Title: Economics for Democratic Socialism
1Economics for Democratic Socialism
- Drexel University
- Spring Quarter 2009
2Economic Planning
- In the early twentieth century, many socialists
and others believed that market outcomes are
chaotic, irrational, and very inefficient. - They called for government control of the economy
in order to implement a rational plan. - However, neoclassical and Austrian economists had
shown that in ideal circumstances, market
equilibria could be rational (in a certain,
utilitarian sense) and, indeed, efficient, as we
have seen.
3Rational Plan 1
- However, it could be argued that there is more to
rational direction of the economy than efficient
allocation of resources. - Even in an ideal market economy, the outcome is
irrational in two ways - Market prices depend on the distribution of
income from wealth, which has no rational basis. - The market makes no provision for distribution
according to need, while a rational plan would
rationally determine what needs are to be met,
and which left to individual decisions via
markets.
4Rational Plan 2
- Moreover, as we have learned since that time --
- Markets are subject to inefficiency due to
externalities, and monopoly power, without
rational basis. - A rational plan would efficiently curtail
externalities and offset monopoly power.
5Market Rationality
- We need some details about the sense in which
market equilibrium is rational. - Market equilibria reflect consumer demand.
- Consumer demand in turn is determined by the
subjective goals of consumers. - In principles of economics, those subjective
goals are expressed as utility. - In more advanced economic theory, preferences are
substituted for utility.
6Planning The Case Against 1
- Nevertheless, the Austrian case against planning
deserves attention. - Von Mises drew on the Austrian representation of
production. - First-order goods directly satisfy human wants.
- Second and higher-order goods do not directly
satisfy wants, can be used to produce first-order
goods when appropriately combined. - How then can we impute value to hither-order
goods? Mises argues only on the basis of prices.
7The Younger Austrian School
- Ludwig von Mises 1881-1973
- Born Lviv, Ukraine, then part of Austria-Hungary
- Friedrich von Hayek 1889-1982
- Born Vienna, Austria
- Nobel, 1974
8From von Mises
- It seems tempting to try to construct a
separate estimation of the economic success of
particular production groups in the socialist
state also. But it is quite impossible. For each
separate calculation of the particular branches
of one and the same enterprise depends
exclusively on the fact that is precisely in
market dealings that market prices to be taken as
the bases of calculation are formed for all kinds
of goods and labor employed. Where there is no
free market, there is no pricing mechanism
without a pricing mechanism, there is no economic
calculation.
9Lange
- In von Mises terminology, socialism planning,
and a system of worker cooperatives would be
syndicalism. - Oscar Lange, a Polish Marxist, responded that a
socialist state could nevertheless make use of
markets.
Oskar Lange, 1904-1965
10Rejoinder 1
- Lange argued that a socialist state could use
markets to direct the allocation of resources. - Lange drew partly on another tradition Walras
general equilibrium theory. - Only equilibrium prices impute values
efficiently. - That means supplydemand in every market.
- Walras envisioned an auction process to determine
those general equilibrium prices. - But there is no such auctioneer in the actual
world.
11Rejoinder 2
- Lange proposed that the managers of socialized
enterprises be directed to maximize profits. - Prices would be determined by the state, and
adjusted by trial and error to the equilibrium
prices, as Walras had envisioned the auctioneer
doing. - Probably Lange thought of this as only an
accounting procedure to support efficient
planning. - Nevertheless it was the origin of modern ideas of
market socialism, i.e. the combination of
public ownership with decentralized management
and a market mechanism.
12The Case Against 2
- Hayek responded that planners could nevertheless
never have sufficient information to plan
rationally. - He stressed that much of the information needed
for economic calculation is not like scientific
and technological information. - Scientific information is true regardless of time
and place. - Much economically relevant information is
specific to time and place. - For example such and such resources are
available at such and such time and place.
13The Case Against 3
- The people who have this information specific to
time and place may not reveal it unless they
profit by doing so. - For this to happen, there has to be actual
trading in the markets for second and
higher-order goods -- that is, (Hayek asserts)
capitalism. - This probably is the first discussion of
asymmetric information in economics, and has
been much extended in late twentieth century
economics -- but mostly in a direction critical
of free markets!
14Asymmetric Information
- Hayeks point is that such information cannot --
even in principle -- be known to central
planners. - The people who have the information can be
induced to put it into effect only in response to
profit motives (in a very general sense). - This can occur, he argues, only with a capitalist
market system.
15Does Hayeks Argument Hold Water?
- Paul Rosenstein-Rodan, who had studied with
Mises, made similar assumptions the basis for a
call for planning. - This illustrates a shortcoming of the Austrian
economics. Their verbal plausible reasoning
often is not conclusive.
P. N. Rosenstein-Rodan (1902-1985)
16Coordination Failure 1
This is Rosenstein-Rodans Shoe factory example.
The managers of the shoe factory assume that
growth in demand will be slow, so
17Coordination Failure 2
- Believing the growth of demand for shoes will
be slow, the managers of the shoe factory decide
not to expand. - Believing the growth of demand for shirts will
be slow, the managers of the shirt factory decide
not to expand. -
-
-
- As a consequence, they are all right -- demand
growth is slow.
18Coordination Failure 3
- Rosenstein-Rodan argues that central planning
is the only way out of this trap. - Notice the role that asymmetric information
plays in this example - None of the managers knows what the plans of
the other managers are. - If they did know, then the problem would not
arise. - Not knowing, they must base their plans on
conjecture, rather than fact. - However, a common conjecture becomes a
self-fulfilling prophesy.
19A Zigzag of Progress?
- Of course, this discussion had no impact on the
practice of planning in the Soviet Union. - Consequently it had relatively little impact on
the discussion of economic planning after World
War II. - Neoclassical economists developed a rudimentary
theory of planning as a means of understanding
Soviet planning -- but mostly by contrast. - Perhaps it is ironic that neither side in the
earlier controversies influenced this theory.
20Simple Economy
Let us return to the simple example of
Economia, and economy that produces only two
goods. How to plan for this tiny economy?
21Planners Preferences
- The first step for Economia's planning bureau is
to determine what its objectives are, and to
express those in terms of quantities of food and
machinery produced. - Recall, in neoclassical market theory, consumers
preferences determine demand. - The neoclassical theory of planning supposes that
the planners have preferences over the outputs of
the national economy. - The Planners' preferences are expressed in
neoclassical thinking by a set of indifference
curves.
22Optimal Planning
The optimal plan in terms of the planners
preferences is at point But, of course, it
isnt that easy!
http//faculty.lebow.drexel.edu/mccainr/ top/prin/
txt/comsysf/cs5.html
23Information
- If the planning bureau had unlimited information
aqnd computational capacity, they could just
compute the plan and instruct the enterprises as
to what they should produce. - How can the planners get the information they
need? One possibility is to ask the enterprise
managers how much they can produce. Let's make
the optimistic assumption that the enterprise
managers will tell the truth -- either because
they are nice guys or because the planning bureau
has found some costless way of giving them an
incentive to tell the truth.
24Iteration
- The bureau starts out optimistically with a
tentative plan at A. But the enterprises'
resource requirements will add up to more
resources than are available -- A is infeasible.
Adjusting, the planning bureau follows up with B.
25Next Step
- B is infeasible, too -- but with the information
they have gotten from the enterprises on these
two attempts, the plan bureau makes its third
iteration C. That is an improvement -- C is
feasible -- but it is inefficient, since
enterprises are capable of producing more than C
with available resources.
26Further Steps
- The planning bureau scales up the production
amounts to D. This is better still -- D is
efficient, that is, on the production possibility
frontier -- but it is not optimal. With the
available resources, the planning bureau would
prefer to see more machines and less food
produced.
27Optimal Plan
- By now, however, the planning bureau has gotten
the information they need, and on the next
iteration they move up the production possibility
frontier to , the optimal plan. This is the plan
they direct the enterprises to carry out.
28Problems
- This is a very optimistic story.
- Even if the enterprise managers tell the truth,
it might take many costly iterations of the plan
to get to the optimum at . - Worse, the enterprise managers have strong
incentives to lie. - Even if the plan is optimal the consumers may
not be very happy with it. If the planning bureau
tells the enterprises to produce one finger brush
per person. - In practice, Soviet planners struggled even to
produce a feasible plan and probably never
approached efficiency or optimality.
29Nevertheless
- Economic planning is very difficult, and the
problems have never been solved in practice. - However, market systems are not efficient either,
if externalities are important. - A real planning system might do better than a
real market system, taking account of
externalities. - Indeed, planning may yet be necessary in order
for us to survive.
30Two Problems
- In principle, planning can be thought of as two
stages - Framing the plan, that is, putting it down in
specific numbers on paper. - Implementing the plan, that is, arranging for the
numbers to be realized in actual production and
distribution. - As we have seen, they are interrelated. Our
ability to frame an efficient plan may depend on
how the plan is to be implemented. - For now, we focus on framing.
31Rational Distribution of Wealth
- So far the discussion is only in terms of
efficiency -- on which markets can do well, at
least in ideal circumstances. - What about rational -- equitable -- distribution
of income and wealth? - There is a neoclassical theory of equity, which
arises from work by Duncan Foley. - This, with externalities and considerations of
need, could explain the planners preferences.
32Equity Example
- We consider a very small economy consisting of
two persons, Grasshopper and Ant, two jobs, a
hard job and an easy job, and an income that can
come in two sizes large and small. - The institutions of the society (the "rules of
the game") link the large income to the hard job
and the small income to the easy job.
33Grasshoppers Preferences
- We suppose that Grasshopper is a bit of a
lazybones. Grasshopper's preferences among jobs
and incomes is shown by the Table.
34Ants Preferences
- Ant's preferences are different and are shown by
this Table.
35Envy
- Suppose that by accident Ant had been assigned
the easy job and Grasshopper the hard job. - Grasshopper has his own third choice, but Ant has
Grasshopper's second choice - Grasshopper "envies" Ant.
- Conversely, Ant has his own third choice, but
Grasshopper has Ant's second choice - Ant "envies" Grasshopper.
36Inequity
- This could be considered inequitable or
unfair. - But the inequity is easily remedied by a market
transaction given the opportunity, Ant and
Grasshopper will voluntarily exchange jobs. - Then Ant has his second preference, while
Grasshopper's allocation is Ant's third
preference. - Conversely, what Ant has is Grasshopper's third
preference, and Grasshopper has his own second
preference. - Since each insect has a job-and-income package he
positively prefers over the package the other
insect has, the allocation between the two
insects is said to be superfair.
37No Equity
- Suppose instead that there are two Ants, Adam
and Hillary. - One of the Ants will have to be assigned the easy
job/small income bundle. Let us suppose it is
Adam. - Adam finds that he is stuck with his own third
preference, while Hillary has Adam's second
preference. Adam "envies" Hillary and the
allocation between them is inequitable. - Switching the Ants will not help -- one or the
other of them will "envy" the other. Inequity is
unavoidable in this example.
38Lottery
- Suppose the planner decides at random which ant
will have the hard job and large income, with
equal probability. - This is fair in a sense -- neither ant prefers
the other ants lottery ticket. - But the outcome, after the draw, is still not
fair. - The lottery is said to be fair ex ante, but not
ex post. - Is ex ante fairness good enough?
39Back to Equity
- Suppose that the "rules of the game" assign
income of 8 to a hard job and 4 to an easy job,
but we have to allocate jobs between two Ants. - Suppose that an Ant will accept a hard job rather
than an easy job only on the condition that the
hard job pays 3 more. - Now, our planner assigns Hillary to the easy job
and Adam to the hard job, the redistributes 0.50
of Adam's income to Hillary. Now Hillary has the
easy job and 4.50 while Adam has the hard job
and 7.50. This makes both Ants indifferent
between the hard job and the easy job with their
associated incomes. The result is a fair (not
superfair) allocation.
40A Further Complication
- I would prefer to be a professional basketball
player or a jazz pianist rather than an
economist. Unfortunately, I have no talent for
either of those professions. According to the
strictest neoclassical conception of equity, my
exclusion from those professions is inequitable
I envy those who do work in those occupations.
But we may be satisfied with a less generous
concept of equity in the allocation of
occupations the allocation of goods and
occupations is inequitable if one person would
prefer the occupation and standard of living of
another, and is capable of doing the work that
the other person does.
41Consider a society in which --
- i. Everyone consumes the same goods and services.
- ii. Jobs are allocated by a lottery, in such a
way that - 1. Everyone is assigned to a job he is capable of
doing, - 2. Everyone has the same chance of being assigned
to a particular job, given that he is capable of
doing it. - This would be fair ex ante but very inefficient.
42Trade and Fairness 1
- Suppose that from the beginning point with equal
consumption, people are allowed to enter into
exchange. - The ski enthusiast can offer her opera tickets to
the opera fan in return for the ski lift tickets
allocated to the opera fan. - This will generate no inequity, since each will
prefer the services she enjoys after the exchange
to the different services the other enjoys. - Let this process of exchanging goods, services,
and job probabilities continue until there is no
pair that can mutually increase their well-being
by exchanging.
43Trade and Fairness 2
- We will then have arrived at an efficient
allocation of resources. Efficiency, in
neoclassical economics, means that no person can
be better off without making someone else better
off. - But the result is also equitable, since we have
begun from an equitable situation, and in each
exchange, each person gives up what he less
prefers to obtain what he more prefers. - Moreover, this allocation is a market
equilibrium. This follows from the fact that
there is no pair that wants to trade.
44Trade and Fairness 3
- Corresponding to a market equilibrium, we have a
system of prices. - All trading takes place before the lottery takes
place, and so the equity and efficiency are ex
ante, not ex post. - The trading is also a mind experiment. In
practice, the prices would have to be estimated. - An ideal plan then would be based on costs and
benefits in terms of these estimated prices,
reflecting value judgments both for equity and
efficiency. - Let us call them planning prices.
45Aufhebung
- The general idea is we begin from a situation
that is generally acknowledged to be equitable,
but inefficient. - An all-knowing central planner would then propose
a transition from this equitable but inefficient
allocation to one that is efficient. - In the terms of benefit-cost analysis, this
transition will generate a certain quantity of
net benefits. - Let the net benefits be divided equally among all
the members of society. - This allocation corresponds, conceptually at
least, to a market equilibrium with a particular
distribution of wealth.
46Externalities and Needs
- Thus far, we have not taken account of
externalities and needs. - Externalities have been included in models of
this kind, and planning prices with efficient
abatement of externalities is no problem in
theory. - Needs have not been considered, but can be
introduced as lower constraints on quantities of
needed goods consumed by each agent.
47Framing and Implementation 1
- We have come to think of a plan that could be
expressed (from one point of view) as a set of
prices for goods and services. - How can such a plan be implemented?
48Framing and Implementation 2
- One possibility would be as follows revenues
from the sale of consumer goods flow, not to the
worker cooperatives that produce the goods, but
into a central fund. - The operations of the social enterprises
producing consumer goods would then be financed
by grants from the same fund, in such a way that
the outputs would be valued at planning prices. - In effect, there would be a national marketing
board, a public monopolist/monopsonist for
consumer goods.
49Framing and Implementation 3
- This is equivalent to a 100 tax on consumer
goods used that to finance subsidies that would
pay wages and other costs of production
consistent with the plan. - It would seem more reasonable instead to impose a
schedule of net taxes and subsidies. Thus, for
example, consumer good production that generates
externalities would pay a higher than average
tax, while production of coarse grains consumed
by poor people, and without externalities, would
receive a positive subsidy.
50Framing and Implementation 4
- This is equivalent to a 100 tax on consumer
goods used that to finance subsidies that would
pay wages and other costs of production
consistent with the plan. - It would seem more reasonable instead to impose a
schedule of net taxes and subsidies. Thus, for
example, consumer good production that generates
externalities would pay a higher than average
tax, while production of coarse grains consumed
by poor people, and without externalities, would
receive a positive subsidy.
51Framing and Implementation 5
- This would be no different from a system of
excise taxes and subsidies already found in most
capitalist market economies. Indeed, so far as
externalities are concerned, the taxes would be
Pigovian taxes. Such taxes or some other,
equivalent correction of market prices is in
any case necessary to attain a rational
allocation of resources under capitalism.
52Conclusion
- In principle we can put neoclassical economics to
work and frame and implement a plan for
efficient, equitable allocation of resources,
using policy tools already widely deployed in
capitalist economies. - Of course, the step from principle to action is
the largest step of all.