The Moral Argument - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 15
About This Presentation
Title:

The Moral Argument

Description:

The Moral Argument – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:147
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 16
Provided by: Philip714
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: The Moral Argument


1
Phil/RS 335
  • The Moral Argument

2
Why be good?
  • Like the design argument, the moral argument for
    God's existence seems more directly rooted in our
    everyday experience than the more abstract
    considerations which generate the ontological and
    cosmological arguments.
  • In the case of the moral argument, the everyday
    experience in question is our concern for the
    moral dimensions of our lives.
  • A common claim of theists is that only God can
    properly justify moral beliefs and judgments.

3
C. S. Lewis, "The Moral Argument"
  • Famed Christian apologist, C. S. Lewis makes this
    sort of claim with a philosophical rigor rarely
    matched in advocates of this argument.
  • The question that animates Lewis's analysis is,
    "How can we understand the force of moral
    judgments?"
  • As our experience suggests, such judgments are
    not just expressions of taste or sentiment. If I
    assert that murder is wrong, I am not saying, and
    no one understands me to be saying, something
    like "I don't like pecan pie."

4
An Appeal to Standards
  • According to Lewis, the difference is to be
    explained by the fact that moral judgments make
    an appeal, implicit or explicit, to a standard
    independent of taste or personal preference.
  • This standard is objective, or at least
    fundamentally intersubjective.
  • Thus, despite the protestations of skeptics or
    relativists, Lewis insists that human beings are
    in fact committed to moral standards of behavior,
    standards which they regularly ignore and/or fall
    short of (137c2).

5
Implications?
  • For Lewis, this description of our moral lives
    has some important implications for our
    understanding of the world we live in.
  • Lewis sees humanity as suspended between two
    competing views of the universe.
  • On the one hand, the power and capacities of
    technology and science incline us toward
    materialist explanations of the world around us.
  • On the other hand, we seem naturally inclined
    towards a religious or mystical account of the
    whole.
  • Though this may seem like a peculiarly modern
    viewpoint, Lewis insists that we've always been
    suspended between these alternatives, and that
    there is no non-question-begging way out.

6
No Recourse?
  • One possible implication of this fact is that we
    are to forever remained suspended, caught in a
    fundamental and inescapable ambiguity.
  • Rejecting this possibility, Lewis seeks to
    identify a way out.
  • We have a resource that we have failed to
    consider our own experience, to which we have a
    privileged, 'insider,' access.
  • In a move that has old roots but into which Lewis
    tries to breathe new life, Lewis insists that our
    inner experience reveals to us the mark of the
    author of our existence.

7
What Mark?
  • The telltale mark revealed in our inner
    experience is just this apparently universal fact
    of our experience of the ground of morality and
    moral judgment in a moral law.
  • Though Lewis is very brief and vague here, the
    idea seems to be that the moral law is a kind of
    trace or sign of the divine in us, a sign which,
    he suggests, "we have to assume is more like a
    mind than it is like any thing else we know"
    (139c2).
  • On the assumption that the only other kind of
    thing is matter.

8
Mackie, "Critique of the Moral Argument"
  • Mackie's article does not directly respond to
    Lewis's.
  • Instead he summarizes the standard form of the
    argument, and then considers and rejects three
    different expressions of this form the versions
    offered by Newman and Kant and then a more
    general form (in which Lewis's version could be
    appropriately located).

9
The Standard Form
  • According to Mackie, the moral argument has two
    parts, which can be summarized as follows
  • Morality is a series of imperatives or commands
    which require an authoritative ground.
  • Morality requires grounding which exceeds any
    possible human authority, individual or social.
  • __________________________
  • Conclusion Morality is grounded in a
    supernatural authority.
  • The stringency of the requirement of morality
    requires a source of moral motivation sufficient
    to it.
  • Such motivation cannot be accounted for by
    reference to merely human incentives.
  • ___________________________
  • Conclusion The supernatural authority of
    morality must be a divine capable of wielding
    positive and negative incentives profound enough
    to motivate humans to satisfy morality's
    stringent requirements.

10
Cardinal Newman on the Conscience
  • John Henry Newman, a catholic cardinal and moral
    theologian, argues that our experience of a
    conscience which serves as a resource for making
    moral judgments and a spur to act in accordance
    with them, serves as the source and appropriate
    basis for belief in God, "a Supreme Governor, a
    Judge, holy, just, powerful, all-seeing,
    retributive" (141c2).
  • As Mackie summarizes his argument, if follows the
    basic form of the moral argument summarized
    above. It moves from a claim about the authority
    of conscience (1) to the ground of that authority
    in the divine (2) which must have the personal
    qualities summarized (3).

11
Does it work?
  • As Mackie goes on to argue, the argument, though
    formally valid, is open to criticism.
  • In particular, the second move, the insistence
    that the authority of the conscience must be
    grounded in the higher authority of the divine,
    does not seem self-evident or necessary.
  • If the conscience really is authoritative, than
    what it authorizes would seem to have moral force
    independently of any reference to the divine.
    Thus, if the first premise of the argument is
    true, than the second and third would seem to be
    false.
  • If, however, the conscience is not authoritative,
    and thus requires grounding, the resources for
    motivating the moral argument from conscience
    would seem to be lost.
  • Ultimately, in as much as we don't need God to
    account for the experience Newman refers to, it
    doesn't seem to justify the metaphysical
    complexity it assumes.

12
Kant and the Moral Argument
  • Though Kant criticizes both the ontological and
    cosmological arguments for the existence of God,
    he seems to offer a version of the moral argument
    in the second of his great works, The Critique of
    Practical Reason.
  • Kant's version is importantly different from
    Newman's in that Kant did not insist that the
    authority of morality requires God.
  • The force of the moral law is a rational, not
    divine force and is thus accessible through
    reason alone.

13
The Summum Bonum
  • What reason reveals, according to Kant, is that
    the proper end of morality is the highest good,
    the unity of virtue and happiness.
  • This is a unity which must be possible (if
    something is required of us, must be possible for
    us), but which neither reason nor experience
    suggests should be expected.
  • Moral reason thus requires us to recognize the
    possibility of the summum bonum in God, "as this
    is possible only on condition of the existence of
    Godit is morally necessary to assume the
    existence of God" (143c2).

14
What did Kant Mean?
  • As Mackie points out, it's not clear how Kant
    intended for us to understand it.
  • Kant is clear that the conclusion that God exists
    is not warranted by theoretical reason, and that
    this conclusion is only required from the
    "practical point of view."
  • One possibility is that Kant was saying that we
    should act "as if" there is a God, but it's not
    clear why this is required and it is clear that
    this is no argument for God's existence.
  • More fundamentally, Kant seems to beg the
    question when he insists that we assume the
    possibility of the summum bonum. Another option
    is that it is a moral ideal that is in principle
    unrealizable, though one that we should strive to
    achieve.

15
God and Moral Objectivity
  • The last version of the moral argument that
    Mackie considers focuses on the putative need for
    objectivity.
  • As we saw with Lewis, many theists have argued
    that the only way in which moral claims could be
    objective is if they were grounded in the divine.
  • Mackie's own take on these matters is a skeptical
    one. That is, he denies that moral claims are
    objective.
  • Here, he's less concerned to argue this than to
    argue that even if moral claims were objective,
    it would not be necessary to refer to God to
    explain that.
  • We recognize all sorts of reasons of objective
    inquiry that do not make any necessary reference
    to God. There's no reason to suppose that the
    situation is any different with morality.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com