Title: 4' The Rise of Expressivism
14. The Rise of Expressivism
- Antti Kauppinen
- PY 3702
- Martinmas Semester 2007
2I What is Expressivism?
3I.1 Expressivism, Non-Cognitivism, Emotivism...
- I will use expressivism as the general term for
the sort of theories on which the primary
constituents of moral judgments are attitudes
rather than beliefs - This sort of views used to be called
non-cognitivist, but as well see, recent
expressivists are willing to talk about moral
knowledge (and even, in a sense, moral beliefs),
so this can be a slightly misleading
characterization - Varieties of expressivism include emotivism,
prescriptivism, quasi-realism, explanatory
expressivism, neo-expressivism, ecumenical
expressivism, and so on
4Defining Characteristics
- Expressivism is the conjunction of the following
three claims - Moral psychology moral judgments consist in
non-cognitive (world-to-mind) attitudes toward
natural facts - Moral semantics the deep structure of moral
discourse must be understood in terms of its
function of expressing moral attitudes its
primary function is non-descriptive - Moral metaphysics the only facts there are are
those certified by natural and social science
talk of moral facts is a matter of projecting our
attitudes onto the world - So, expressivism is characterized by
non-cognitivism, non-descriptivism, and
projectivism - Note some recent expressivists reject some of
these
5I.2 Expressivism and Subjectivism
- It is essential not to confuse expressivism with
subjectivism - According to subjectivism, when I say Cheating
on your spouse is wrong, I am describing or
reporting my attitude toward cheating - Crudely, this is saying I dont like cheating
- This is straightforwardly true iff I dont like
cheating - According to expressivism, when I say Cheating
on your spouse is wrong, I am expressing or
manifesting my attitude toward cheating - Crudely, this is saying Boo cheating!
- This is neither true nor false
6The Basic Problem for Subjectivism
- (Simple) subjectivism cant explain moral
disagreement - If you say Collecting an estate tax is wrong,
and I say, Hang on, collecting an estate tax is
not wrong, we certainly appear to disagree about
the wrongness of estate tax - However, on the subjectivist account, you just
said I disapprove of estate tax and I said I
dont disapprove of estate tax these two
sentences may well be true at the same time, so
where is our disagreement? - On the subjectivist account, to contradict you, I
should say No, you do not disapprove of estate
tax! - There are better ways to capture whats worth
capturing in the idea that something can be good
for x but not good for y
7Disagreement in Attitude
- Stevenson
- Disagreement in belief two people have beliefs
that cant both be true - Disagreement in attitude two people have
attitudes that cant both be satisfied - Two men are planning to have dinner together.
One wants to eat at a restaurant that the other
doesnt like. Temporarily, then, the men cannot
agree on where to dine. - Typically, ethical disagreement involves both,
but only disagreement in attitude is essential to
it - You say Boo dancing!, expressing an attitude
with a world-to-mind direction of fit that will
be satisfied if the world is such that there is
no dancing and I say Hurrah dancing!, which is
otherwise the same except that it will be
satisfied if there is dancing so both cant be
satisfied at the same time - D-in-a determines which beliefs are relevant, and
ethical argument will terminate with A-in-A
regardless of D-in-B
8I.3 A Problem for Expressivism?
- Philip Pettit and Frank Jackson have recently
argued that if we accept a Lockean picture of
language, expressivism collapses into
subjectivism - On the Lockean picture, words are voluntary
signs that come to stand for something when we
agree to use them in the presence of certain
beliefs - Any explanation of how we English speakers came
to use the voluntary sign good' for the attitude
we do use it to express, according to
expressivists, must allow that we recognise the
attitude in question in us. For, to follow Locke,
we could hardly have agreed to use the word for
an attitude we did not recognise and failed to
believe we had, since that would be to use the
word for we know not what'. But that is to say
that expressivists must allow that - we use the word sincerely only when we believe
that we have a certain kind of attitude. And then
it is hard to see how they can avoid - conceding truth conditions to That is good',
namely, those of that belief. - So, my utterance of That is good is true iff I
approve of the demonstrated object
9No Problem for Expressivism
- Smith and Stoljar
- We have agreed to use square for square things
(to refer to them), and so utter That is square
only when we believe something is square, insofar
as were sincere. In virtue of the referential
convention, claims like That is square can be
true or false depending on whether the object is
square or not. - By contrast, while we have indeed agreed to utter
That is good only when we approve of something,
insofar as were sincere, we havent agreed to
use it for the state of approval it does not,
by our linguistic conventions, refer to our own
psychological states any more than square does - In short, while saying Thats good may indeed
conventionally convey the speakers belief that
she has the attitude of approval, but those are
not its truth conditions - Compare That is square even though I only
sincerely utter this when I believe that I
believe the object is square, its truth doesnt
consist in my so believing, but precisely in the
object being square!
10Varieties of Expressivism
- By and large, expressivists agree on metaphysics
all there is are natural facts - Differences between expressivists come out in
moral psychology, semantics, and epistemology - What exactly does thinking that something is
wrong consist in? - What is the non-descriptive function of moral
discourse? - Can there be something worth calling moral
knowledge if there are no moral facts that would
make our moral representations true?
11II First Wave Expressivism
12Basic Arguments for Expressivism
- Depending on their philosophical background
commitments, expressivists articulate different
varieties of the following four basic arguments - The Argument from Moral Internalism Only
expressivists can make sense of the essential
action-guiding character of moral judgments - The Argument from Metaphysical Parsimony
Expressivism can make sense of the phenomena of
morality without problematic metaphysical
assumptions - The Argument from Epistemic Inaccessibility
Expressivism can make sense of our talk of moral
knowledge without assuming peculiar and
implausible cognitive capacities - The Argument from Semantic Openness
Expressivists have the best explanation for the
open feel that Moore noted
13II.1 The Argument from Moral Internalism
- This is the familiar Humean argument
- Moral judgments essentially motivate
- Stevenson goodness is magnetic, so that a
person who recognizes X to be good must ipso
facto acquire a stronger tendency to act in its
favour than he otherwise would have had (1938,
16) - Only non-cognitive states (those with
world-to-mind direction of fit) essentially
motivate - So, moral judgements are non-cognitive states
- So, cognitivist theories like those of Moore,
Ross, and naturalists must be false
14Emotivism and Internalism
- The emotivism of Ayer and Stevenson is in the
first instance a thesis about the function of
moral language - For emotivists, moral judgments consist in
feelings of approval and disapproval, and moral
utterances, in spite of surface grammar, are
vehicles for expressing these feelings - Thus if I say to someone, You acted wrongly in
stealing that money, I am not stating anything
more than if I had simply said, You stole that
money. ... It is as if I had said You stole
that money, in a peculiar tone of horror, or
written it with the addition of some special
exclamation marks. The tone, or the exclamation
marks, adds nothing to the literal meaning of the
sentence. It merely serves to show that the
expression of it is attended by certain feelings
in the speaker. (Ayer) - Ayer and Stevenson are not particularly clear on
exactly which feelings and attitudes are moral
(as opposed to aesthetic or gustatory), but
plainly they are meant to give rise to action, or
at least a tendency to act - Ayer simply speaks of ethical feeling and
special sort of moral disapproval
15Emotivism and Moral Language
- Stevenson emphasizes that the key purpose of
moral language isnt merely expressing attitudes
but exhorting others to share them - When you tell a man he oughtnt to steal, your
object isnt merely to let him know that people
disapprove of stealing. You are attempting,
rather, to get him to disapprove of it. ...
Ethical terms are instruments used in the complex
interplay and readjustment of human interests.
(19) - Some words have an emotive meaning, a tendency
arising through the history of its usage, to
produce (result from) affective responses in
people - The word good has only an emotive meaning
- Words like democracy and slut have both
emotive and factual meanings
16Emotivism and Moral Argument
- For Stevenson, giving reasons in a moral
argument is a matter of citing facts that are
likely to influence the emotional reactions of
others - The alternative is non-rational persuasion, as in
presenting the suffering of the poor with such
appeal that the opponent changes her attitudes
toward the facts - Similarly, Ayer argues that moral argumentation
presupposes shared attitudes toward facts and
consists in trying to show that the opponent has
been mistaken about the empirical facts of the
case or made a logical error - If our opponent concurs with us in expressing
moral disapproval of all actions of a given type
t, then we may get him to condemn a particular
action A, by bringing forward arguments to show
that A is of type t. - If, on the other hand, the opponent, as a result
of different conditioning, doesnt share our
reactions, we finally resort to mere abuse
17II.2 Semantics and Metaphysics
- For the early expressivists, the main rivals were
intuitionist non-naturalism and varieties of
analytic naturalism - Both of these rivals drew metaphysical
conclusions from semantic premises - In effect, both shared the assumption that good
refers to a property, and analysis of its meaning
can tell us which property it is an irreducible
non-natural one or a natural one - Thus, the anti-realist expressivists defended
their view by attacking the semantic premises of
the realists
18The Argument from Semantic Openness
- As Moore had argued, whatever natural property N
x has, it always makes sense to ask whether x is
good - For expressivists, this amounts to asking whether
to approve of x this is always an open question
because - to think that something is good is to approve of
it, but - to think that something has a natural property,
whatever it may be, is not, as such to approve of
it - So, expressivism can explain the openness of the
open question without assuming that goodness is a
simple, indefinable non-natural property - Early expressivists join Moore in inferring from
the lack of natural definability that goodness
cant be a natural property
19Hare Against Descriptivism
- An alternative expressivist argument against
analytic naturalism is based on the possibility
of moral disagreement and reform - Grant that we use terms like good on the basis
of some natural properties that the object has - Still, it is possible that A thinks things that
are x are good and B thinks different things that
are y are good - If good means x for A and y for B, there is no
disagreement between A and B things that are x
are good-A and things that are y are good-B - But, intuitively, A and B disagree, so good
cannot mean either x or y - Similarly, moral reform is possible someone may
intelligibly deny that something we all have
thought is good isnt such
20The Argument from Unverifiability
- Ayers argument was based on the verificationist
theory of meaning, according to which only
statements whose truth or falsity can (in
principle) be verified are cognitively
significant - More precisely, meaningful synthetic statements
are those that some possible experience can
support - No possible observations, however, support moral
conclusions, any more than they do metaphysical
or religious ones - Thus, there is no way, in principle, to settle
the argument between someone who thinks that
abortion is wrong and someone who thinks its not
wrong by appeal to facts - So, ethical statements lack cognitive meaning
- They are unverifiable for the same reason as a
cry of pain or a word of command is unverifiable
because they do not express genuine
propositions. (Ayer, 43)
21Problems with First Wave Expressivism
- No explanation for why we make the error we
apparently do when we think and talk as if there
were moral properties and facts - No explanation for the inferential role that
moral statements, unlike expressions of emotions,
can play - Verificationist theories of meaning have few
supports, and the open question argument makes
questionable assumptions, so the case for
expressivism cant be build on them
22III Second Wave Expressivism
23Saving the Apperances
- First wave expressivism could be attacked by way
of rejecting the four basic arguments - Even if one were to accept their basic thrust,
most philosophers now agree that there is a
further desideratum that early expressivists
missed, namely that of saving the apperances - We seem to argue about ethics, assert
propositions, make inferences, think that some
moral conclusions can be true independently of
how we feel in short, our ethical thought and
talk has a realist surface - To save the appearances, the expressivist must
how this realist surface comes about if ethics is
about attitudes
24Quasi-Realism and Explanatory Expressivism
- The two most sophisticated contemporary
expressivist theories, those of Simon Blackburn
and Allan Gibbard, are attempts to carry out this
project of saving the appearances - In addition, they develop further the classic
expressivist arguments from internalism and
metaphysical parsimony
25The Argument from Metaphysical Parsimony
- Unlike the logical positivists, contemporary
expressivists do not reject metaphysics as such - Rather, they embrace a particular metaphysical
outlook, naturalism or physicalism at the end of
the day, all that there is are the sort of
properties that play an explanatory role in
science - The project is fitting ethics into this picture
telling a story that explains the features of our
moral thought and practice using only
naturalistic building blocks natural facts and
our (natural) reactions to them
26III.1 The Argument from Internalism Refined
- Internalism is an essential part of a
naturalistic, evolutionary explanation for why we
have a distinct capacity to make moral judgments
in the first place - As social animals, we need to cooperate and
coordinate our actions and reactions - The key function of morality is to make this
possible - But morality can serve this function only if it
is motivationally effective - Evolutionary success may attend the animal that
helps those that have helped it, but it would not
attend any allegedly possible animal that thinks
it ought to help but does not. In the competition
for survival, it is what the animal does that
matters. This is important, for it shows that
only if values are intrinsically motivating is a
natural story of their emergence possible.
(Blackburn, FE 48)
27Blackburn on Moral Attitudes
- As weve seen, Blackburn wants to leave room for
failure to be motivated - He also wants to avoid defining moral attitudes
in phenomenal terms, since it is implausible that
you must always experience a particular feeling
when you sincerely call something wrong, say - Instead, Blackburn appeals to emotional ascent
and stability to explain what makes an attitude
moral - Start with preference, disgust, anger. Say I am
angry with you for treating her like that. This
is not yet moralizing, but suppose Im further
disposed to accept others being angry with you,
too, and even encourage them. Even stronger, Im
angry with those who are not angry with you. Im
even angry with those who are themselves angry
but are not angry with those who arent. - Someone who moralizes in this way would
disapprove of herself changing her attitudes, so
her valuing attitudes tend to be stable - Being moralistic is treating everything from
dress codes to food preferences high up on the
ladder
28The Common Point of View
- We cant very well expect others to share in our
anger (and anger at those who fail to be angry
etc.) if we moralize things that merely stand in
the way of our own self-interest - There is thus an inherent pressure toward
adopting what Hume called the common point of
view when moralizing - When a man denominates another his enemy, his
rival, his antagonist, his adversary, he is
understood to speak the language of self-love,
and to express sentiments peculiar to himself and
arising from his particular sentiments and
situation. But when he bestows on any man the
epithets of vicious or odious or depraved, he
then speaks another language, and expresses
sentiments in which he expects all his audience
are to concur with him. He must here, therefore,
depart from his private and particular situation
and must choose a point of view common to him
with others he must move some universal
principle of the human frame and tough a string
to which all mankind have an accord and
symphony. (Hume, Enquiry IX)
29Moralizing, Guilt, and Coordination
- I feel guilt when I think that the anger of
others would be justified in expressivist
terms, I myself approve of disapproval of someone
like me - Guilt is thus a matter of internalizing the anger
of others. It characteristically derives from
ones own actions and motivates one to make
amends. - Shame, in contrast, is about internalizing the
disdain of others. It characteristically
motivates to hide, and may derive from anything
associated with oneself. - Without feelings like guilt and shame, people
would be much less likely to curb the pursuit of
their short-term self-interest and pleasure,
which in turn would lead to conflict and
instability
30Gibbard on Moral Judgment
- Gibbards account of moral judgment is cast in
terms of rationality of emotions - A judges that x is morally wrong iff A judges
that (in the absence of excusing conditions) it
is rational for her to feel guilt for having done
x and for others to be angry with her because of
it - A judges that x is morally obligatory iff A
judges that it is rational for her to feel guilt
for not having done x and for others to be angry
with her because of it - Thus, it is possible to feel guilt for x without
judging that x is morally wrong, since one might
think ones guilt is not rational - So, the inquiry into understanding moral judgment
splits into two what is it to judge that
something is rational and what is it to feel
guilt?
31Expressivism about Rationality
- To think that f-ing is rational (warranted) is to
- accept a set of
- norms that
- permit f-ing
- Norms can be thought of as rules that pair
actions with deontic statuses (permitted,
obligatory, forbidden) - So, the Ten Commandments pair killing and
fornicating with your neighbours wife with the
status of forbidden and honouring your parents
with obligatory - For any set of norms, it is a matter of fact
which deontic statuses it assigns to actions - Ideally, a set of norms covers every situation
that is, you can derive a deontic status for
every possible action
32Accepting Norms
- Hypothesis we have a special motivational
control system that - responds to linguistically encoded precepts
(norms) because - coordination and planning through language
conferred an evolutionary advantage - Being guided by language could enhance a
proto-humans biological fitness, both by
enabling him to develop complex plans for action,
and by leading him to coordinate his emotions and
actions with those of his fellows. (68) - Those who can work out together reactions to an
absent situation what to do and what to feel
are ready for like situations. 72 - Coordination requires aiming for consensus and
being motivated by one when it is found
33Norms and Rationality
- According to Gibbard, all norms are basically
norms of rationality of various responses - The various different kinds of norms governing a
thing moral norms, aesthetic norms, norms of
propriety are each norms for the rationality of
some one kind of attitude one can have toward it.
Just as moral norms are norms for the rationality
of guilt and resentment, so aesthetic norms are
norms for the rationality of kinds of aesthetic
appreciation. Norms of propriety are norms for
the rationality of shock, so that something is
improper if it makes sense to be shocked by it.
(51-52) - Conversely, questions about rationality are
questions about which norms to accept - In trying to decide what is rational, we are
engaging our normative capacities to try to
decide which norms to accept. We do this in
normative discussion, actual and imaginative, as
we take positions, subject ourselves to demands
for consistency, and undergo mutual influence.
(81)
34Emotions as Adaptations
- As Gibbard acknowledges, his account of moral
judgment is viciously circular if guilt and anger
themselves involve moral judgments - So, he argues that they are plausibly adaptive
syndromes - An adaptive syndrome is a combination of a cause
(like intrusion), expressive behaviour (barking),
and other behavioural tendencies (chasing the
intruder away) - Its adaptive, because ancestors innately
disposed to such behaviour in such circumstances
were more likely to survive and reproduce,
passing the relevant genes on
35Guilt and Shame as Adaptations
- Gibbard suggests that negative human emotions
result from threats to ones place in cooperative
schemes - Lack of resources to contribute shame
- Lack of motivation to contribute guilt
- Having such emotions is adaptive, because they
help smooth out conflicts that would otherwise
arise - These emotions are induced by things that
typically portend bad treatment by others they
are first-person counterparts to anger and
disdain - Basically, early humans who had a tendency to
modify their behaviour in these specific ways to
mollify the anger and disdain of others were more
likely to succeed in cooperative schemes and thus
survive and leave offspring
36III.2 The Argument from Moral Supervenience
- Briefly, Blackburns argument from moral
supervenience against moral realism goes as
follows - It is a priori that moral predicates supervene on
natural predicates - A metaethical theory must explain why a priori
truths about moral language hold - Moral realists cant explain why moral
supervenience is a priori - Expressivists can explain why moral supervenience
is a priori - So, we should reject moral realism and embrace
expressivism
37Supervenience
- Supervenience can be either an ontological
relation between sets of properties or a logical
relation between sets of predicates - In ontological terms, supervenience holds between
base properties and supervening properties when
it is necessarily the case that - there is no change in the supervening properties
without a change in the base properties (for
example, your beliefs dont change without a
change in your brain) and - two objects (or worlds) that have the same base
properties have the same supervening properties
(for example, if two worlds have the same
distribution of neurological patterns, people in
them have the same thoughts) - Thus, as it is sometimes put, if mental
properties ultimately supervene on physical
properties, then if God wants to create a world
in which people think exactly the same thoughts
as they now do, all She has to do is to create a
world which has identical physical properties
38Supervenience, Reduction, and Identity
- Supervenience as such is neutral between
reductivist and non-reductivist views about the
relationship between base and supervening
properties - If A-properties and B-properties are really the
same, there (trivially) can be no change in
A-properties without change in B-properties - The interest in supervenience stems largely from
the fact that it is a relationship of dependence
that is compatible with the two sets of
properties being non-identical - Supervenience is compatible with multiple
realizability A-properties can be realized by
many different bases - So, pain could be realized by C-fiber activation
in humans, D-fiber activation in baboons,
activation of area 51 in Martians, and so on
39The A Priori Supervenience of the Moral
- When it comes to the mind, it is an empirical
discovery that thoughts supervene on brain events - We can coherently conceive of a world in which
peoples thoughts change without a change in
their brain - That is, Cartesian dualism isnt a priori false
- Arguably, this is not the case with ethics
- Everyone who grasps the point of moral language
knows that if two people do exactly the same
thing in the same context, it cannot be the case
that one of them does something morally wrong and
the other something morally acceptable - Or, if you think that someone can go from being a
good person to being a bad person without a
change in her natural features (or
circumstances), it only shows you dont properly
grasp the concepts involved
40Supervenience and Analytic Necessity
- If it was analytically necessary that euthanasia,
for example, was always wrong, supervenience
would be explained - It could not be the case that something has the
same natural properties and different moral
properties, because having certain natural
properties would entail have certain moral
properties - However, if non-naturalists are right, there is
no necessary connection between any particular
natural properties and being good - So, there are no necessities of the form Vx (Nx
-gt Mx) - So, it is logically possible both that euthanasia
is right and that euthanasia is wrong, for
example - To tell which moral quality results from a given
natural state means using standards whose
correctness cannot be shown by conceptual means
alone. It means moralizing, and bad people
moralize badly, but need not be confused.
(Blackburn 1984, 184)
41The Explanatory Challenge
- So, if it is possible that an act of euthanasia
isnt wrong, how come is it a priori that if it
is wrong, any other act just like it is
necessarily wrong? - If God could have created a world in which
euthanasia has the property of being wrong or a
world in which euthanasia doesnt have the
property of being wrong, why couldnt he have
created a world in which some acts of euthanasia
have the property of being wrong and others
dont? Why is there a ban on mixed worlds? - Note that since we are talking about an a priori
necessary truth, induction wont do the trick - It isnt just that we observe act x of kind A to
be wrong, act y of kind A to be wrong etc. and
then conclude that all acts of kind A are wrong
rather, we know in advance that if one action of
kind A is wrong, all are
42Expressivism and Supervenience
- Blackburn argues that expressivists, and only
expressivists, can explain why moral
supervenience is a priori in spite of lack of
analytic necessities - The purpose of moral language is to guide choices
on the basis of natural features - If we didnt evaluate like cases alike, we
couldnt guide choices on the basis of natural
features - So, we must evaluate like cases alike to fulfil
the purpose of moral language - Competent users of concepts are in a position to
know what is necessary to fulfil the purpose of a
discourse - So, we know a priori that that we must evaluate
like cases alike
43Blackburn on Supervenience
- When we announce our moral commitments we are
projecting, we are neither reacting to a given
distribution of moral properties, nor speculating
about one. So the supervenience can be explained
in terms of the constraints upon proper
projection. Our purpose in projecting value
predicates may demand that we respect
supervenience. (Blackburn 1984, 186) - If we allowed ourselves a system (schmoralizing)
which was like ordinary evaluative practice, but
subject to no such constraint, then it would
allow us to treat naturally identical cases in
morally different ways. ... That would unfit
schmoralizing from being any kind of guide to
practical decision making (a thing could be
deemed schbetter than another although it shared
with it all the features relevant to choice or
desirability. (ibid.)