Title: Overview
1Ethnography Ethnomethodology
- Overview
- Personal background using ethnomethodlogically-i
nformed ethnography in IT research - What is ethnography?
- An ethnomethodological reading
- Questions and short break
- The radical studies of work programme
- A rough and ready example studying homes
- Questions
2A Cautionary Word
- Ethnomethodology (EM) does not cast social
phenomenon in terms of conventional social
science distinctions and practices. For example, - EM does not exploit objective/subjective
dichotomy - Or agency and structure
- Or macro and micro
- You will find these and other staple topics of
the social sciences discussed within the EM
literature but they are treated critically and
dispensed with as EM has no use for them, no work
for them to do - See Wes Sharrock and Rod Watson Autonomy
among social theories the incarnation of social
structures, Actions and Structure (ed. Fielding,
N.), pp. 56-77, Sage, 1988. - Wes Sharrock and Graham Button The social
actor social action in real time,
Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences (ed.
Button, G.), pp. 137-175, Cambridge University
Press, 1991.
3Square Pegs and Round Holes
- So you cant align EM with conventional social
science - A strange kind of Californian subjectivity its
not - Garfinkels slogans
- EM is asymmetrically alternate
- EM is incommensurable
- EM is not available to conventional social
science - Of course you can try to make EM answerable to
conventional social science but you will only end
up losing what it is about, you will misread it - See Harold Garfinkel and Lawrence Wieder Two
incommensurable, asymmetrically alternate
technologies of social analysis, Text in
Context Contributions to Ethnomethodology (eds.
Watson, G. and Seiler, S.M.), pp.175-206, Sage,
1992.
4Setting Caution Aside
- Im not going to tell you why EM has no use for
the conventional distinctions and practices of
social science - Dealing with these issues would take many
lectures - And they are well documented - see Button, G.
(ed.) Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences,
Cambridge University Press, 1991 for a
comprehensive introduction and treatment - So why tell you, beyond inviting you to read into
the matter? - EM requires that you suspend the educated ways
in which you have been taught to make sense of
the social (Sacks 1992) - to suspend talking
about life in terms of agency, structures, and
the like - and demands that you step outside the
box - Harvey Sacks On exchanging glances, in
Lectures on Conversation (ed. Jefferson, G.),
Volume 1, Part 1, Fall 1964 - Spring 1965), pp.
81-94, Oxford Blackwell Publishers, 1992.
5Moving On What is Ethnography?
- Put 20 different ethnographers in a room and you
will get 20 different answers - So what does that tell us?
- That ethnography is a diverse enterprise
consisting of heterogeneous conceptions and
practices - Ethnography cannot be commonly defined - it has
the characteristics alluded to in Wittgensteins
aphorism about games - What is common to them all? - Dont say There
must be something common, or they would not be
called games - but look and see whether there
is anything common to all. - For if you look at
them you will not see something that is common to
all, but similarities, relationships, and a whole
series of them at that To repeat dont think,
but look! - To understand something of the salience of
Wittgensteinian thought to EM see, Jeff Coulter
The Social Construction of Mind Studies in
Ethnomethodology and Linguistic Philosophy, Rowan
and Littlefield, 1979.
6No Commonality?
- But what about method?
- Surely ethnography minimally requires first-hand
observation, the immersion of a fieldworker in
some setting of social action? - When doing ethnographic research one thing is
needful first-hand observation. Go and sit in
the lounges of the luxury hotels and on the
doorsteps of the flophouses sit on the Gold
Coast settees and the slum shakedowns sit in the
orchestra hall and in the Star and Garter
burlesque. In short, gentlemen, go get the seat
of your pants dirty in real research. - Robert Ezra Park, cited in Robert Prus Symbolic
Interaction and Ethnographic Research
Intersubjectivity and the Study of Human Lived
Experience, State University of New York Press,
1996. - The problem is, what is meant by observation,
setting and immersion? - Is a fieldworker who investigates news paper
reports by reading them doing observation by
immersion in a setting? - See, for example, Lena Jayyusi The equivocal
text and the objective world an
ethnomethodological analysis of a news report,
The Australian Journal of Media Culture, vol. 5
(1), 1991. http//wwwmcc.murdoch.edu.au/ReadingRoo
m/ 5.1/Jayyusi.html - Well, yes. The point is that there is no
commonality of methods. Ethnography cannot be
pinned down. There is no definitive version.
Furthermore, old versions fall out of use and new
ones get created all the time (hence similarities
and relationships)
7So Where Does That Leave Us?
- Trading in (competing) versions an
ethnomethodological version (one of many, EM not
a unified field) - There is nothing special about ethnography
- Ethnographies are a staple feature of everyday
life - the member in the midst of witnessed actual
settings recognizes that witnessed settings have
an accomplished sense, an accomplished facticity,
an accomplished accountability That
accomplishment consists of members doing,
recognizing, and using ethnographies. - Harold Garfinkel Studies in Ethnomethodology,
Prentice-Hall, 1967. - Forget the terminology (close encounters with
difficult words), the point is that Garfinkel
sees ethnography as something that members do all
of the time (some examples) - Ethnography is a members method for
investigating, observing, querying, articulating,
understanding, recognizing, etc., social settings
from within the flow of activities and events
that populate those settings - What the method of the matter consists of is
EMs central concern and an issue that we will
return to
8Lay and Professional Ethnographies
- If ethnography is a ubiquitous feature of
everyday life, something ordinary members do, why
is it part of the social science research
armoury? - A distinction between lay and professional
ethnographies a recognizable difference exists
as to the ways in which ethnographic materials
are analyzed - It is not that in our capacity as ordinary
members we do not analyze ethnographic materials
- clearly an account of whats happening at work
or a family members account of his or her day is
open to analysis - but that as members (at home,
at work, at play, etc.) we do so in different
ways to professional ethnographers. - For example, classifying descriptions or treating
family members objectively - professional
approaches and methods have no place in members
analyses and are not answerable to them - See Harold Garfinkel Studies of the routine
grounds of everyday activities, Studies in
Ethnomethodology, pp. 35-75, Prentice-Hall, 1967.
9Professional Analysis
- Marked by different approaches and practices
- They come packaged in reports - i.e.
professional ethnographies are textually rendered - Even visual ethnographys rely on texts and,
following the post-modern turn, rightly or
wrongly, may be construed of in textual ways - More importantly, those texts are rendered or
constructed in one of two fundamental ways - Through formal analysis, which renders
ethnographic materials in terms of coding
schemes, taxonomies, grand theories or
narratives, models and other situationally absent
descriptions. - See Harold Garfinkel and Harvey Sacks On formal
structures of practical action, Theoretical
Sociology (eds. McKinney, J.C. and Tiryakian,
E.), pp. 160-193, Apple-Century-Crofts, 1970. - Ethnomethodologically, through thick description
of the practical action and practical reasoning
exhibited by members in the unfolding course of
their activities together. That is thick
description pace Gilbert Ryle who coined the
phrase, but not Clifford Geertz who popularized
it and made it answerable to formal analysis. - See Gilbert Ryle The thinking of thoughts,
University Lectures No. 18, University of
Saskatchewan 1971. http//lucy.ukc.ac.uk/CSACSIA/V
ol14/Papers/ryle_1.html - Wes Sharrock and Robert Anderson Epistemology,
Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences (ed.
Button, G.), pp. 51-76, Cambridge University
Press, 1991.
10The Primacy of Description in Analysis
- Both approaches recognize that analysis is
intimately bound up with description - that the
way in which you describe something is
reflexively connected to your analysis. - For example, consider the following sentence
The baby cried. The astronaut picked it up. - When you read this sentence the chances are that
they hear something strange, that something is
not right about it. - What is wrong is that the method of description
does not fit the scene. The method at work here
is one of membership categorization devices or
MCDs (Sacks 1972). - Harvey SacksThe baby cried. The mommy picked it
up, Lectures on Conversation (ed. Jefferson,
G.), Volume 1, Lecture 1, Spring 1966, pp.
236-242, Blackwell Publishers, 1992.
11Description and Analysis
- MCDs come in families quite literally we might
speak of mother, father, brother, aunt,
cousin, etc., as belonging to a family of
categories. Similarly, the categories
protestant, catholic, buddhist, etc.,
belong to the religious family of categories. - The example The baby cried. The astronaut picked
it up. violates this ordinary members method of
description, however (as you might intuitively
recognize). - The descriptive categories baby and astronaut
are incongruent within the context of the
sentence and the scene it describes. - Baby and astronaut do not belong to the same
family of MCDs, they do not fit together, and so
they sound strange. - If we substitute astronaut for mommy,
however, the sentence starts to make sense, as
the categories mommy and baby belong to the
same MCD. - See Jeff Coulter Logic ethnomethodology and
the logic of language, Ethnomethodology and the
Human Sciences (ed. Button, G.), pp. 20-50,
Cambridge University Press, 1991.
12Description and Analysis?
- Of course it might asked if we are really
analyzing anything here? In response to that we
might briefly consider Sacks account of the
sentences properly construed. - When I hear The baby cried. The mommy picked
it up. one of the things I hear is that the
mommy who picks the baby up is the mommy of the
baby. Now its not only the case that I hear it
that way - and of course theres no genitive
there to say its mommy picked it up, his
mommy, her mommy - when I hear it that way a
kind of interesting thing is that I also feel
pretty confident that all of you, at least the
natives among you, hear that also. Is that
magic? - Its not magic of course but a matter of methods
of description and MCDs in this case, which as
natural language speakers or natives we all
share and exploit to reason about - to analyze -
the events we attend to. - So, the way in which things are described - the
methods employed, whether lay or professional -
are intimately bound up with how things are
analyzed then, and this has a consequence for how
ethnographies get done.
13Reflexivity of Description and Analysis
- In producing ethnographic texts, both formal
analysis and ethnomethodology have an abiding
concern with reflexivity, but in very different
ways. - Formal analysis is largely concerned with
analytic reflexivity, a notion which came into
focus following the crisis of representation that
marked the post-modern turn in the social
sciences - Analytic reflexivity (and its variants, e.g.,
positional reflexivity, textual reflexivity) is
directed towards critical self-reflection in
order to understand the ways in which the very
act of ethnography and ethnographic reportage
shapes our understanding of the social - And is concerned to find solutions to the
professional belief that there is an inevitable
degree of cultural and subjective bias built into
the act ethnography and ethnographic reportage - See Doug Macbeth On reflexivity in
qualitative research two readings, and a third,
Qualitative Inquiry, vol. 7, pp. 35-68, 2001.
14Analytic Reflexivity and EM
- EM respects the good sense and tradition of
critical reflection - It does not except what Egon Bittner calls the
the self-indulgent concentration that marks
analytic reflexivity - Concern with the ethnographers cultural context,
position, influence, bias, textual practices,
etc., pre-dates the post-modern turn - And Bittner was fiercely critical of it then as
ethnomethodologists are now, suggesting that such
forms of self-absorption represent a pallid
ideology of cultural relativism - Egon Bittner Objectivity and realism in
sociology, Phenomenological Sociology (ed.
Psathas, G.), pp. 109-125, John Wiley, 1973. - Mike Lynch Against reflexivity as an academic
virtue and source of privileged knowledge,
Theory, Culture, and Society vol. 17, pp. 27-53,
2000.
15So What is EMs Interest in Reflexivity?
- We are not now interested in professional
beliefs but in that outlook which takes over
when something must be done, for example, when
someone must do what needs doing to successfully
take a plane across the country. The point here
is that when someone has business with the world,
or any part of it, he must be prepared to deal on
the worlds terms. What these terms are is not
reliably taken from what the timid have to say.
Instead, the terms are, from case to case, in
what even the most radical of the radical comes
to see when he sees that sometimes some things
have to be done, and sometimes there is no
getting around certain things, no matter what, in
spite of all rational considerations. Egon
Bittner - EM is interested in the practical achievement of
social phenomenon - In how things are done by parties to them, by
members, and done congregationally,
collaboratively, in concert with others - I.e., in how things are done as the socially
organized affairs of everyday life - Reflexivity is an essential and indispensable
feature of this achievement
16Reflexivity in Ethnomethodology
- The reflexivity of accounts
- We offer the observation that persons, in that
they are heard to be speaking a natural language,
somehow are heard to be engaged in the objective
production and objective display of everyday
activities as observable and reportable phenomena
What is it about natural language that makes
these phenomena observable-reportable, i.e.,
account-able phenomena? The interests of
ethnomethodological research are directed to
provide, through detailed analyses, that
account-able phenomena are through and through
practical accomplishments. We shall speak of the
work of that accomplishment in order to gain the
emphasis for it of an ongoing course of action.
Garfinkel and Sacks (1970) - Accounts are features of talk and talk is a
feature of all social settings - Ethnomethodology suggests that it is through
talking - through the ongoing production of
accounts - that members reflexively produce the
social settings they inhabit as objective
features of everyday life - EM is exclusively dedicated to uncovering how in
the ongoing production of their accounts - in
their work together - members come to organize
everyday life and reflexively produce the
everyday settings they inhabit - It is here, however, that ethnomethodologists
start to fall out
17Orienting to the Reflexivity of Accounts
- Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis
- EM developed by Garfinkel, CA by Sacks
- Often spoken about in the same breathe, as if
they were concerned with the same things - To some extent they are but there are fundamental
differences between the two, which impact on
analytic treatment of the reflexivity of accounts - The difference revolves around formulations
- Formulations are integral features of talk, when
we talk we formulate remarks, questions,
greetings, disputes, etc. - Formulation is a pervasive moment-by-moment
feature of talk that never stops - open your
mouth and you are doing it again (and you need
not even do that much)
18Handling Formulations
- CA takes it that the work of everyday life is
to be found in members formulations and has,
over the years, uncovered a turn-taking
machinery organizing the production of talk and
the organized affairs of everyday life - Harvey Sacks, Emanuel Schegloff, and Gail
Jefferson A simplest systematics for the
organization of turn-taking in conversation,
Language, vol. 50, pp. 696-735, 1974. - EM takes it that while an accountable feature of
everyday life, formulations do not make the
work of everyday life - and thus the socially
organized production of everyday settings -
available - Instead the work of everyday life becomes a
feature of the turn-taking machinery the work of
everyday life has been substituted by CA for an
analytic apparatus then - Mike Lynch, M. Scientific Practice and Ordinary
Action Ethnomethodological and Social Studies of
Science, Cambridge University Press, 1993. - Mike Lynch and Dave Bogen Harvey Sacks
primitive natural science, Theory, Culture and
Society, vol. 11, pp. 65-104, 1994.
19EM Treatment of Formulations
- While formulations do work - i.e., are
constituent features of greetings, questions,
disputes, and the rest - they are not the work
of setting - Rather, formulations make the work of a setting
observable and reportable or account-able. - What the work is - what members practical
achievement of congregationally produced everyday
settings (workplaces, homes, football matches,
etc.) consists of - is not shown by examining
members formulations then, even if those
formulations are part and parcel of the settings
ongoing production here and now - So, while EM recognizes formulations and pays
foundational attention to them, it is not in the
same way as CA - For EM, analytic attention is not to be directed
towards members formulations per se - and work
attributed to the workings of an analytic
apparatus - but to the practical actions and
activities accomplished by members over the
unfolding course of doing and recognizing
formulations. - It might otherwise be said that while members
formulations provide the initial focus for EM
study and analysis, the work they accomplish is
the primary object of analysis, as it is in the
work that formulations do that the social
organization of everyday settings becomes visible.
20Making Work Visible
- So EM is different to CA in that is concerned to
uncover what work talk accomplishes rather than
how talk works - How does EM go about uncovering work - i.e.,
the practical, socially organized achievement of
everyday life? - Like social science research generally, by
consulting or eliciting information from
members. The question is, how is consultation
done? - Fundamentally, essentially, without evasion, EM
suspends the use of social science methods as a
means of consultation - and that includes
theorising - Why? Because EM sees theorising not only as a
means of representation but reflexively as a
method of description, which involves rendering
everyday life in terms of a priori, situationally
absent formulations - Harvey Sacks Sociological description,
Berkeley Journal of Sociology, vol. 8, pp. 1-16,
1963. - Melinda Baccus Sociological indication and the
visibility criterion of real world social
theorising, Ethnomethodological Studies of Work
(ed. Garfinkel, H.), pp. 1-19, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1986. - And what EM wants to get at in the first instance
is members formulations, and in the second
21Methods and EM
- Whose methods?
- As Garfinkel and Wieder (1992) put it,
- Just in any actual case a phenomenon of order
be it paid labour, domestic life, play,
education, prison, driving, walking down the
street, etc. already possesses whatever as
methods methods could be - Or as Lynch (1993) describes EMs position on
methods, - Methods (whether avowedly scientific or not)
do not provide a priori guarantees, and the
initial requirement for an ethnomethodological
investigator is to find ways to elucidate methods
from within the relevant competence systems to
which they are bound. - As far as EM is concerned, whatever method
might be is not to found in the academy, in
social science tutorials, seminars, lectures,
textbooks, and the like - Other than as objects of EM study, as the academy
is an everyday setting possessed of its own
methods just as every other setting in everyday
life is possessed - So you know as a member what sorts of methods are
at work in your academic and/or research
setting, but what methods are at work in the
everyday settings you are researching? - That is the animal in the foliage EM is after -
members methods - Consequently, EM has no work for methods to do -
that is, textbook methods and the like - so it
dispenses with them
22Abandoning Method
- But surely methods are required?
- The point is that no special methods are required
to uncover members methods - nothing that
requires a social science degree - You may, however, require a degree in some other
discipline - If you want to uncover members methods in
mathematics, for example - See Eric Livingstone The Ethnomethodological
Foundations of Mathematics, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 986. - Harold Garfinkel An ethnomethodological study
of the work of Galileos inclined plane
demonstration of the real motion of free falling
bodies, Ethnomethodologys Program Working Out
Durkheims Aphorism, pp. 263-285, Rowman and
Littlefield, 2001. - Why? Because uncovering the methods with which
everyday activities are possessed requires that
you have a vulgar competence in those very
methods
23Developing Vulgar Competence
- The unique adequacy requirement of methods
- for analysts to recognize, or identify, or
follow the development of, or describe phenomena
of order in local production of coherent detail
the analyst must be vulgarly competent in the
local production and reflexively natural
accountability of the phenomena of order he is
studying. We will replace the abbreviation
studying with the specific requirement that the
analyst be, with others, in a concerted
competence of methods with which to recognize,
identify, follow, display, and describe phenomena
of order in local productions of coherent detail.
These are uniquely possessed in, and as of, the
objects endogenous local production and natural
accountability. (Garfinkel and Wieder 1992) - Vulgar competence means that you can understand
how what it is that members are doing is being
done so as to reflexively produce the organized
affairs of everyday life - That how consists of the work of the matter and
methods organizing the works production, and
it is as Garfinkel puts it EMs distinctive
prize - We shall consider what that prize consists of in
the next section on radical studies of work
24Ethnomethodologys Prize
- Radical studies of work
- What are they?
- Develop an answer to that question by looking at
their origins - Edmund Husserls phenomenology
- The Idea of Phenomenology (trans. Hardy, L.),
Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1999. - Concerned with the production of objective or
positive knowledge in the natural sciences - Husserl wanted to understand how positive
knowledge is possible - Not questioning truth or correctness, that is for
the sciences themselves to do. - Instead, wants to understand on what foundations
positive knowledge stands and emerges from - EM not doing phenomenology but inspired by
Husserls studies and those of his protégés,
Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty
because the focus of their studies, because of
what it is they are oriented to
25Phenomenological Origins
- The possibility of objective knowledge
- Foundations positive knowledge originates from
the natural attitude where objects are given
in various ways to experience as
objects-existing-in-a-world-out-there,
independent of the particular observer. - Husserls problem To say that positive knowledge
is, in the various technical ways of the natural
sciences, given by an objects availability to
experience is not enough to account for objective
knowledge. Husserl wants to know how it is
possible for objective knowledge to be given in
the first place? - More precisely, Husserl wants to know how it is
possible for knowledge to make contact with an
objective world and so transcend individual
experience
26Making Contact with a Transcendent
- Sources of knowing
- what is unclear is the contact with a
transcendent that is ascribed to knowledge, to
knowing knowing is something other than the
known object How can I understand this
possibility? Naturally, the answer is I could
only understand it if the relation itself could
be given, as something that could be seen. - Positive knowledge is given in the relationship
between the knowing subject and known object - What does that relationship consist of?
- Natural science account formal methods described
in scientific texts - The problem with formal methods descriptions
- Formal methods and descriptions are certainly
not useless, and learning to compose step-by-step
instructions is an important point of scientific
training, but such accounts do not provide the
stable grounds for reproducing a practice.
Although it is possible to reproduce an
observation from a written description, a text
can only allude to what eventually may count as a
replication of the observation It might be more
advisable to say that methods accounts are part
and parcel of the concerted practices that enable
them to be descriptive and instructive. Mike
Lynch Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action - Formal methods rely on some unspecified
phenomenon - the relationship between knowing and
known object consists, then, of undocumented
sources of knowing
27Documenting the Undocumented
- Unpacking the knowing-known relationship
- The optical discovery of pulsar NP 0532
- Done by astronomers John Cocke and Michael Disney
on the evening of January 16th 1969 - John Cocke, Michael Disney and Don Taylor
Discovery of optical signals from pulsar NP
0532, Nature, vol. 221, February 8th, 1969. - Imagine the situation in the astronomy
community in 1968. A graduate student doing some
ordinary measurements of radio stars has come
across a phenomenon that is truly extraordinary.
A star is blinking on and off ten times per
second. How could this be? How could a star turn
its radio emissions on and off so rapidly? In any
star there exists a fire of incredible
temperature - hotter than the largest furnace on
earth. How could it turn on, then off, over and
over again? - Astronomers all over the world begin to look for
other pulsars, and sure enough, such objects
are everywhere in the skies All, however, can
only be detected by their radio waves Would
anyone locate a pulsar which emitted so much
energy that it could be observed with ordinary
light? Some of the most famous astronomers
enter the race, equipped with the world's largest
telescopes. The winners, however, are two unknown
young scientists who had only recently met.
Whats more, they had never before operated a
telescope. The American Institute of Physics
http//www.aip.org/history/mod/pulsar/pulsar1/01.h
tml - So how did Cocke and Disney come to know pulsar
NP 0532?
28Optical Discovery of Pulsar NP 0532
- Studying the nights work
- Garfinkel, Livingston and Lynch got their hands
on audio tape recordings of the nights work from
the American Institute of Physics - They examined the tapes to see how Cocke and
Disneys observations were shaped over the night
in their work together and in the company of
another astronomer, Bob McCallister - Harold Garfinkel, Eric Livingston and Mike Lynch
The work of a discovering science construed with
materials from the optically discovered pulsar,
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, vol. 11, pp.
131-158, 1981. - Having examined the tapes they focused
particularly on how the astronomers work evolved
from identifying a vague object-of-sorts (which
had neither demonstrable sense nor concrete
astronomical reference in the first instance), to
identifying a transcendent Independent Galilean
Object (IGO) - a pulsar - available to the
scrutiny of the wider scientific community. - In details of the astronomers talk together, the
tapes documented an unfolding series of
observations or scientific episodes over the
course of which pulsar NP 0532 came into view.
How?
29Unpacking the Observations
- Examining account-able features
- Observation 18.
- McCallister Theres a nice dip on the side of
that sky. Im going to turn this thing the
oscilloscope down. - Disney Weve got a bleeding pulse here.
- Cocke Hey! Wow! You dont suppose thats really
it, do you? Cant be. - Disney Its right bang in the middle of the
period. Look, I mean right bang in the middle of
the scale on the screen. It really looks like
something from here to at the moment to me. - Cocke Hmm.
- Disney And its growing too. I wont believe it
until we get a second one pulse. - Cocke I wont believe it until we get the
second one and until the thing has shifted
somewhere else on the horizontal axis of the
screen.
30Account-able Features of Obs. 18
- Working up a sense of the known object
- a nice dip on the side of that sky reveals a
pulse but it is not a given pulse, not a
practically observable and practically objective
pulse, but a dubitable pulse, one whose
facticity, which although suspected, is doubted
at this point in time. - The pulse represents a potential Independent
Galilean Object, which in the current flow of
their talk assumes the status of a vague
object-of-sorts an object whose facticity stands
in need of verification. - Consequently, Cocke and Disney formulate
technical conditions providing for the prima
facie facticity of the object to-hand. These
conditions include - 1) reproducing the Observation such that a
second pulse is detected, - and 2) looking for a shift in the objects
on-screen representation. - This latter condition is predicated on the
suspicion that the visibility of the object
right bang in the middle of the scale may be an
artefact of the technology a subsequent correct
reading should place the object elsewhere on the
screen.
31Verifying the Object
- Observation 19.
- Disney Beginning.
- Disney My God, its still there. Its as good
as it was, or better than it was last time. - Cocke It disturbs me, thats right in the
middle of the screen. - Disney It isnt John, look.
- Cocke Its moved a little bit.
- McCallister If you get the right frequency then
itll be more or less the same place, wouldnt
it? - Disney It should be more or less, you wont be
exactly the same place. - Disney Thats a bloody pulse isnt it.
- Cocke Lets move off that position and do
somewhere else and see if we get the same thing.
I hope to God this isnt some sort of artefact of
the instrumentation.
32Doing Verification Work
- Reproducing the observation, subject to emerging
contingencies - Condition 1 is readily satisfied in this
Observation, indeed its better than it was last
time. - The satisfaction of Condition 2 is still in
dispute, however. Although the on-screen
representation of the pulse has shifted a little,
it is not enough to determine whether or not the
pulse is some sort of artefact of the
instrumentation. - Judgements as to the facticity of the object
to-hand are suspended and a further technical
condition is formulated. - Condition 3 specifies moving the telescope (.25
of a millimetre northwards). - This positional check confirms that the equipment
is working properly and results, in the following
Observation, in the reproduction of the pulse and
a shift in its on-screen position corresponding
to the movement of the telescope - The readings have been verified to their
satisfaction and they conclude that a pulsar has
been observed.
33Formalising the Object
- Observation 22
- Disney We should be able to work out how many
photons coming in per second to this pulse,
right? - Cocke Well, we should be, yeah.
- Disney Can we get the actual number can we
read off digitally the number of photons in each
channel subsequent to this? - Cocke Oh yeah.
- Disney Now the fun begins, weve got to write
out some sort of programme to reduce this tape
and have the whole lot go in so - Cocke I dont think we need to reduce the damn
tape. - Disney No.
- Cocke We have wed have to reduce the tape
only if we saw nothing or just a bare little hint
of something.
34Making the Object Available
- Measurement
- Having established the facticity of the object,
the astronomers formulate ways in which the the
object may be found and verified by other members
of the astronomical community. - In order to achieve this, they examine their data
for its measurable properties (such as photons
per second). - With these exact measures, other astronomers
may reproduce the observation, and in the
technical ways of their discipline, see Pulsar NP
0532 for themselves. - The Crab Pulsar, discovered by radio
astronomers in November 1968, was seen to pulsate
in optical light in January 1969 (Cocke et al.
1969) by three groups within a matter of days.
Brian Kern (2002), PhD Thesis, Optical
Pulse-Phased Observations of Faint Pulsars with a
Phase-Binning CCD Camera
35The Knowing-Known Relationship
- Lived work
- Examining the accountable features of the nights
work revealed the lived work whereby Cocke and
Disney came to know pulsar NP 5302 - That work consisted of an unfolding series of
observations populated by a host of concerted
practical activities - The nights work was socially organized in terms
of configuring the equipment, doing verification
work (including reproducing observations subject
emergent contingencies), formalising the object,
and so on - It was through this unfolding, socially
organized, course of lived work that a vague
object-of-sorts came into view and was
transformed into a definite astronomical object
having properties that exist independent of the
people, the place and the equipment with which it
was discovered and which make it available to
others
36So What?
- The lived account and the formal account
- At no point in Cocke and Disneys account of NP
0532 does the lived work of the objects
production and recognition - its discovery -
figure - The lived work of the discovery - of how they
come to see and know NP 0532 - is completely
absent from their account (as it is absent from
scientific accounts generally) - The source of knowing - the lived work - is
entirely absent, yet it is through this work that
the relationship between knowing and known object
is given (and account-ably so) - The lived work is substituted for the formal
account and divorced from what Husserl called the
vital practices from which the possibility of
knowledge emerges - There is, then, what Garfinkel calls a gap in
the literature, not only of scientific practice,
but of everyday activities generally and it is
towards filling this gap that the radical studies
of work programme is directed
37Why Radical?
- Inverting the accounting relationship
- Suspending the use of formal methods to account
for everyday activities - And instead orienting to, focusing on, and
treating as a topic in their own right, the
vital practices organizing the lived work of a
setting as made available in members accounts - Natural organization instead of formal
organization then how things are organized on
the ground by parties to them (not dispensing
with the formal (e.g., method, procedure, rules,
etc.) but, where it is an issue, unpacking how
it is concertedly achieved - A note on vital practices and members methods
the two terms are different ways of speaking
about the same thing and that is the visibly and
materially embodied ways in which people concert
their everyday activities and get them done - There are other terms too work-practice is
very common these days and, a phrase that
propelled the radical studies of work programme,
the missing interactional what of formal
studies
38The Missing Interactional What
- The orientation of EM studies
- Harvey Sacks speaks of a curiosity in the work
and history of the social sciences the missing
interactional what in lay and professional
studies of organization. Several observable
phenomena make specific what he is talking about.
1) Available for observation is the omnipresence
of accountable organizations of commonplace
activities like families, faculties,
traffic, welfare agencies, hospitals,
manufacturing plants, city governments, or
street gangs. 2) It is a matter for observation
too that endlessly many inquiries accompany these
accountable organizations as constituent features
of them. It is to be observed in these
accountable organizations and their inquiries
that the occasioned, embodied, interactional
just-so just-what of ordinary activities remains
ignored, unknown, unsuspected, and unmissed as
technical phenomena. 3) Finally, there is to be
observed that 1) and 2) taken together compose a
technical phenomenon that is discoverable, is
consequential, and for the study of naturally
organized activities is criterial. The phenomenon
consists of the essential, used, and ignored
relevance to the collaborated production of the
orderliness in, of, and as ordinary activities,
of the occasioned, embodied, interactional
just-so-and-just-what of ordinary activities.
Harold Garfinkel, unpublished manuscript
39Working the Orientation
- Studying and representing naturally organized
activities - Focus on lived work as articulated in members
accounts, or shopwork and shoptalk as
Garfinkel puts it - Harold Garfinkel Ethnomethodologys program,
Social Psychology Quarterly, vol. 59 (1), pp.
5-21, 1996. - Examine shopwork and shoptalk to identify its
endogenous socially organized features - i.e.,
the organizational features that are internal to
and exhibited by that shopwork and shoptalk
(e.g., configuring the equipment, doing
verification, and formalising objects in
astronomical work) - Representing the social organization of everyday
activities in terms of their witnessable
haecceities - i.e., the specific details of
everyday activities that make them the activities
that they recognizably are - So, not just doing verification, for example,
but doing verification by formulating
verification conditions, reproducing the
observation in accordance with those conditions,
and formulating further verification conditions
to rule in or out artefacts of the technology - Through description of haecceities EM seeks to
exhibit the ways in which everyday activities are
naturally organized by parties to them
40Exhibiting Social Organization
- Durkheims social facts
- Social structures that exist above and beyond
the individual and shape his or her everyday
activities (IGOs) - These structures of action are formally specified
in the social sciences (e.g., Marxs model of
capital, Webers bureaucratic model, Parsons
social system, and more recently, actor-network
theory) - Formal studies seek to explain social facts but
not do not show how they come into existence as
lived features of members everyday activities,
recognized, produced and shaped by them in their
work together - Distinctively, EM does not attempt to explain
Durkheimanian social facts, but to show or
exhibit them as and in details of their
concerted, real world, real time achievement - EM studies do NOT correspond to Durkheims
social facts. Nor do they copy Durkheims social
facts. Nor do they imitate, represent, write in
place of, offer as a plan, schema, essence, or
model for Durkheims social facts. Instead they
exhibit Durkheims social facts Described
from the bottom up each study specifies the
particular social facts identifying orderliness - Harold Garfinkel Autochthonous order
properties of formatted queues,
Ethnomethodologys Program Working Out
Durkheims Aphorism, Rowman Littlefield,
2002.istinctive constituents
41Generalizing Exhibits
- EM doesnt
- Generalization is part of the formal social
science machinery that EM eschews - Generalization begs the question of validity,
which EM addresses not by formalising its
findings (through quantitative methods, for
example), but by the availability of its studies
to members - EM studies are corrigible sketches of social
organization, and may as such, be agreed with or
contested by members (Garfinkel and Wieder 1992) - EM studies are also studies of situated action
and do not set out to make claims about the
society at large (so again, we have no work for
generalization to do) - That is not to say that there is no ubiquity to
EM studies, that EM is micro social science -
e.g., CA and the turn-taking machine
42Other Ubiquitous Settings
- Understanding work, organization and technology
- Propelled by early studies (e.g., of the nature
of rules and procedures in organizations) - Egon Bittner The concept of organization,
Social Research, vol. 32, pp. 239-255, 1965. - Don Zimmerman The practicalities of rule use,
Understanding Everyday Life Toward the
Reconstruction of Sociological Knowledge (ed.
Douglas, J.D.), pp. 221-238, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1973. - Lead to adoption of EM in industrial IT research
labs (Xerox, Intel, Microsoft and many other
companies besides) - Lucy Suchman Plans and Situated Actions The
Problem of Human-Machine Communication, Cambridge
University Press, 1987. - Graham Button (ed.) Technology in Working Order
Studies of Work, Interaction, and Technology,
Routledge, 1992. - Instrumental in development of Computer Supported
Cooperative Work - See the Association of Computing Machinerys
digital library http//portal.acm.org - Now a diverse field of study both in terms of IT
research and the new domains that computing is
moving into (domestic life, health, science,
education, etc.) - Driven by the need to understand how people
actually work together and organize everyday
activities in diverse settings
43A Final Word Either/Or?
- The law of the excluded middle
- With its rejection of formal machinery at all
points, EM is often construed as being
antithetical to formal social science research - And ethnomethodology certainly provides the
grounds for making a sustained critique, one
which sets up an either/or choice - While it is true that you cannot do EM studies
through formal means without losing EMs prize,
that does not mean that FA and EM need be at
loggerheads - Rather than see EM as competing with FA, it might
be more profitable to see EM as complementary to
FA - EM will always be alternate an incommensurable as
a research approach, but in exhibiting social
facts EM provides insights that FA cannot and
never will be able to (and, of course, the
inverse is true) - The only choice to be made is whether or not to
repair the gap in the literature and extend
social science knowledge of everyday life
44-
- A copy of this presentation, including
references, is available online _at_ - www.mrl.nott.ac.uk/axc/EM_presentation.pdf