DGZ and Lewis on probabilities in deterministic theories - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 22
About This Presentation
Title:

DGZ and Lewis on probabilities in deterministic theories

Description:

So, for example, the Chicago cubs early exist from the playoffs was typical or appears so. ... of inevitability-at least among Cubs fans- that they will never ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:113
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 23
Provided by: philo154
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: DGZ and Lewis on probabilities in deterministic theories


1
DGZ and Lewis on probabilities in deterministic
theories
  • Barry Loewer
  • Rutgers

2
  • What we regard as the obvious choice of
    primitive ontology- the basic kinds of entities
    that are the building blocks of everything else
    (except, of course, the wave function)should by
    now be clear Particles, described by their
    positions in space, changing with timesome of
    which, owing to the dynamical laws governing
    their evolutions, perhaps combine to form the
    familiar objects of daily experience. (1992 p10 )

3
Creation Myth
  • God made the world by creating
  • 1. space-time
  • 2. the Bohmian dynamical laws (Schrödinger and
    the guidance equation)
  • 3. the initial wave function
  • 4. the initial particle positions
  • Every physical thing is composed of particles and
    every contingent physical fact supervenes on the
    actual and counterfactual motions of particles.

4
Probabilities?
  • But if this is all God does to create the world
    it is not clear that he has done enough or
    whether he has done the right thing to get
    quantum mechanics as it is used by physicists.
    Quantum mechanics is a probabilistic theory that
    makes claims about the probabilities of events
    e.g. that the probability that a certain particle
    will hit a screen in a particular region is such
    an such, that a spin measurement will result in
    such and such an outcome, and so on.
    Probabilities are an integral part of the kinds
    of phenomena typically taken to be quantum
    mechanical, e.g. the uncertainty principles and
    the violations of Bells inequalities.. These
    dont follow from the Bohmian dynamical laws
    alone.

5
Bohmian probabilities
  • Where do the probabilities in Bohmian mechanics
    come from? And what do they mean? In orthodox qm
    probabilities come in via the collapse postulate
    which- if understood realistically- is an
    indeterministic law that governs the evolution of
    the quantum state when measurements- whatever
    they are- are made. In GRW they also come in via
    an indeterministic law although without
    measurement figuring in the law. But in Bohmain
    mechanics the dynamical laws- Shroedingers and
    the guidance equation- are deterministic. In a
    deterministic theory it seems that there is
    only one place for probabilities to enter. as a
    distribution over the initial conditions of the
    universe.

6
Initial condition probabilities?
  • But what is the meaning of a probability
    distribution over the possible initial positions
    compatible with the initial wave function? There
    seem to be two answers 1 it is a subjective
    probability - perhaps one meeting certain
    rationality constraints- that represents
    ignorance of the initial positions of particles.
    2. it is an objective probability distribution
    over the initial positions of particles
    corresponding to some fact about the world..

7
  • DGZ argue that it makes no sense to construe the
    initial distribution as a probability. The reason
    is that there is only one universe. Evidently
    they have in mind frequency accounts of
    probability on which an event has a probability
    only relative to an ensemble of experiments or
    trials. The probability of e.g. heads on a coin
    flip is the frequency of heads on coin flips or
    perhaps the frequency in the infinite limit were
    the coin to be tossed infinitely many times.

8
DGZ approach
  • First off they drop talk of probability for talk
    of typicality. Even after having discussed this
    with Shelly I am not sure I understand their
    notion of typicality. But here is my take on it.
    Typical behavior is behavior that occurs almost
    all the time. But not any almost aways behavior
    is typical. For behavior to be typical laws have
    to be in some way responsible or partly
    responsible for the behavior occurring almost
    always. One can rely on typical behavior so it is
    rational to believe that behavior will be
    typical. So, for example, the Chicago cubs early
    exist from the playoffs was typical or appears
    so. There is a feeling of inevitability-at least
    among Cubs fans- that they will never win the
    world series- or if they do it will be a fluke.

9
Typical Bohmian Worlds
  • DGZ claim that a typical Bohmian world is one
    that behaves quantum mechanically.

10
Problem
  • There are as many (two to the alpha 0) initial
    conditions that lead to unQM worlds as there are
    that lead to QM worlds (world in which the QM
    frequencies are manifested).

11
DGZ reply
  • DGZ say instead that majority should be
    understood in terms of a measure of typicality.
    Specifically they suggest that ? squared be
    understood as measuring the typicality of
    possible initial particle positions compatible
    with the initial universal wave function. The
    idea is that the greater the value of this
    measure the more typical is the initial
    condition. The typicality of a proposition is
    then the sum of the typicality of the worlds at
    which it is true. A typical proposition has
    typicality 1 or very close to 1. DGZ prove

12
DGZ
  • In Bohmian mechanics, a property P is typical if
    it holds true for the overwhelming majority of
    histories Q(t) of a Bohmian universe. More
    precisely, suppose that ?t is the wave function
    of a universe governed by Bohmian mechanics a
    property P, which a solution Q(t) of the guiding
    equation for the entire universe can have or not
    have, is called typical if the set S0(P) of all
    initial configurations Q(0) leading to a history
    Q(t) with the property P has size very close to
    one, S0(P) ?0(q)2dq 1 - e , 0 e 1 , with
    size understood relative to the ?02
    distribution on the configuration space of the
    universe. For instance, think of P as the
    property that a particular sequence of
    experiments yields results that look random
    (accepted by a suitable statistical test),
    governed by the appropriate quantum distribution.
    One can show, using the law of large numbers,
    that P is a typical property.

13
  • With typicality measured relative to ? squared
    DGZ show that a certain property P of solutions
    Q(t) is typical. The property P is having a
    configuration such that, when subsystems of it
    merit effective wavefunctions, the actual
    subensembles have probability density of
    positions given by ?2. This pattern is
    precisely what needs to be the case for Borns
    rule to be appropriate. The claim that P is
    typical is another way of saying that a Law of
    Large Numbers result has been proven such that
    most (with respect to measure (6)) Bohmian
    histories Q(t) have property P. They have proved
    that- given a particular construal of most-
    most Bohmian universes are such that Borns rule
    works in them.

14
Two questions
  • 1. Why should anyone care about this account of
    most and its companion notion of typical? i.e.
    why should we believe that typical behavior will
    occur. Afterall a proposition can be typical but
    false and there are continummly many Bohmian
    worlds in which it false.
  • 2. What facts about the world make it the case
    that (given an answer to the first question) ?
    squared is the correct measure of typicality.

15
What makes a measure the correct typicality
measure
  • 1. Nothing objective about the world. Rather it
    is subjective matter what one finds typical.
  • 2. It is a matter of rationality what measures
    are typical.
  • 3. The typicality measure(s) supervene on the
    dynamical laws.
  • 4. The typicality measure(s) supervene on the
    dynamical laws and the initial condition (the
    initial wave function and intitial particle
    position) i.e. supervenes on the total physical
    history of the world and the laws..
  • 5. The typicality measure(s) is a fundamental law
    or principle over and above the laws and total
    history.

16
Neither 1, 2,5 are plausible
  • I dont think either 1 or 2 are tenable for the
    same reason that it isnt tenable to construe the
    worlds initial probability distribution as
    subjective or dictated by rationality principles
    like the principle of indifference. Which
    measures are typical will ultimately determine
    what behaviors are lawful- e.g. that the
    uncertainty relations are laws- and that isnt a
    matter of subjective belief or even rationality
    alone.
  • 5 doesnt have this problem but is quite
    unbelievable since it severs the connection
    between typicality and the laws and facts.

17
Another grounding for typicality measures
  • There is another line of thought that points to
    the claim that what is typical is a consequence
    of the dynamical laws. According to it we dont
    have to rely on ? squared to tell us what is
    typical. Many other measures every measure that
    is continuous with ? squared- delivers the same
    verdict concerning typicality of frequencies in
    infinite sequences of experiments.

18
  • Nevertheless there are infinitely many worlds
    satisfying the Bohmian dynamics that behave
    utterly unquanntum mechanical. It looks like more
    than the laws are required to ground the correct
    measure.

19
Lewis account of laws
  • . On Lewis account the laws that obtain in a
    world are specified by what he calls the Best
    Theory of that world. The Best Theory of a world
    is the true theory that Best combines simplicity,
    informativeness, (perhaps other scientific
    virtues e.g. comprehnsiveness). Lewis observes
    that simplicity and informativeness are typically
    at odds increase in informativeness may come at
    a cost in simplicity. But his idea is that our
    world may be such that there is a uniqe true
    theory that Best combines these two virtues so
    that increases in informativeness come only at a
    great cost in simplicity and increases in
    simplicity come only at a great cost in
    informativenss.

20
  • The idea is that probabilities assignment can be
    introduced into a theory so as to make a great
    gain in informativeness while keeping the theory
    fairly simple. For example, given a long sequence
    hhthhhtthtttththhtththhth.. a very informative
    description of the sequence will be very complex.
    A simple description will be quite
    uninformative. But it may be that the
    description sequence of outcomes of independent
    trials each with probability .5 for heads is both
    highly informative and also simple.

21
Lewis applied to Bohmian Mechanics
  • What God creates is the space time- perhaps a
    high dimensional space to accommodate the wave
    function- or perhaps he can get away with 31
    space time. He then distributes the particle
    positions and the values of the wave function (or
    whatever corresponds to the wave function that
    can be fit into 3-d) throughout all of space
    time. The laws then are given by the Best theory
    of this world. Of course, what laws there are
    will depend on the distribution. But it may be
    that the laws are a package of the two dynamical
    laws and the initial probability distribution ?
    squared. Note that on this account ? squared is
    not derived from the other laws- or dependent on
    a prior notion of typicality. And it is on an
    equal footing as far as lawfulness is concerned
    with the dynamical laws. This is why it can
    ground the lawfulness of the qm frequencies, the
    uncertainty relations, the impossibility of
    superluminal signaling and so on. It is not
    surprising that we have guessed that the initial
    probability distribution is the equivariant one.
    Its being equivariant makes it enormously simple.
    Any other distribution would be incredibly
    complicated wince it would change over time. Of
    course there is no guarantee that God created a
    world whose Best Theory is Bohmian Mechanics.

22
Comparisons
  • 1. DGZ the initial distribution or family of
    distributions measures typicality not probability
  • Lewis the initial distribution is a probability
    distribution but not probability understood in
    terms of frequencies.
  • 2. The DGZ account is not tied to any particular
    account of laws. But if laws are understood along
    Maudlins lines then it is not clear that the
    typical quantum mechanical frequencies should
    count as lawful since they are not consequences
    of the dynamical laws alone. They have the status
    of special science laws that depend on special
    intial conditions
  • Lewis The initial probability distribution has
    the same nomological status as the dynaical laws.
  • 3. DGZ prove that the frequencies obtained in
    measurement situations (and other quantum
    mechanical frequencies) are typical. This
    underlies the usual applications of Borns rule.
  • Lewis can take over DGZs argument but now as an
    argument directly for the probabilities of the
    outcomes of experiments and other events. There
    is no need to take a detour through typicality
    and frequencies.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com