Propositional Logic - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 55
About This Presentation
Title:

Propositional Logic

Description:

Propositional Logic – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:101
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 56
Provided by: thomo
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Propositional Logic


1
Propositional Logic
2
Grammatical Complexity
  • A natural language is complex. E.g.
  • The dog chased the cat.
  • The dog that ate the rat chased the cat.
  • The cherry blossoms in the spring sank.

3
Ambiguity
  • A natural language has ambiguity, e.g.
  • Theres a girl in the room with a telescope.
  • Which one of the figures the sentence intends to
    capture?
  • In short we need to define a syntax.

4
Syntax
5
Propositional Constants
  • Examples
  • raining
  • r32aining
  • rAiNiNg
  • rainingorsnowing
  • Non-Examples
  • 324567
  • raining.or.snowing

6
Compound Sentences
  • Negations
  • Øraining
  • Conjunctions
  • (rainingÙsnowing)
  • The arguments of a conjunction are called
    conjuncts.
  • Disjunctions
  • (rainingÚsnowing)
  • The arguments of a disjunction are called
    disjuncts.

7
Compound Sentences
  • Implications
  • (raining Þ cloudy)
  • The left argument of an implication is the
    antecedent.
  • The right argument of an implication is the
    consequent.
  • Reductions
  • (cloudy Ü raining)
  • The left argument of a reduction is the
    consequent.
  • The right argument of a reduction is the
    antecedent.
  • Equivalences
  • (cloudy Û raining)
  • Notice that the constituent sentences within any
    compound sentence can be either simple sentences
    or compound sentences or a mixture of two.

8
Parenthesis Removal
  • One disadvantage of our notation, as written, is
    that the parentheses tend to build up and need to
    be matched correctly. It would be nice if we
    could dispense with parentheses, e.g. simplifying
  • ((pÚq) Þ Ør) into
  • pÚq Þ Ør
  • Unfortunately, we cannot do without parentheses
    entirely, since then we would be unable to render
    certain sentences unambiguously.
  • For example, the sentence shown above could have
    resulted from dropping parentheses from either of
    the following sentences.
  • ((p Úq)Þ Ør )
  • (p Ú(q Þ Ør ))

9
Operator Precedence
  • The solution to this problem is the use of
    operator precedence. The following table gives a
    hierarchy of precedences for our operators.
  • The Ø operator has higher precedence than Ù, Ù
    has higher precedence than Ú,and Ú has higher
    precedence than Þ,
  • Ü, and Û.
  • Ø
  • Ù
  • Ú
  • ÜÛÞ

10
Parenthesis
  • Note that just because precedence allows us to
    delete parentheses in some cases, this doesnt
    mean that we can dispense with parentheses
    entirely.
  • E.g.
  • (p Þ q) Ú (sÞ r)
  • Here, we cannot remove the parenthesis

11
Semantics
12
Algebra and Logic
  • The semantics of logic is similar to the
    semantics of algebra.
  • Algebra is unconcerned with the real-world
    meaning of variables like x and y.
  • What is interesting is the relationship between
    the variables expressed in the equations we
    write and
  • algebraic methods are designed to respect these
    relationships, no matter what meanings or values
    are assigned to the constituent variables.
  • In a similar way, logic itself is unconcerned
    with what sentences say about the world being
    described.
  • What is interesting is the relationship between
    the truth of simple sentences and the truth of
    compound sentences within which the simple
    sentences are contained.
  • Also, logical reasoning methods are designed to
    work no matter what meanings or values are
    assigned to the logical variables used in
    sentences.

13
Interpretation
  • Although the values assigned to variables are not
    crucial in the sense just described, in talking
    about logic itself, it is sometimes useful to
    make these assignments explicit and to consider
    various assignments or all assignments and so
    forth. Such an assignment is called an
    interpretation.
  • A propositional logic interpretation (i) is an
    association between the propositional constants
    in a propositional language and the truth values
    T or F.
  • p ¾i T pi T
  • q ¾i F can be written also qi F
  • r ¾i T ri T

14
Operator Semantics
  • The notion of interpretation can be extended to
    all sentences by application of operator
    semantics.
  • Negation
  • f Øf
  • T F
  • F T
  • For example, if the interpretation of p is F,
    then the interpretation of Øp is T.
  • For example, if the interpretation of Øp is T,
    then the interpretation of ØØp is F.

15
Operator Semantics (continued)
  • Conjunction
  • f y f Ùy
  • T T T
  • T F F
  • F T F
  • F F F
  • Disjunction
  • f y f Úy
  • T T T
  • T F T
  • F T T
  • F F F

16
Operator Semantics (continued)
  • Implication
  • f y f Þy
  • T T T
  • T F F
  • F T T
  • F F T
  • Reduction
  • f y f Üy
  • T T T
  • T F T
  • F T F
  • F F T

17
Evaluation
  • We can easily determine for any given
    interpretation whether or not any sentence is
    true or false under that interpretation.
  • The technique is simple. We substitute true and
    false values for the propositional constants and
    replace complex expressions with the
    corresponding values, working from the inside
    out.
  • We say that an interpretation i satisfies a
    sentence if and only if it is true under that
    interpretation.
  • As an example, consider the interpretation i show
    below.
  • pi true
  • qi false
  • ri true
  • We can see that i satisfies (pÚq)Ù(ØqÚr).
  • (true Ú false) Ù (Øfalse Ú true)
  • true Ù(Øfalse Ú true)
  • true Ù(true Ú true)
  • true Ù true
  • true

18
Evaluation (continued)
  • Now consider interpretation j defined as follows.
  • pj true
  • qj true
  • rj false
  • In this case, j does not satisfy (pÚq)Ù(ØqÚr).
  • (true Ú true) Ù(Øtrue Ú false)
  • trueÙ (Øtrue Ú false)
  • true Ù( false Ú false)
  • trueÙ false
  • false
  • Using this technique, we can evaluate the truth
    of arbitrary sentences in our language.
  • The cost is proportional to the size of the
    sentence.

19
Reverse Evaluation
  • Reverse evaluation is the opposite of evaluation.
    We begin with one or more compound sentences and
    try to figure out which interpretations satisfy
    those sentences.
  • One way to do this is using a truth table for the
    language.
  • A truth table for a propositional language is a
    table showing all of the possible interpretations
    for the propositional constants in the language.
  • The interpretations i and j correspond to the
    third and seventh rows of this table,
    respectively.
  • Note that, for a propositional language with n
    logical constants, there are n columns in the
    truth tables 2n rows.

p q r T T T T T F T F T T F
F F T T F T F F F T F F F
20
Validity, Satisfiability, Unsatisfiability
  • A sentence is valid if and only if it is
    satisfied by every interpretation.
  • p Ú Øp is valid.
  • A sentence is satisfiable if and only if it is
    satisfied by at least one interpretation.
  • We have already seen several examples of
    satisfiable sentences.
  • A sentence is unsatisfiable if and only if it is
    not satisfied by any interpretation.
  • p Û Øp is unsatisfiable. No matter what
    interpretation we take, the sentence is always
    false.
  • In one sense, valid sentences and unsatisfiable
    sentences are useless. Valid sentences do not
    rule out any possible interpretations
    unsatisfiable sentences rule out all
    interpretations thus they say nothing about the
    world.
  • On the other hand, from a logical perspective,
    they are extremely useful in that, as we shall
    see, they serve as the basis for legal
    transformations that we can perform on other
    logical sentences.
  • Note that we can easily check the validity,
    satisfiability, or unsatisfiability of a sentence
    can easily by looking at the truth table for the
    propositional constants in the sentence.
  • In one sense, valid sentences and unsatisfiable
    sentences are useless.
  • Valid sentences do not rule out any possible
    interpretations
  • Unsatisfiable sentences rule out all
    interpretations thus they say nothing about the
    world.
  • On the other hand, they are very useful in that,
    they serve as the basis for legal transformations
    that we can perform on other logical sentences.
  • Note that we can easily check the validity,
    satisfiability, or unsatisfiability of a sentence
    by looking at the truth table for the
    propositional constants in the sentence.

21
Entailment
  • We would like to know, given some sentences,
    whether other sentences are or are not logical
    conclusions.
  • This relative property is known as logical
    entailment.
  • A set of sentences D logically entails a sentence
    j
  • D j
  • iff every interpretation that satisfies D also
    satisfies j.
  • E.g.
  • The sentence p logically entails the sentence (p
    Ú q).
  • Since a disjunction is true whenever one of its
    disjuncts is true, then (p Ú q) must be true
    whenever p is true.
  • On the other hand, the sentence p does not
    logically entail (p Ù q).
  • A conjunction is true if and only if both of its
    conjuncts are true, and q may be false.

22
Semantic Reasoning Methods
  • Several basic methods for determining whether a
    given set of premises propositionally entails a
    given conclusion.

23
Truth Table Method
  • One way of determining whether or not a set of
    premises logically entails a possible conclusion
    is to check the truth table for the logical
    constants of the language.
  • This is called the truth table method and can be
    formalized as follows.
  • Starting with a complete truth table for the
    propositional constants, iterate through all the
    premises of the problem, for each premise
    eliminating any row that does not satisfy the
    premise.
  • Do the same for the conclusion.
  • Finally, compare the two tables. If every row
    that remains in the premise table, i.e. is not
    eliminated, also remains in the conclusion table,
    i.e. is not eliminated, then the premises
    logically entail the conclusion.

24
Amys
Simple sentences Amy loves Pat. loves(amy,
pat) Since we dont have vars but only
constants, it the same as saying
lovesAmyPat. Amy loves Quincy. loves(amy,
quincy) Same as lovesAmyQuincy It is
Monday. ismonday
Premises If Amy loves Pat, Amy loves
Quincy. lovesAmyPat Þ lovesAmyQuincy If it
Monday, Amy loves Pat or Quincy. ismonday Þ
lovesAmyPat Ú lovesAmyQuincy Question If it
is Monday, does Amy love Quincy? I.e. is
ismonday ÞlovesAmyQuincy entailed by the premises?
25
Truth table for the premises
lovesAmyPat lovesAmyQuincy ismonday lovesAmyPat Þ lovesAmyQuincy ismonday Þ lovesAmyPat Ú lovesAmyQuincy
T T T T T
T T F T T
T F T F T
T F F F T
F T T T T
F T F T T
F F T T F
F F F T T
26
Crossing out non-sat interpretations
lovesAmyPat lovesAmyQuincy ismonday lovesAmyPat Þ lovesAmyQuincy ismonday Þ lovesAmyPat Ú lovesAmyQuincy
T T T T T
T T F T T
T F T F T
T F F F T
F T T T T
F T F T T
F F T T F
F F F T T
27
Truth table for the conclusion
lovesAmyPat lovesAmyQuincy ismonday ismonday Þ lovesAmyQuincy
T T T T
T T F T
T F T F
T F F T
F T T T
F T F T
F F T F
F F F T
28
Crossing out non-sat interpretations
lovesAmyPat lovesAmyQuincy ismonday ismonday Þ lovesAmyQuincy
T T T T
T T F T
T F T F
T F F T
F T T T
F T F T
F F T F
F F F T
29
Comparing tables
  • Finally, in order to make the determination of
    logical entailment, we compare the two rightmost
    tables and notice that every row remaining in the
    premise table also remains in the conclusion
    table.
  • In other words, the premises logically entail the
    conclusion.
  • The truth table method has the merit that it is
    easy to understand. It is a direct implementation
    of the definition of logical entailment.
  • In practice, it is awkward to manage two tables,
    especially since there are simpler approaches in
    which only one table needs to be manipulated.

30
Validity checking
  • One of these approaches is the validity checking
    method. It goes as follows.
  • To determine whether a set of sentences
  • j1,,jn
  • logically entails a sentence j, we form the
    sentence
  • (j1 Ù Ù jn Þ j)
  • and check that it is valid.
  • To see how this method works, consider the
    problem of Amy and Pat and Quincy once again. In
    this case, we write the tentative conclusion as
    shown below.
  • (lovesAmyPat Þ lovesAmyQuincy) Ù (ismonday Þ
    lovesAmyPat Ú lovesAmyQuincy) Þ (ismonday Þ
    lovesAmyQuincy)
  • We then form a truth table for our language with
    an added column for this sentence and check its
    satisfaction under each of the possible
    interpretations for our logical constants.

31
Unsatisfability Checking
  • The satisfiability checking method is another
    single table approach. It is almost exactly the
    same as the validity checking method, except that
    it works negatively instead of positively.
  • To determine whether a finite set of sentences
    j1,,jn logically entails a sentence j, we form
    the sentence
  • (j1 Ù Ù jn Ù Øj)
  • and check that it is unsatisfiable.
  • Both the validity checking method and the
    satisfiability checking method require about the
    same amount of work as the truth table method,
    but they have the merit of manipulating only one
    table.

32
A truth table
p q r p Þ q p Þ r p Þ r ? q (p Þ q) ? (p Þ r) Þ (p Þ r ? q) p Þ r ? q (p Þ q) ? (p Þ r) Þ (p Þ r ? q)
T T T T T T T T T
T T F T F T T F T
T F T F T T T F T
T F F F F F T F T
F T T T T T T T T
F T F T T T T T T
F F T T T T T T T
F F F T T T T T T
33
Proofs
34
Intro
  • Semantic methods for checking logical entailment
    have the merit of being conceptually simple they
    directly manipulate interpretations of sentences.
  • Unfortunately, the number of interpretations of a
    language grows exponentially with the number of
    logical constants.
  • When the number of logical constants in a
    propositional language is large, the number of
    interpretations may be impossible to manipulate.
  • Proof methods provide an alternative way of
    checking and communicating logical entailment
    that addresses this problem.
  • In many cases, it is possible to create a proof
    of a conclusion from a set of premises that is
    much smaller than the truth table for the
    language
  • moreover, it is often possible to find such
    proofs with less work than is necessary to check
    the entire truth table.

35
Schemata
  • An important component in the treatment of proofs
    is the notion of a schema. A schema is an
    expression satisfying the grammatical rules of
    our language except for the occurrence of
    metavariables in place of various subparts of the
    expression.
  • For example, the following expression is a
    pattern with metavariables j and y.
  • j Þ (y Þj)
  • An instance of a sentence schema is the
    expression obtained by substituting expressions
    for the metavariables.
  • For example, the following is an instance of the
    preceding schema.
  • p Þ(qÞ p)

36
Rules of Inference
  • The basis for proof methods is the use of correct
    rules of inference that can be applied directly
    to sentences to derive conclusions that are
    guaranteed to be correct under all
    interpretations.
  • Since the interpretations are not enumerated,
    time and space can often be saved.
  • A rule of inference is a pattern of reasoning
    consisting of
  • one set of sentence schemata, called premises,
    and
  • a second set of sentence schemata, called
    conclusions.
  • A rule of inference is sound if and only if, for
    every instance, the premises logically entail the
    conclusions.

37
E.g. Modus Ponens
  • j Þy
  • j
  • y
  • rainingÞ wet
  • raining
  • wet
  • wet Þ slippery
  • wet
  • slippery
  • p Þ(qÞ r)
  • p
  • q Þ r
  • (p Þ q)Þ r
  • p Þ q
  • r
  • I.e. we can substitute for the metavariables
    complex sentences
  • Note that, by stringing together applications of
    rules of inference, it is possible to derive
    conclusions that cannot be derived in a single
    step. This idea of stringing together rule
    applications leads to the notion of a proof.

38
Axiom schemata
  • The implication introduction schema (II),
    together with Modus Ponens, allows us to infer
    implications.
  • j Þ (y Þj)
  • The implication distribution schema (ID) allows
    us to distribute one implication over another.
  • (j Þ (y Þ c)) Þ((jÞy) Þ(jÞ c))
  • The contradiction realization schemata (CR)
    permit us to infer a sentence if the negation of
    that sentence implies some sentence and its
    negation.
  • (y Þ Øj) Þ((y Þj) ÞØy)
  • (Øy ÞØj) Þ((Øy Þj)Þy)
  • The equivalence schemata (EQ) capture the meaning
    of the Û operator.
  • (j Ûy)Þ (j Þy)
  • (j Ûy)Þ (y Þj)
  • (j Þy)Þ ((y Þj)Þ (y Ûj))
  • The meaning of the other operators in
    propositional logic is captured in the following
    axiom schemata.
  • (j Üy)Û(y Þj)
  • (j Úy )Û(Øj Þy)
  • (j Ùy)Û Ø(Øj Ú Øy)
  • The axiom schemata in this section are jointly
    called the standard axiom schemata for
    Propositional Logic. They all are valid.

39
Proofs
  • A proof of a conclusion from a set of premises is
    a sequence of sentences terminating in the
    conclusion in which each item is either (1) a
    premise, (2) an instance of an axiom schema, or
    (3) the result of applying a rule of inference to
    earlier items in sequence.
  • 1. p Þ q Premise
  • 2. q Þ r Premise
  • 3. (q Þ r)Þ (p Þ(q Þ r)) II
  • 4. p Þ(qÞ r) MP 3,2
  • 5. (p Þ(qÞ r)) Þ(( pÞ q) Þ(p Þ r)) ID
  • 6. (p Þ q)Þ (p Þr ) MP 5,4
  • 7. p Þ r MP 6,1

40
Proofs (continued)
  • If there exists a proof of a sentence j from a
    set D of premises and the standard axiom schemata
    using Modus Ponens, then j is said to be provable
    from D (written as D - j) and is called a
    theorem of D.
  • Earlier, it was suggested that there is a close
    connection between provability and logical
    entailment. In fact, they are equivalent. A set
    of sentences D logically entails a sentence j if
    and only if j is provable from D.
  • Soundness Theorem If j is provable from D, then
    D logically entails j.
  • Completeness Theorem If D logically entails j,
    then j is provable from D.
  • The concept of provability is important because
    it suggests how we can automate the determination
    of logical entailment.
  • Starting from a set of premises D, we enumerate
    conclusions from this set.
  • If a sentence j appears, then it is provable from
    D and is, therefore, a logical consequence.
  • If the negation of j appears, then Øj is a
    logical consequence of D and j is not logically
    entailed (unless D is inconsistent).
  • Note that it is possible that neither j nor Øj
    will appear.

41
Resolution
42
Intro
  • Propositional resolution is an extremely powerful
    rule of inference for Propositional Logic. Using
    propositional resolution (without axiom schemata
    or other rules of inference), it is possible to
    build a theorem prover that is sound and complete
    for all of Propositional Logic.
  • What's more, the search space using propositional
    resolution is much smaller than for standard
    propositional logic.

43
Clausal Form
  • Propositional resolution works only on
    expressions in clausal form. Before the rule can
    be applied, the premises and conclusions must be
    converted to this form.
  • A literal is either an atomic sentence or a
    negation of an atomic sentence. For example, if p
    is a logical constant, the following sentences
    are both literals p, Øp
  • A clause expression is either a literal or a
    disjunction of literals. If p and q are logical
    constants, then the following are clause
    expressions
  • p, Øp, p Úq
  • A clause is the set of literals in a clause
    expression. For example, the following sets are
    the corresponding clauses p, Øp, p,q
  • Note that the empty set is also a clause. It
    is equivalent to an empty disjunction and,
    therefore, is unsatisfiable.

44
Converting to clausal form
  • 1. Implications (I)
  • j1 Þ j2 Øj1 Ú j2
  • j1 Ü j2 j1 Ú Øj2
  • j1 Ûj2 (Øj1 Ú j2 ) Ù(j1 Ú Øj2 )
  • 2. Negations (N)
  • ØØj j
  • Ø(j1 Ù j2 ) Øj1 ÚØj2
  • Ø(j1 Új2 ) Øj1 ÙØj2
  • 3. Distribution (D)
  • j1 Ú (j2 Ù j3 ) (j1 Ú j2) Ù(j1 Ú j3 )
  • (j1 Ùj2 ) Ú j3 (j1 Ú j3 ) Ù (j2 Ú j3)
  • (j1 Új2 ) Ú j3 j1 Ú (j2 Ú j3 )
  • (j1 Ùj2 ) Ù j3 j1 Ù (j2 Ù j3)
  • 4. Operators (O)
  • j1 Ú... Újn j1,...,jn
  • j1 Ù ...Ùjn j1...jn

45
Examples
  • g Ù (r Þ f )
  • I g Ù (Ør Ú f )
  • N g Ù (Ør Ú f )
  • D g Ù (Ør Ú f )
  • O g
  • Ør, f

Ø(g Ù (rÞ f )) I Ø(g Ù (Ør Ú f )) N Øg ÚØ(Ør Ú
f )) Øg Ú(ØØr Ù Øf ) Øg Ú(r ÙØf ) D (Øg Úr)
Ù(Øg Ú Øf ) O Øg,r Øg,Øf
46
Propositional Resolution
  • j1,..., c,...,jm
  • y1,...,Øc,...,yn
  • j1,...,jm,y1,...,yn
  • E.g.
  • p,q
  • Øp,r
  • q,r
  • The idea of resolution is simple.
  • Suppose we know that p is true or q is true, and
    suppose we also know that p is false or r is
    true.
  • One clause contains p, and the other contains Øp.
  • If p is false, then by the first clause q must be
    true.
  • If p is true, then, by the second clause, r must
    be true.
  • Since p must be either true or false, then it
    must be the case that q is true or r is true.
  • In other words, we can cancel the p literals.

47
Example
  • 1. p,q Premise
  • 2. Øp, q Premise
  • 3. p,Øq Premise
  • 4. Øp,Øq Premise
  • 5. q 1,2
  • 6. Øq 3,4
  • 7. 5,6

48
Two finger (or pointer) method
  • We keep two pointers (the slow and the fast)
  • On each step we compare the sentences under the
    pointers. If we can resolve, we add the new
    derived sentence at the end of the list.
  • At the start of the inference we initialize slow
    and fast at the top of the list.
  • As long as the two pointers point to different
    positions, we leave the slow where it is and
    advance the fast.
  • When they meet, we move the fast at the top of
    the list and we move the slow one position down
    the list.

49
Example (two finger method)
  • 1. p,q Premise
  • 2. Øp,r Premise
  • 3. Øq, r Premise
  • 4. Ør Premise
  • 5. q,r 1,2
  • 6. p,r 1,3
  • 7. Øp 2,4
  • 8. Øq 3,4

9. r 3,5 10. q 4,5 11. r 2,6 12. p
4,6 13. q 1,7 14. r 6,7 15. p 1,8 16.
r 5,8 17. 4,9
50
TFM With Identical Clause Elimination
  • 1. p,q Premise
  • 2. Øp,r Premise
  • 3. Øq, r Premise
  • 4. Ør Premise
  • 5. q,r 1,2
  • 6. p,r 1,3
  • 7. Øp 2,4
  • 8. Øq 3,4
  • 9. r 3,5
  • 10. q 4,5
  • 11. p 4,6
  • 12. 4,9

51
Another TFM example
  • 1. p,q
  • 2. p,Øq
  • 3. Øp,q
  • 4. Øp,Øq
  • 5. p 1,2
  • 6. q 1,3
  • 7. Øq, q 2,3
  • 8. p,Øp 2,3
  • 9. q,Øq 1,4
  • 9.5 p,Øp 1,4
  • 10. Øq 2,4

11. Øp 3, 4 12. q 3,5 13. Øq 4,5 14. p
2,6 15. Øp 4,6 16. p,q 1,7 17. Øq, p
2,7 18. Øp,q 3,7 19. Øq,Øp 4,7 20. q 6,7
52
continued
  • 21. Øq, q 7, 7
  • 22. Øq, q 7, 7
  • 23. q, p 1,8
  • 24. Øq, p 2,8
  • 25. Øp,q 3,8
  • 26. Øp,Øq 4,8
  • 27. p 5,8
  • 28. Øp, p 8,8
  • 29. Øp, p 8,8
  • 30. p,q 1,9

31. Øq, p 2,9 32. Øp, q 3,9 33. Øq,Øp 4,
9 34. q 6,9 35. Øq,q 7,9 36. q,Øq
9,9 37. q,Øq 9,9 38. p 1,10 39. Øp
3,10 40. 6,10
53
Proof With Identical Clause Elimination
  • 1. p,q
  • 2. p,Øq
  • 3. Øp,q
  • 4. Øp,Øq
  • 5. p 1,2
  • 6. q 1,3
  • 7. Øq, q 2,3
  • 8. p,Øp 2,3
  • 9. q,Øq 1,4
  • 10. Øq 2,4
  • 11. Øp 3,4
  • 12. 6,10

54
Motivation for Tautology Elimination
  • A tautology is a clause with a complementary pair
    of literals.
  • 1. p,q Premise
  • 2. p,Øp Premise
  • 3. p,q 1,2

55
Proof with TE and ICE
  • 1. p, q
  • 2. p,Øq
  • 3. Øp, q
  • 4. Øp,Øq
  • 5. p 1,2
  • 6. q 1,3
  • 7. Øq 2, 4
  • 8. Øp 3,4
  • 9. 6,7
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com