Title: Lecture 1 Logical positivism
1Lecture 1Logical positivism
2The basic historical facts
- Logical positivism started as a philosophical
movement in Austria (the Vienna Circle) and
Germany (the Berlin Circle) in the mid-1920s. - The main representatives Rudolf Carnap, Moritz
Schlick, Carl Gustav Hempel, Hans Hahn, Herbert
Feigl, Philipp Frank, Hans Reichenbach, Richard
von Mises, etc. - With the rise of Nazism in the 1930s, most
logical positivists emigrated to the United
States, and exerted an extremely strong influence
on American Philosophy.
3The philosophical background
- Empiricism-rationalism debate
- What is the main source of knowledge observation
(Locke, Berkeley, Hume), or reason (Descartes,
Spinoza, Leibniz)? - The third way Kant
- Kant was basically an empiricist, but he thought
that science gave us some knowledge that is so
certain that it cannot be based just on
observation. - Examples Euclidean geometry, arithmetic, the
principle of causality, Newtons laws of motion - Kants problem Some knowledge in science cannot
be based just on observation, but on the other
hand, observation is the only way to know
anything about the external world. - His solution the doctrine of the synthetic a
priori.
4Analytic - synthetic, a priori a posteriori
- Analytic syntheticAnalytic statements true
by virtue of their meaning (Examples All
bachelors are unmarried, Tomorrow it will
either rain or not rain) Synthetic statements
not analytic (Tomorrow it will rain, All
Lingnan students are unmarried) - A priori a posterioriA priori statements
their truth can be established without
observation (Examples All bachelors are
unmarried, Tomorrow it will either rain or not
rain) A posteriori statements their truth
cannot be established without observation
(Tomorrow it will rain, All Lingnan students
are unmarried)
5Kants table
6Speculative philosophy after Kant
- Of the three categories of statements, the most
interesting is synthetic a priori, because only
it contains general, necessary and deep truths.
The other two are either trivial and
uninteresting (analytic), or relating to
knowledge that has no necessity and generality
(synthetic a posteriori). - Since Kant used philosophical arguments to
explain our knowledge of synthetic a priori, some
philosophers after him (Hegel and Schelling)
tried to develop comprehensive systems of
knowledge by using pure thinking (speculation). - They didnt call it synthetic a priori but they
were definitely trying to discover some deep
truths about the world without making
observations.
7The Elimination of Metaphysics
- Logical positivists detested speculative
philosophy or metaphysics, as they called it.
They regarded statements made by Hegel, Schelling
and Heidegger as not just false, but meaningless. - The truth can be known only by (1) analyzing
meanings or (2) by observation. All else is
nonsense! - If we take in our hand any volume of divinity or
school metaphysics, for instance let us ask,
"Does it contain any abstract reasoning
concerning quantity or number?" No. "Does it
contain any experimental reasoning concerning
matter of fact and existence?" No. Commit it then
to the flames for it can contain nothing but
sophistry and illusion. (Hume) - Another cell in Kants table became empty.
8The logical positivists table
9The principle of verifiability
- Some statements are meaningless, although they
appear to have some meaning. - The fire that passed into crystal is its own
melting, self-burning, in which the crystal
becomes a volcano. The volcanoes should not be
understood too mechanically, but as a storm with
earthquake that happens beneath the earth. - What does that statement mean?
- Or the following Nothing nothings. (Heidegger)
- Logical positivists tried to find a way to
distinguish real statements from (meaningless)
pseudo-statements. They were looking for a
criterion of demarcation. - Their solution the principle of verifiability A
statement is meaningful only if there is a
possible experience (observation) that would show
that the statement is true.
10Why the principle of verifiability?
- The idea behind the principle if you know what
the statement mean, you know what would make it
true. But if you know what would make it true,
you know how the world would look if the
statement was true. But if you know how the world
would look if the statement was true, then you
know what observations you would make if you were
there, and if the statement was true. - Two senses of the principle strong and weak.
- Strong verifiability it must be possible to
prove that the statement is true. - Weak verifiability it must be possible to show
that the statement is probably true. - The weak version is preferable. (Scientific laws
speak about infinitely many objects and cannot be
verified in the strong sense.)
11Some problems with the principle of verifiability
- Some statements seem to be perfectly meaningful
but it is not at all clear how they could be
verified by observation. - Example Murder is wrong, The world will still
exist even after all conscious life disappears - What about the principle of verifiability itself?
Is it verifiable or not? If yes, how? If not,
then it is meaningless because it is not an
analytic statement. - The principle of verifiability was supposed to
divide all non-analytic sentences in two groups
(a) meaningless (metaphysics and other nonsense),
and (b) meaningful (science in the first place,
but also ordinary common-sense statements etc.). - But it was not successful. On strong
interpretation, it did eliminate metaphysics,
but it excluded some scientific statements too. - On weak interpretation, it preserved science, but
some metaphysical statements crept in as well.
12Humes problem of induction
- How do we verify a universal generalization?
(Scientific laws are often universal
generalizations.) - We observe many swans, and on that basis we
conclude that (S) All swans are white. Is S
really verified by these observations? - Obviously, despite all the observations of white
swans, S may still be false. - The usual answer is that the observations do not
prove S, but they certainly make it probably true
(weak verification). - But Humes argument was precisely that we have no
reason whatsoever to think that S is even
probably true! - If all observed swans were white, How can we
logically justify our expectation that the next
swan will also be white? - Hume argued that we cannot. Logical positivists
tried to show that we can. Their attempt to build
a system of inductive logic were not very
convincing. Humes problem remained unsolved.
13Why not jump out of the window?
- Answer I will fall and hurt myself. But how do I
know that I will fall? - Answer Law of gravitation. But how do I know
that the law of gravitation is true? - Answer Verified by observation (All objects
without support fall toward the surface of the
earth.) But in fact observation only tells me
that in the past all observed unsupported objects
fell. How do I know that I will fall if I jump
now? - Answer The fact that all unsupported objects
always fell in the past shows that this is a law
of nature. Otherwise, it would not have always
happened. But I dont see that. It is a logical
fallacy to conclude that an observed regularity
will continue into the future. Why shouldnt I
jump? - Answer Well, then jump, you, moron!
14Science and verifiability
- There is an inferential gap between premises
about observation and the conclusion (scientific
law). - An argument is obviously deductively invalid.
Humes challenge is to find an inductive or
probabilistic justification that could make the
argument reasonable. - Logical positivists (especially Carnap) tried to
develop inductive logic that would serve this
purpose, but they were not very successful. - Scientific laws are often regarded as having some
kind of necessity (Unsupported objects must
fall, Every biological organism must die). But
it turns out that we are not only unable to
explain their necessity. We cannot even show that
they are true! We cannot verify them.