shot game)?
78Contributions in a repeated public goods game
with the same partner or a new partner (stranger)
under conditions of punishment and non-punishment
(see Gintis, et al., 2003)
Punishment option Removed
Punishment Permitted
Average Contribution
Games
79- Milgrams study of obediance is the best known
study with data about what people expect someone
to do when punishing another person. At first
glance, the findings seem to argue against
assuming the tendency to punish free-riders is an
adaptation. - But does it? Is the person being punished
free-riding? If not, does the finding imply
anything about tendencies to punish in the
absence of free-riding? Let look at Milgrims
data.
80Punishing Members Who Refuse to Punish Deviants
May Be Unnecessary to Produce Conformity
Predictions that People (including Self) Will
Refuse to Punish Deviant Learner Are Wrong.
81(No Transcript)
82Cooperation and the Division of Labor
- The division of labor is probably the most common
form of cooperation in everyday life. - It is occurs when (i) members know, prefer to or
can do different things and (ii) coordinate their
respective knowledge or performances to their
mutual benefit. - The division of labor can be not only formal,
explicit and hierarchical (e.g., military units,
sports teams, surgical teams, business teams,
etc.) but also informal, implicit and egalitarian
(e.g., families, friends, co-workers and lovers).
83Cooperation Depends on Trust
- Contrary to Axelrod, simulation studies
demonstrate that his best game strategy,
TIT-FOR-TAT, really isnt. Actually, it counts
for little in respect to inclusive fitness
compared to the partner-selection strategy, i.e.,
being able to distinguish between trustworthy and
untrustworthy partners ahead of time. - If so, then humans, being so eminently
cooperative and cooperation being so vulneralbe
to cheating, must be designed to detect potential
cheaters somehow. You agree, of course? Well
okay, what do we know about such mechanism?
84 The DOG Partner Selection Algorithm
- The secret to DOGs success
- 1 Unlike the other partner selection
strategies, when it assesses the trustworthiness
of a potential partner DOG ignores transaction
costs it doesnt care whether a player
cooperated or defected in prior transactions. - ii Instead it focuses only on opportunity
costs it tries to select the player offering the
highest potential return and never selects a
player one offering a negative return regardless
of whether the player previously defected or
cooperated.
85- How does DOG work?
- 1. On the first trial DOG assigns a random
preference rank to all other players. - 2. From the second trial on, DOG assigns a
preference rank to all the other players
according to the following X-value rule - a. For any player DOG has ever played in the
past, the X-value is the score DOG earned in the
most recent transaction with that player (X can
vary from some positive value to some negative
value, i.e., it can reflect a large, moderate or
small positive or negative return from the
transaction). - b. In the case of a stranger, a player with
whom DOG has never played, X is the average of
the positive X-values of the players with whom
DOG has played in the past. - 3. On each trial DOG first selects the player
with the largest X-value. - 4. If that player doesnt select DOG as a
partner within three matching rounds, DOG selects
the player with the second largest X-value. - 5. This process continues until all the players
with positive X-values are exhausted at which
point DOG returns to the player with largest
X-value that is still available and repeats the
whole process, ad infinitum.
86Evidence for mechanism to assess the likelihood
of defecting, cheating, free-riding and
untrustworthiness
87(No Transcript)
88Abstract Rule Example
- Rule If you are in category X you have to be
taller than 6.0 feet. Is the rule being
violated? - Card P Someone who is in category X.
- Card not-P Someone who is in category Y.
- Card Q Someone who is 6.5 feet.
- Card not-Q Someone who is 5.5 feet.
89Social Norm Example
- Norm If you are drinking alcohol you have to be
21 or older. Is it being violated? - Card P Someone is drinking a beer.
- Card not-P Someone is drinking a coke.
- Card Q Someone is 23 years old.
- Card not-Q Someone is 17 years old.
90What Makes Us More Trustworthy?
- H.L. Menken (Its) the little voice inside
of you that says someone is watching. Which
implies concern about - 1. Being monitored.
- 2. Reputation.
- 3. Opportunity costs (i.e., other members
reject you as a partner in transactions involving
trust). - 4. Other kinds of punishment (e.g., make
him an offer he cant refuse ).
91Concern about being monitored can implicit and
automatic in transactions involving trust
Computer Monitor (Haley Fessler, 2005)
92Probability of Allocation Funds to an Agent to
Invest in the Trust Game
Effects of Eyes and Crowd-Noise on Allocation
N 24
N 24
N 29
N 22
N 25
(Haley Fessler, 2005)
93Cues to Trust and Distrust
- Aside from Cosmides cheater-detection mechanism
she demonstrated using the Wason Selection task,
are there other situational or internal cues
besides reputation, payoff structure (e.g.,
temptations to defect in PDG) and transparency of
return (e.g., rice versus rubber markets) that
are used to compute or infer trustworthiness? - 1. Self-resemblance Facial self-morphing
(conscious and unconscious effects). - 2. Facial prototypes Defector recognition
(specific features, e.g., eye shape?). - 3. How you feel (mood) Oxytocin inhalation.
- 4. Brain activity Anticipation of returns.
94Whom Do You Trust? Self Resemblance Studies
Using Facial Morphs
95Plt.08
Plt.01
Plt.001
NS
Plt.01
Experimental Control
Experiment 1
Experiment 2
Experiment 3
Experiment 4
96Effects of Qxytocin on Investor Transfers with
Human (Trust) and Programmed (Risk)
Trustee (Kosfeld, Heinrichs, Zak, Fischbacher,
Fehr, 2005)
97Neural Correlates of Reputation Building in
Trustee Brain (King-Casas, Tomlin, Anew, Camerer,
Quartz, Montague, 2005)
98Human Adaptations for Cheater Detection
Information Processing and Computation Under
Focused and Unfocused Distrust
- In many situations we know who may be tempted to
deceive us. Sometimes, however, we do not. - Focused distrust refers to occasions when we
suspect deception and know the source. - Unfocused distrust refers to occasions when we
suspect deception without being aware of its
source something just doesnt seem right. - Have we evolved to process information under
these two conditions differently compared to when
we trust others?
99Cheater-detection makes us think more
- If we elaborate on and analyze a lot what
suspected cheaters say, then we should confuse
what their actual statements with inferences we
made while encoding them. - Examples of types of inferences
- Direct inference Her boss says Mary works
quickly and doesnt make mistakes and we infer
Mary is an efficient worker. - Compound inference Her boss says Mary works
quickly etc., and we give a bonus to our most
efficient workers. We infer Mary won a bonus.
100(No Transcript)
101(No Transcript)
102Favorable
Neutral
Favorable ? Unfavorable
Unfavorable ? Favorable
Unfavorable
103(No Transcript)
104Suspicion Can Influence Judgment Unconsciously
- In recent experiments a few seconds before they
make a judgment, individuals are subliminally
primed with a word (e.g., an adjective or noun)
presented imbedded in a supraliminal honest or
dishonest face. - The word prime as well as the face is irrelevant
to the judgments they are about to make (e.g., Is
a second word, presented above threshold, an
adjective or a noun?).
105- The model tested in these experiments assumes
they will elaborate congruent associates to the
subliminal word prime in the honest-face context
and incongruent associates to the subliminal word
prime in the dishonest-face context. - If so, the model predicts that
- when the prime and the to-be judged word are
both nouns or both adjectives, then in the
honest-face context individuals will elaborate
congruent associates to the prime (e.g., the
concept of noun or specific nouns when both the
prime and the supraliminal word are nouns) and
categorization of the to-be-judged word is
facilitated (e.g., faster) whereas in the
dishonest-face context they elaborates
incongruent associates (e.g., the concept of
adjective or specific adjectives when both words
are nouns) and categorization is disrupted (e.g.,
slower). - by the same logic, when the to-be-judged word is
incongruent with the prime (e.g., one is a noun,
the other an adjective), judgments will be
disrupted (e.g., slower) in the honest-face
context and facilitated in the dishonest-face
context.
106(No Transcript)
107(No Transcript)
108(No Transcript)
109(No Transcript)
110(No Transcript)
111Being able to efficiently process information
about our relations with others (e.g., Is he or
she a friend or foe? Is his or her status higher
or lower than mine?) is useful. Is there
evidence that humans are designed to make and
store such computations?
112Adaptations Mechanisms for Coding Social
Relations
- If humans are designed to live in groups, then
they are also likely to be designed to code
(i.e., recognize, interpret, remember and
elaborate upon) information that reduces the
costs of group living and increase its benefits. - Among the most adaptive pieces of information
concern relations among group members - Who in the group have common interests, are
friends, who have conflicting interests, are
enemies? - Who is has high status (i.e., is powerful, rich,
skillful, etc.), who has low status (i.e., is
weak, poor, inept, etc.)?
113(No Transcript)
114(No Transcript)
115(No Transcript)
116(No Transcript)
117(No Transcript)
118A Procedure for Assessing Cognitive
Categorization of Individuals Are They Perceived
as Belonging Together, Forming a Coalition or
Unit?
119Suppose You Wanted to Know If Observers Grouped
People Based on Common Interest or Opinion.
- Tell observers about some characteristic of the
people (e.g., sex, age, race, clothes, and what
they said that indicated whether they were pro
or con regarding an issue). - Next ask observers to recall if an individual
made a particular statement (e.g., whether he or
she said X). - Count how often the individual is confused with
another (e.g., observers say he or she made the
statement when it was actually made by another).
120- What was the reason for these confusions? Did
they occur most often if the two individuals were
the same sex, the same age, the same race, wore
the same t-shirt or had the same opinion (both
were either pro or con)? - Intra-category confusion are most frequent.
Therefore, if confusion occurred most often
between those with the same opinion (both were
pro or both con), then its evidence that
observers were categorizing or cognitively
grouping the individuals based on common opinions
or common interests. Kurzban calls this
coalitional thinking. In Heider, the
grouping would reflect a positive unit
relationship and, perhaps implicitly, a
positive sentiment relationship.
121(No Transcript)
122(No Transcript)
123Social Dominance Orientation Following Ethnic
Prime (Questions on Ashkenazi-Sephardi Relations)
or National Prime (Questions on
Israeli-Palestinian Relations)
124(No Transcript)
125Consensus and Conformity
- Intentional cooperation typically is a form of
collective action (e.g., several friends decide
to form a study group, a community decides to
subsidize medical care for the poor a
hunter-gatherer tribe decide to migrate a
country decides to go to war) based on consensus. - An effective consensus must prevent cheating and
free-riding. - This implies social psychological mechanisms to
minimize distrust and insure conformity. - i. Informational influence (e.g., Sherif)
- social comparison
- persuasive argumentation
- ii. Normative influence (e.g., Asch)
- extrinsic reward or punishment
126But first, the mystery of compliance and human
nature
- What conclusion do you draw about human nature
from the amazing (okay, amazing only to the
naïve) relationship between (i) predicted and
actual compliance and (ii) proximity of victim
to punisher and the amount of pain the latter
is willing to inflict on the former? - Is there other evidence (e.g., studies of
soldiers ordered to shoot someone)? - Implications for normative influence and
conformity and second order punishment?
127(No Transcript)
128(No Transcript)
129(No Transcript)
130(No Transcript)
131(No Transcript)
132The Benefits and Cost of Conformity
- You dont have to learn what to believe or how to
do something. Just imitate others actions and
conform to their beliefs. - Social comparison as an adaptive mechanism for
imitation and conformity. - But imitation and conformity may have opportunity
costs, i.e., you will not discover that there are
better ways of doing something or that there are
more valid views of the world. - Hence, humans may be designed to discount the
validity of others actions or beliefs to the
extent that these actions and beliefs are
themselves products of conformity (not
independently arrived at) and are not objectively
demonstrable. - Is this why conformity in Asch-like normative
influence settings doesnt increase when
unanimous majority becomes relatively large?
133Why Normative Influence Peaks at a Very Small
Unanimous Majority
- 1. Discounting mechanisms
- i. Majority has shared interests different
from that of deviant. - ii. Non-independence of majority members.
- 2. Futile search for independent evidence or
objective demonstration of the majority choice. - Search is typically done under time stress and at
the cost of cognitive inconsistency (i.e., the
majority seems incorrect) relative to the cost of
social rejection.
134Conformity to a Unanimous Blame-the-Mother-Not-th
e-Manufacturer Majority in a One Six Member
Group, Two Three Member Groups and Three Two
Member Groups
10K 9K 8K 7K 6K 5K 4K
Degree of Blame
135Conformity to a Unanimous Blame-the-Mother-Not-th
e-Manufacturer Majority in Groups and in
Non-Groups (Aggregates of Individuals) of
Identical Sizes
Degree of Blame
136(No Transcript)
137(No Transcript)
138- According to Mueller and Mazur (1997), we
automatically judge someons status or dominence
from his or her face (Mueller and Mazur, 1997). - The faces used by Mueller and Mazur are from a
yearbook published by West Point, the U.S.
Military Academy, that trains career army
officers. Some examples (Can you detect
differences in facial dominance?)
139(No Transcript)
140- See slides based on WHO data for male-female
differences in mortality as a function of status
competition.
141Mating
- What does sexual selection theory predict about
male-female difference in - 1. Preferred number of partners?
- 2. Probability of consenting to intercourse?
- 3. Preferred age difference in mate?
- 4. Importance of mates provisioning prospects?
- 5. Importance of mates attractiveness?
142(No Transcript)
143(No Transcript)
144(No Transcript)
145(No Transcript)
146(No Transcript)
147Male-Female Differences in Antecedents and
Consequences of Homicide Demographic Evidence
- How (if at all) might theories of sex differences
in mating strategies, especially their
implications regarding competition between and
within the sexes, explain the differences in the
following data sets?
148Risky Competition Age- and sex-specific homicide
rates in Canada, 1974-1983.
Female victims
Homicides per million persons per annum
Age (years)
Female offenders
Age (years)
149(No Transcript)
150Age- and Sex-specific Rates of Homicide in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
Male victims
Homicides per million persons per annum
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
Male offenders
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
151Age- and Sex-specific Rates of Homicide in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
Female victims
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Homicides per million persons per annum
Age (years)
Female offenders
0-4 10-14 20-24 30-34
40-44 50-54 60-64
70-74 80-84 85 5-9
15-19 25-29 35-39
45-49 55-59 65-69 75-79
Age (years)
152(No Transcript)
153Unemployment Rates Among Male Homicide Offenders,
Male victims, and the Male Population-at-Large in
Detroit, 1972. (From Wilson Daly, 1985)
154Proportions Unmarried Among Male Homicide
Offenders, Male victims, and the Male
Population-at-Large in Detroit, 1972. (From
Wilson Daly, 1985)
155Spousal Homicde Rates as a Function of the Age
Difference Between Wife and Husband. Canada,
1974-1983.
Wife older
Wife younger
156Motive Categories and the Number of Cases
(Victims) Within Each, for 588 Criminal Homicides
in the City of Philadelphia, 1948-1952. (From
Wolfgang, 1958)
157Two hundred Twelve Closed Social Conflict
homicides in Detroit, 1972, in Which Victim and
Offender Were Unrelated (Friends, Acquaintances
or Strangers), Classified by Conflict Typology
and by the Sexes of the Principals. (From
Wilson and Daly, 1985)
158Dispositions of Spousal Homicides in Various
Studies. (Data from Canada and Detroit are from
Daly Wilson, 1988 for Miami from Wilbanks,
1984 and for Houston from Lundsgaarde, 1977)
159The Probability of Suicide After Homicide, in
Relation to the Sexes of Killer and Victim, and
Their Relationship, Canada, 1974-1983
160Intergroup Relations
- 1. Realistic Group Conflict Theory (Sherif)
versus Social Categorization Theory (Tajfel)
Are they incompatible? - 2. The minimal intergroup situation Is
advantaging the ingroup (or disadvantaging
outgroups) the default reaction to social
categorization? Is strategy likely to have been
adaptive (positively selected for) in the
ancestral environment - 3. What about N-group (not merely one in-group
and one outgroup) environments and coalitions as
in the balance-of-power model? - 4. Group/category membership, the hierarchy of
groups/categories, and self-evaluation Are
there dimensions other than prestige or power for
ordering groups?