Economics for Democratic Socialism - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 52
About This Presentation
Title:

Economics for Democratic Socialism

Description:

... tempting to try to construct ... This would be 'fair' ex ante but very inefficient. Trade ... place, and so the equity and efficiency are ex ante, not ex post. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:26
Avg rating:3.0/5.0

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Economics for Democratic Socialism


1
Economics for Democratic Socialism
  • Drexel University
  • Spring Quarter 2009

2
Economic Planning
  • In the early twentieth century, many socialists
    and others believed that market outcomes are
    chaotic, irrational, and very inefficient.
  • They called for government control of the economy
    in order to implement a rational plan.
  • However, neoclassical and Austrian economists had
    shown that in ideal circumstances, market
    equilibria could be rational (in a certain,
    utilitarian sense) and, indeed, efficient, as we
    have seen.

3
Rational Plan 1
  • However, it could be argued that there is more to
    rational direction of the economy than efficient
    allocation of resources.
  • Even in an ideal market economy, the outcome is
    irrational in two ways
  • Market prices depend on the distribution of
    income from wealth, which has no rational basis.
  • The market makes no provision for distribution
    according to need, while a rational plan would
    rationally determine what needs are to be met,
    and which left to individual decisions via
    markets.

4
Rational Plan 2
  • Moreover, as we have learned since that time --
  • Markets are subject to inefficiency due to
    externalities, and monopoly power, without
    rational basis.
  • A rational plan would efficiently curtail
    externalities and offset monopoly power.

5
Market Rationality
  • We need some details about the sense in which
    market equilibrium is rational.
  • Market equilibria reflect consumer demand.
  • Consumer demand in turn is determined by the
    subjective goals of consumers.
  • In principles of economics, those subjective
    goals are expressed as utility.
  • In more advanced economic theory, preferences are
    substituted for utility.

6
Planning The Case Against 1
  • Nevertheless, the Austrian case against planning
    deserves attention.
  • Von Mises drew on the Austrian representation of
    production.
  • First-order goods directly satisfy human wants.
  • Second and higher-order goods do not directly
    satisfy wants, can be used to produce first-order
    goods when appropriately combined.
  • How then can we impute value to hither-order
    goods? Mises argues only on the basis of prices.

7
The Younger Austrian School
  • Ludwig von Mises 1881-1973
  • Born Lviv, Ukraine, then part of Austria-Hungary
  • Friedrich von Hayek 1889-1982
  • Born Vienna, Austria
  • Nobel, 1974

8
From von Mises
  • It seems tempting to try to construct a
    separate estimation of the economic success of
    particular production groups in the socialist
    state also. But it is quite impossible. For each
    separate calculation of the particular branches
    of one and the same enterprise depends
    exclusively on the fact that is precisely in
    market dealings that market prices to be taken as
    the bases of calculation are formed for all kinds
    of goods and labor employed. Where there is no
    free market, there is no pricing mechanism
    without a pricing mechanism, there is no economic
    calculation.

9
Lange
  • In von Mises terminology, socialism planning,
    and a system of worker cooperatives would be
    syndicalism.
  • Oscar Lange, a Polish Marxist, responded that a
    socialist state could nevertheless make use of
    markets.

Oskar Lange, 1904-1965
10
Rejoinder 1
  • Lange argued that a socialist state could use
    markets to direct the allocation of resources.
  • Lange drew partly on another tradition Walras
    general equilibrium theory.
  • Only equilibrium prices impute values
    efficiently.
  • That means supplydemand in every market.
  • Walras envisioned an auction process to determine
    those general equilibrium prices.
  • But there is no such auctioneer in the actual
    world.

11
Rejoinder 2
  • Lange proposed that the managers of socialized
    enterprises be directed to maximize profits.
  • Prices would be determined by the state, and
    adjusted by trial and error to the equilibrium
    prices, as Walras had envisioned the auctioneer
    doing.
  • Probably Lange thought of this as only an
    accounting procedure to support efficient
    planning.
  • Nevertheless it was the origin of modern ideas of
    market socialism, i.e. the combination of
    public ownership with decentralized management
    and a market mechanism.

12
The Case Against 2
  • Hayek responded that planners could nevertheless
    never have sufficient information to plan
    rationally.
  • He stressed that much of the information needed
    for economic calculation is not like scientific
    and technological information.
  • Scientific information is true regardless of time
    and place.
  • Much economically relevant information is
    specific to time and place.
  • For example such and such resources are
    available at such and such time and place.

13
The Case Against 3
  • The people who have this information specific to
    time and place may not reveal it unless they
    profit by doing so.
  • For this to happen, there has to be actual
    trading in the markets for second and
    higher-order goods -- that is, (Hayek asserts)
    capitalism.
  • This probably is the first discussion of
    asymmetric information in economics, and has
    been much extended in late twentieth century
    economics -- but mostly in a direction critical
    of free markets!

14
Asymmetric Information
  • Hayeks point is that such information cannot --
    even in principle -- be known to central
    planners.
  • The people who have the information can be
    induced to put it into effect only in response to
    profit motives (in a very general sense).
  • This can occur, he argues, only with a capitalist
    market system.

15
Does Hayeks Argument Hold Water?
  • Paul Rosenstein-Rodan, who had studied with
    Mises, made similar assumptions the basis for a
    call for planning.
  • This illustrates a shortcoming of the Austrian
    economics. Their verbal plausible reasoning
    often is not conclusive.

P. N. Rosenstein-Rodan (1902-1985)
16
Coordination Failure 1
This is Rosenstein-Rodans Shoe factory example.
The managers of the shoe factory assume that
growth in demand will be slow, so
17
Coordination Failure 2
  • Believing the growth of demand for shoes will
    be slow, the managers of the shoe factory decide
    not to expand.
  • Believing the growth of demand for shirts will
    be slow, the managers of the shirt factory decide
    not to expand.
  • As a consequence, they are all right -- demand
    growth is slow.

18
Coordination Failure 3
  • Rosenstein-Rodan argues that central planning
    is the only way out of this trap.
  • Notice the role that asymmetric information
    plays in this example
  • None of the managers knows what the plans of
    the other managers are.
  • If they did know, then the problem would not
    arise.
  • Not knowing, they must base their plans on
    conjecture, rather than fact.
  • However, a common conjecture becomes a
    self-fulfilling prophesy.

19
A Zigzag of Progress?
  • Of course, this discussion had no impact on the
    practice of planning in the Soviet Union.
  • Consequently it had relatively little impact on
    the discussion of economic planning after World
    War II.
  • Neoclassical economists developed a rudimentary
    theory of planning as a means of understanding
    Soviet planning -- but mostly by contrast.
  • Perhaps it is ironic that neither side in the
    earlier controversies influenced this theory.

20
Simple Economy
Let us return to the simple example of
Economia, and economy that produces only two
goods. How to plan for this tiny economy?
21
Planners Preferences
  • The first step for Economia's planning bureau is
    to determine what its objectives are, and to
    express those in terms of quantities of food and
    machinery produced.
  • Recall, in neoclassical market theory, consumers
    preferences determine demand.
  • The neoclassical theory of planning supposes that
    the planners have preferences over the outputs of
    the national economy.
  • The Planners' preferences are expressed in
    neoclassical thinking by a set of indifference
    curves.

22
Optimal Planning
The optimal plan in terms of the planners
preferences is at point But, of course, it
isnt that easy!
http//faculty.lebow.drexel.edu/mccainr/ top/prin/
txt/comsysf/cs5.html
23
Information
  • If the planning bureau had unlimited information
    aqnd computational capacity, they could just
    compute the plan and instruct the enterprises as
    to what they should produce.
  • How can the planners get the information they
    need? One possibility is to ask the enterprise
    managers how much they can produce. Let's make
    the optimistic assumption that the enterprise
    managers will tell the truth -- either because
    they are nice guys or because the planning bureau
    has found some costless way of giving them an
    incentive to tell the truth.

24
Iteration
  • The bureau starts out optimistically with a
    tentative plan at A. But the enterprises'
    resource requirements will add up to more
    resources than are available -- A is infeasible.
    Adjusting, the planning bureau follows up with B.

25
Next Step
  • B is infeasible, too -- but with the information
    they have gotten from the enterprises on these
    two attempts, the plan bureau makes its third
    iteration C. That is an improvement -- C is
    feasible -- but it is inefficient, since
    enterprises are capable of producing more than C
    with available resources.

26
Further Steps
  • The planning bureau scales up the production
    amounts to D. This is better still -- D is
    efficient, that is, on the production possibility
    frontier -- but it is not optimal. With the
    available resources, the planning bureau would
    prefer to see more machines and less food
    produced.

27
Optimal Plan
  • By now, however, the planning bureau has gotten
    the information they need, and on the next
    iteration they move up the production possibility
    frontier to , the optimal plan. This is the plan
    they direct the enterprises to carry out.

28
Problems
  • This is a very optimistic story.
  • Even if the enterprise managers tell the truth,
    it might take many costly iterations of the plan
    to get to the optimum at .
  • Worse, the enterprise managers have strong
    incentives to lie.
  • Even if the plan is optimal the consumers may
    not be very happy with it. If the planning bureau
    tells the enterprises to produce one finger brush
    per person.
  • In practice, Soviet planners struggled even to
    produce a feasible plan and probably never
    approached efficiency or optimality.

29
Nevertheless
  • Economic planning is very difficult, and the
    problems have never been solved in practice.
  • However, market systems are not efficient either,
    if externalities are important.
  • A real planning system might do better than a
    real market system, taking account of
    externalities.
  • Indeed, planning may yet be necessary in order
    for us to survive.

30
Two Problems
  • In principle, planning can be thought of as two
    stages
  • Framing the plan, that is, putting it down in
    specific numbers on paper.
  • Implementing the plan, that is, arranging for the
    numbers to be realized in actual production and
    distribution.
  • As we have seen, they are interrelated. Our
    ability to frame an efficient plan may depend on
    how the plan is to be implemented.
  • For now, we focus on framing.

31
Rational Distribution of Wealth
  • So far the discussion is only in terms of
    efficiency -- on which markets can do well, at
    least in ideal circumstances.
  • What about rational -- equitable -- distribution
    of income and wealth?
  • There is a neoclassical theory of equity, which
    arises from work by Duncan Foley.
  • This, with externalities and considerations of
    need, could explain the planners preferences.

32
Equity Example
  • We consider a very small economy consisting of
    two persons, Grasshopper and Ant, two jobs, a
    hard job and an easy job, and an income that can
    come in two sizes large and small.
  • The institutions of the society (the "rules of
    the game") link the large income to the hard job
    and the small income to the easy job.

33
Grasshoppers Preferences
  • We suppose that Grasshopper is a bit of a
    lazybones. Grasshopper's preferences among jobs
    and incomes is shown by the Table.

34
Ants Preferences
  • Ant's preferences are different and are shown by
    this Table.

35
Envy
  • Suppose that by accident Ant had been assigned
    the easy job and Grasshopper the hard job.
  • Grasshopper has his own third choice, but Ant has
    Grasshopper's second choice
  • Grasshopper "envies" Ant.
  • Conversely, Ant has his own third choice, but
    Grasshopper has Ant's second choice
  • Ant "envies" Grasshopper.

36
Inequity
  • This could be considered inequitable or
    unfair.
  • But the inequity is easily remedied by a market
    transaction given the opportunity, Ant and
    Grasshopper will voluntarily exchange jobs.
  • Then Ant has his second preference, while
    Grasshopper's allocation is Ant's third
    preference.
  • Conversely, what Ant has is Grasshopper's third
    preference, and Grasshopper has his own second
    preference.
  • Since each insect has a job-and-income package he
    positively prefers over the package the other
    insect has, the allocation between the two
    insects is said to be superfair.

37
No Equity
  • Suppose instead that there are two Ants, Adam
    and Hillary.
  • One of the Ants will have to be assigned the easy
    job/small income bundle. Let us suppose it is
    Adam.
  • Adam finds that he is stuck with his own third
    preference, while Hillary has Adam's second
    preference. Adam "envies" Hillary and the
    allocation between them is inequitable.
  • Switching the Ants will not help -- one or the
    other of them will "envy" the other. Inequity is
    unavoidable in this example.

38
Lottery
  • Suppose the planner decides at random which ant
    will have the hard job and large income, with
    equal probability.
  • This is fair in a sense -- neither ant prefers
    the other ants lottery ticket.
  • But the outcome, after the draw, is still not
    fair.
  • The lottery is said to be fair ex ante, but not
    ex post.
  • Is ex ante fairness good enough?

39
Back to Equity
  • Suppose that the "rules of the game" assign
    income of 8 to a hard job and 4 to an easy job,
    but we have to allocate jobs between two Ants.
  • Suppose that an Ant will accept a hard job rather
    than an easy job only on the condition that the
    hard job pays 3 more.
  • Now, our planner assigns Hillary to the easy job
    and Adam to the hard job, the redistributes 0.50
    of Adam's income to Hillary. Now Hillary has the
    easy job and 4.50 while Adam has the hard job
    and 7.50. This makes both Ants indifferent
    between the hard job and the easy job with their
    associated incomes. The result is a fair (not
    superfair) allocation.

40
A Further Complication
  • I would prefer to be a professional basketball
    player or a jazz pianist rather than an
    economist. Unfortunately, I have no talent for
    either of those professions. According to the
    strictest neoclassical conception of equity, my
    exclusion from those professions is inequitable
    I envy those who do work in those occupations.
    But we may be satisfied with a less generous
    concept of equity in the allocation of
    occupations the allocation of goods and
    occupations is inequitable if one person would
    prefer the occupation and standard of living of
    another, and is capable of doing the work that
    the other person does.

41
Consider a society in which --
  • i. Everyone consumes the same goods and services.
  • ii. Jobs are allocated by a lottery, in such a
    way that
  • 1. Everyone is assigned to a job he is capable of
    doing,
  • 2. Everyone has the same chance of being assigned
    to a particular job, given that he is capable of
    doing it.
  • This would be fair ex ante but very inefficient.

42
Trade and Fairness 1
  • Suppose that from the beginning point with equal
    consumption, people are allowed to enter into
    exchange.
  • The ski enthusiast can offer her opera tickets to
    the opera fan in return for the ski lift tickets
    allocated to the opera fan.
  • This will generate no inequity, since each will
    prefer the services she enjoys after the exchange
    to the different services the other enjoys.
  • Let this process of exchanging goods, services,
    and job probabilities continue until there is no
    pair that can mutually increase their well-being
    by exchanging.

43
Trade and Fairness 2
  • We will then have arrived at an efficient
    allocation of resources. Efficiency, in
    neoclassical economics, means that no person can
    be better off without making someone else better
    off.
  • But the result is also equitable, since we have
    begun from an equitable situation, and in each
    exchange, each person gives up what he less
    prefers to obtain what he more prefers.
  • Moreover, this allocation is a market
    equilibrium. This follows from the fact that
    there is no pair that wants to trade.

44
Trade and Fairness 3
  • Corresponding to a market equilibrium, we have a
    system of prices.
  • All trading takes place before the lottery takes
    place, and so the equity and efficiency are ex
    ante, not ex post.
  • The trading is also a mind experiment. In
    practice, the prices would have to be estimated.
  • An ideal plan then would be based on costs and
    benefits in terms of these estimated prices,
    reflecting value judgments both for equity and
    efficiency.
  • Let us call them planning prices.

45
Aufhebung
  • The general idea is we begin from a situation
    that is generally acknowledged to be equitable,
    but inefficient.
  • An all-knowing central planner would then propose
    a transition from this equitable but inefficient
    allocation to one that is efficient.
  • In the terms of benefit-cost analysis, this
    transition will generate a certain quantity of
    net benefits.
  • Let the net benefits be divided equally among all
    the members of society.
  • This allocation corresponds, conceptually at
    least, to a market equilibrium with a particular
    distribution of wealth.

46
Externalities and Needs
  • Thus far, we have not taken account of
    externalities and needs.
  • Externalities have been included in models of
    this kind, and planning prices with efficient
    abatement of externalities is no problem in
    theory.
  • Needs have not been considered, but can be
    introduced as lower constraints on quantities of
    needed goods consumed by each agent.

47
Framing and Implementation 1
  • We have come to think of a plan that could be
    expressed (from one point of view) as a set of
    prices for goods and services.
  • How can such a plan be implemented?

48
Framing and Implementation 2
  • One possibility would be as follows revenues
    from the sale of consumer goods flow, not to the
    worker cooperatives that produce the goods, but
    into a central fund.
  • The operations of the social enterprises
    producing consumer goods would then be financed
    by grants from the same fund, in such a way that
    the outputs would be valued at planning prices.
  • In effect, there would be a national marketing
    board, a public monopolist/monopsonist for
    consumer goods.

49
Framing and Implementation 3
  • This is equivalent to a 100 tax on consumer
    goods used that to finance subsidies that would
    pay wages and other costs of production
    consistent with the plan.
  • It would seem more reasonable instead to impose a
    schedule of net taxes and subsidies. Thus, for
    example, consumer good production that generates
    externalities would pay a higher than average
    tax, while production of coarse grains consumed
    by poor people, and without externalities, would
    receive a positive subsidy.

50
Framing and Implementation 4
  • This is equivalent to a 100 tax on consumer
    goods used that to finance subsidies that would
    pay wages and other costs of production
    consistent with the plan.
  • It would seem more reasonable instead to impose a
    schedule of net taxes and subsidies. Thus, for
    example, consumer good production that generates
    externalities would pay a higher than average
    tax, while production of coarse grains consumed
    by poor people, and without externalities, would
    receive a positive subsidy.

51
Framing and Implementation 5
  • This would be no different from a system of
    excise taxes and subsidies already found in most
    capitalist market economies. Indeed, so far as
    externalities are concerned, the taxes would be
    Pigovian taxes. Such taxes or some other,
    equivalent correction of market prices is in
    any case necessary to attain a rational
    allocation of resources under capitalism.

52
Conclusion
  • In principle we can put neoclassical economics to
    work and frame and implement a plan for
    efficient, equitable allocation of resources,
    using policy tools already widely deployed in
    capitalist economies.
  • Of course, the step from principle to action is
    the largest step of all.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com