Rational Engagement, Emotional Response, - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 54
About This Presentation
Title:

Rational Engagement, Emotional Response,

Description:

Rational Engagement, Emotional Response, & the Prospects for Moral Progress in Animal Use Debates Ethicists have increasingly turned their attention to moral ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:222
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 55
Provided by: DanielS178
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Rational Engagement, Emotional Response,


1
Rational Engagement, Emotional Response, the
Prospects for Moral Progress in Animal Use
Debates
  • Ethicists have increasingly turned their
    attention to moral questions about the treatment
    of non-human animals. Arguments from a range of
    perspectives have been given for the conclusion
    that routine uses of animals in agriculture, the
    fashion industry, and experimentation are morally
    wrong.
  • Defenses of these practices, however, have been
    far fewer, and generally less developed, than the
    cases in favor of animals.
  • My aim in this presentation is to encourage
    development of stronger arguments in favor of
    animal use and provide methodological guidance on
    how to do so.
  • Nathan Nobis For Animal Research in Theory
    Practice,
  • ed. Jeremy Garrett, Rice, Philosophy

2
Harms Moral Justification
  • Many fields and occupations involve harming
    animals, making them worse off.
  • Animals for our purposes, mammals birds
    least controversial cases for discussion.
  • Typically, people in these fields will agree that
    animals are being harmed.
  • They claim, however, that these harms are morally
    justified not all harms are wrong, and these
    harms arent wrong (indeed, perhaps some are
    morally obligatory).

3
Common experimental procedures include
  • drowning,
  • suffocating,
  • starving,
  • burning,
  • blinding,
  • destroying their ability to hear,
  • damaging their brains,
  • severing their limbs,
  • crushing their organs
  • inducing
  • heart attacks,
  • cancers
  • ulcers
  • paralysis,
  • Seizures
  • forcing them to inhale tobacco smoke, drink
    alcohol, and ingest various drugs, such as
    heroine and cocaine.

4
A few commonly overlooked observations about harm
  • (1) Painless killing can be (and often is)
    harmful for the one who is killed it is bad for
    him/her.
  • Why? They are deprived of whatever goods they
    would have experienced. No interests can be
    satisfied.
  • Thus, the common if painlessly killed, then
    humane, so nothing morally objectionable views
    need defense.
  • (2) Recent ethological research shows that just
    being in a laboratory, and undergoing routine
    procedures, is stressful (and thus harmful) for
    animals.

5
Balcombe JP, Barnard ND, Sandusky C, Laboratory
routines cause animal stress, Contemporary
Topics in Laboratory Animal Science, 2004, Nov,
43 (6)42-51
  • Abstract Eighty published studies were appraised
    to document the potential stress associated with
    three routine laboratory procedures commonly
    performed on animals handling, blood collection,
    and orogastric gavage . . .
  • Significant changes in physiologic parameters
    correlated with stress . . were associated with
    all three procedures in multiple species in the
    studies we examined.
  • The results of these studies demonstrated that
    animals responded with rapid, pronounced, and
    statistically significant elevations in
    stress-related responses for each of the
    procedures . . .
  • We interpret these findings to indicate that
    laboratory routines are associated with stress,
    and that animals do not readily habituate to
    them. The data suggest that significant fear,
    stress, and possibly distress are predictable
    consequences of routine laboratory procedures,
    and that these phenomena have substantial
    scientific and humane implications for the use of
    animals in laboratory research.

6
Balcombe JP, Laboratory environments and
rodents behavioural needs A review, Laboratory
Animals (in press)
  • Abstract Laboratory housing conditions have
    significant physiological and psychological
    effects on rodents, raising both scientific and
    humane concerns.  Published studies of rats, mice
    and other rodents were reviewed to document
    behavioural and psychological problems
    attributable to predominant laboratory housing
    conditions.
  • Studies indicate that rats and mice value
    opportunities to take cover, build nests,
    explore, gain social contact, and exercise some
    control over their social milieu, and that the
    inability to satisfy these needs is physically
    and psychologically detrimental, leading to
    impaired brain development and behavioural
    anomalies (e.g., stereotypies). To the extent
    that space is a means to gain access to such
    resources, spatial confinement likely exacerbates
    these deficits. Adding environmental
    enrichments to small cages reduces but does not
    eliminate these problems, and I argue that
    substantial changes in housing and husbandry
    conditions would be needed to further reduce them.

7
Many ethicists have argued that its wrong to use
animals these ways theyve given reasons for
their views and defended them
  • utilitarianism and other consequentialisms,
  • rights-based deontologies,
  • ideal contractarianisms (veil of ignorance,
    Golden rule ethics),
  • virtue ethics,
  • common-sense (least harm, needless harm)
    moralities,
  • religious moralities, feminist ethics,
  • and more indeed almost every major, influential
    perspective in moral theory.

8
Even Kants, Rawls, and other moral theories
have been modified to be friendly to non-rational
moral patients (not moral agents)
  • Improve the theory so there are direct duties to
    baby ( other non-rational powerless humans
    shes of moral value not because others care
    about her, despite her not being a
    moral agent, rational, etc.

9
If the theory is now not Bad for Baby (and other
vulnerable humans), it is now not Bad for
Animals?
10
Thus, an abundance of ethical resources in
defense of animals.
  • However, this hasnt made much of a difference in
    thought or deed regarding uses of animals.
  • Possible explanations
  • big changes are always slow trickle-down is
    slow
  • philosophers (and other thinkers and authors)
    typically just arent very influential,
  • personal, financial, legal, political,
    institutional barriers to doing the right thing,
  • ???

11
A competing explanation
  • There are strong arguments that morally justify
    (much of) the current treatment of animals.
  • Since these arguments are strong / sound / very
    reasonable to accept, the defenses of animals are
    weak / unsound / unreasonable.
  • Im going to suggest that this explanation is
    unlikely, because these arguments are weak.
  • I encourage development of more and stronger
    arguments in favor of, defending, animal use and
    provide methodological guidance on doing so.

12
Emotional responses to moral issues
  • It sometimes appears that the quality of our
    thought on a topic is inversely proportional to
    the intensity of our emotions concerning that
    topic.
  • -- Fred Feldman, Confrontations With the Reaper
    A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of
    Death (Oxford, 1994).

13
Rational engagement of moral issues
  • Identify some past instances of moral progress
    in thought, attitude, deed
  • Hopefully, rational evaluation of arguments
    contributed to this, somewhat!
  • We can identify some basic logical skills that
    can help us improve the quality of our thought.
  • Apply these skills to some recent arguments
    made by scientists and philosophers regarding
    animals.
  • This is important because it seems that not
    enough people consistently use these skills this
    is not good.

14
Formerly controversial issues and simple
arguments
  • Women shouldnt be allowed to go to university
    because women are so emotional that abstract
    thought is so difficult for them.
  • "Slavery is morally right because we slave-owners
    benefit greatly from slavery."
  • "Since animals are not rational, it's morally ok
    to raise them to be killed and eaten."
  • These are arguments what are their faults?

15
Women (1)
  • Conclusion
  • Women shouldnt be allowed to go to university.
  • Why think that?
  • Women are such emotional beings that abstract
    thought is difficult for them.
  • Imprecise! SOME? or ALL?
  • Some women are so emotional that abstract
    thought is difficult. True, and true for some
    men!
  • All women are so emotional False,
    empirically indefensible claim, so unsound
    argument

16
Women (2)
  • Some women are so emotional that abstract
    thought is difficult. True, and true for some
    men!
  • Therefore, no women should be allowed to go to
    university.
  • But how do you get from (1) to (2)? Whats the
    missing linking premise?
  • A question How would some womens emotionality
    justify restricting educational opportunities
    from all women? Not clear.

17
Women (3)
  • However, even if some or even all women are so
    emotional and have difficulty with abstract
    thought why would that justify denying any women
    the opportunity to improve themselves through
    education?
  • If my cup won't hold but a pint, and yours holds
    a quart, wouldn't you be mean not to let me have
    my little half measure full?
  • Sojourner Truth, Ain't I A Woman? 1851

18
Slavery
  • "Slavery is morally right because we slave-owners
    benefit greatly from slavery.
  • (1) Slave-owners benefit from slavery. True
  • (C) Therefore, slavery is morally right. ?
  • --------------------------------------------------
    ------------
  • How do you get from (1) to (2)?
  • Whats the missing, assumed linking premise?
  • Slave-owners benefit from slavery. True
  • If some group benefits from some arrangement,
    then that arrangement is right. ?
  • Therefore, slavery is morally right.

19
Animals
  • "Since animals are not rational, it's morally ok
    to raise them to be killed and eaten.
  • Animals are not rational.
  • Therefore, its OK to kill them
  • Observations and questions
  • (1) is imprecise some, or all, animals are not
    rational? Which animals?
  • Ambiguity, lack of clarity what is meant by
    rational?
  • Missing-link premise needed to make argument
    logically valid If a being is not rational,
    then its ok to kill it. False?

20
Logical skills The (moral) value of basic
predicate logic
  • Attending to the intended meanings of unclear or
    ambiguous words
  • what do you mean?
  • animal, human, being human, human being,
    person, human person, humanity
  • Precision regarding , quantity some, all?
  • Assumed, unstated premises that link stated
    reason(s) to conclusion. (Logical validity).

21
It seems these logical skills are generally
useful.
  • A bioethicist disagrees about the value of these
    skills for professional ethics
  • Frankly, science students would have very little
    patience for the abstract argumentation and
    reasoning that one finds in your paper and is
    standard fare in philosophy journals.

22
Apply these ( other) logical skills to some
recent arguments
  • Scientists
  • Stuart Derbyshire, Ph.D., U Birmingham UK (used
    to be at Pitt) pain researcher.
  • Mark Mattfield, Ph.D., Research Defense Society,
    UK
  • Colin Blakemore, Ph.D., Medical Research Council,
    UK
  • Adrian Morrison, Ph.D., DVM, U Penn, sleep
    disorders
  • Philosophers
  • Carl Cohen
  • Neil Levy, Cohen Kinds A Response to Nathan
    Nobis, JoAP)
  • Tibor Machan, Putting Humans First
  • Matthew Liao, Virtually All Human Beings as
    Rightholders A Non-Speciesist Approach

23
The issue neednt be whether animals have
rights
  • Moral or legal rights?
  • Which moral rights? (be specific)
  • Rights conflicts right to smoke, right to
    a smoke-free environment
  • Rights appeals can conceal details.
  • Common invalid argument
  • If animals have rights, then serious change is
    needed. But they dont have rights, so change
    isnt needed.
  • Logically invalid conclusion doesnt follow
    and avoids the concrete questions.

24
The issue neednt be whether animals have
rights
  • Better to consider
  • (1) whether various (specific) uses of animals
    are morally permissible or not, whether any ways
    of treatment are morally obligatory and
  • (2) why or why not.
  • Keep this the focus on these deontic categories
    is helpful for many practical and theoretical
    reasons.

25
The issue also neednt be whether animals are
equal to humans
  • Are any animals equal to humans? Are all humans
    equal? Hard to answer
  • What is meant by equal? Not obvious.
  • Which humans, which animals? (What is meant by
    humans and animals?). (fetus, baby, adult,
    100 y/o?)
  • Common invalid argument avoids the concrete
    questions.
  • If animals are equal to humans, then serious
    change is needed. But they arent equal, so
    change isnt needed.
  • Equal consid. vs.No consid.vs. mid-level
    consid?
  • Again, ideal Qs are about moral permissibility.

26
Objection An abundance of resources is a
philosophical embarrassment?
  • Many philosophers argue that animals are treated
    wrongly, but disagree on why (e.g., Peter Singer
    demolishes Tom Regan and Regan demolishes
    Singer). Therefore, there is no justification for
    thinking that animals are treated wrongly.
  • Adrian Morrison Richard Vance, JAMA

27
A parallel argument
  • Many thinkers argue that animals are not treated
    wrongly, but disagree on why (e.g., Carl Cohen
    demolishes Jan Narveson Narveson demolishes
    Cohen). Therefore, there is no justification for
    thinking that animals are not treated wrongly.

28
The false, unstated assumption
  • If you believe p, and for reasons X, Y, Z, but
    others believe p for reasons A, B, C, etc. and
    these reasons are logically incompatible (and you
    recognize this), then either you have no (good)
    reason to believe p or there is no good reason to
    believe p.
  • At the very least, this principle isnt one
    typically accepted or universally applied (e.g.,
    global warming is bad).

29
Appeals to evolution / biological perspectives
  • Morrison to refrain from exploring nature in
    every possible way would be an arrogant rejection
    of evolutionary forces.
  • Evolution has endowed us with a need to know as
    much as we can. (Nicoll, Russell).
  • Humans evolved therefore, morally we should .
    Does not follow.
  • Constraints on using other humans to advance our
    own genetic line, when its in our interest?

30
Benefits Arguments / Arguments from Necessity
  • animal experiments are vital to the future
    well-being of humans and, as long as they are
    conducted to high ethical standards, they are
    entirely justifiable. Mark Matfield
  • The argument Benefits for humans justify animal
    experimentation (and other uses)
  • The are necessary.

31
Is animal use necessary? (1)
  • Depends on what you mean by necessary.
  • In one sense, yes!
  • To do animal experiments, it is necessary to do
    animal experiments. To make these exact
    scientific discoveries using animals, it is
    essential to use animals if animals werent
    used, the experiments would be different.

32
Is animal use necessary? (2)
  • In other senses, perhaps not. Is animal necessary
    for making medical progress and for, more
    generally, bettering human welfare?
  • Necessary for the well-being of humans, but
    which humans? A few? (Maybe!). Everyone? Doubtful
    that every human benefits from (every) animal
    experiment.
  • There are other ways of bringing about goods for
    humans
  • clinical research, epidemiology, in vitro
    research, uses of technology, autopsies,
    prevention, etc.
  • feeding people, getting existing medical care to
    them, etc.. Its been argued that these would
    yield greater human utility.

33
Defenses of the low (human) utility of animal
experimentation
  • RC Greek N Shanks, Animal Research in Light of
    Science (2006? Rodopi)
  • N Shanks LaFollette, Brute Science (Routledge
    1997)
  • RC Greek J Greek DVM, Sacred Cows Golden
    Geese (Continuum 2000), Specious Science (2002),
    What Will We Do if We Dont Experiment on
    Animals? (2004)
  • They argue that other methods of research are
    more effective at addressing human needs.

34
Benefits argument
  • Animal experiment yields some benefits.
  • If some action benefits someone (or some group),
    then that action is right. false needs
    refinement and serious defense
  • Therefore, animal experimentation (and other
    uses) are right.
  • What about direct harms (to animals, to humans,
    esp. indirect harms from opportunity costs)? How
    are these weighed? A careful methodology would be
    nice, at least is necessary for serious defense.

35
Want benefits?
  • Whatever benefits animal experimentation is
    thought to hold in store for us, those very same
    benefits could be obtained through experimenting
    on humans esp. vulnerable ones instead of
    animals. Indeed, given that problems exist
    because scientists must extrapolate from animal
    models to humans, one might think there are good
    scientific reasons for preferring human
    subjects.
  • Philosopher Ray Frey

36
Why not use these humans?Blakemores answer
  • The only firm line to make moral distinctions
    on genetic and morphological grounds is between
    our own species and other species.
  • Suggested if something is of our species, then
    it is more morally valuable than any animals.
  • But he says a human embryo, certainly before the
    nervous system begins to develop, is just a
    bundle of cells.
  • Suggested being of our species does not
    necessarily confer moral value.
  • We should have a special attitude toward other
    humans, so crucial to this argument is how we
    define a person. He did not do this.

37
Why not use these humans?Derbyshires answer
  • Animals lack the capacity for reflection (and
    therefore an inner world) and the capacity for
    reasoning (So do many humans!!)
  • Its remarkable that we have to consider the
    question.
  • Not remarkable if someone suggests that whats
    required for a presumption against harm are
    properties that many, many human beings lack.
  • Society cares about vulnerable humans.
  • All of them? What about secret experiments? What
    if they could be re-educated? Why do they care?
    (Harms)

38
Avoiding objections from non-rational human
beings.
  • A common claim
  • Its wrong to seriously harm a being only if that
    being is rational, autonomous, makes moral
    choices, is creative, intelligent, contributes to
    society, etc.
  • OK, animals arent like that, but neither are
    lots of (conscious, feeling) humans. This
    principle suggests its not seriously wrong to
    harm them. Is this principle correct?

39
Some odd inferencesCohen, Levy Kinds
  • Cohen NEJM Moral rights depend on moral
    agency, the ability to respond to moral claims.
    A being has rights only if its a of a kind
    characterized by moral agency.
  • Finnis to be a person is to belong to a kind of
    being characterized by rational (self-conscious,
    intelligent) nature.
  • Scanlon the class of beings whom it is possible
    to wrong will include at least all those beings
    who are of a kind that is normally capable of
    judgment-sensitive attitudes.

40
Cohen, Levy Kinds
  • Cohen All humans are of a kind capable of moral
    agency, but
  • animals are not beings of a kind capable of
    exercising or responding to moral claims. Animals
    therefore have no rights, and they can have
    none.
  • What kind are animals? How are humans who are not
    moral agents of the kind moral agent? Cohen
    doesnt explain.

41
Cohens possible answer?
  • Humans who are non-moral agents are of this kind
    because they are members of a set e.g., the
    kind, a species some of which are moral agents.
  • Response But animals are also members of a set
    e.g., the kind, sentient beings some of whom
    are moral agents also! They have rights too, on
    Cohens account!
  • Humans and animals are of many kinds, some
    overlapping, some not. Inconsistent conclusions
    follow from Cohen-esque reasoning.

42
Levys attempt to find the right kind the
narrowest natural kind
  • If (1) an individual A is a member of some
    species S and (2) some, most or all of the other
    members of that species have some property C and
    (3), on the basis of having property C, they have
    moral property R, then individual A has moral
    property R as well, even though A lacks property
    C.

43
If (1) an individual A is a member of some
species S and (2) some, most or all of the other
members of that species have some property C and
(3), on the basis of having property C, they have
moral property R, then individual A has moral
property R as well, even though A lacks property
C.
  • C non-moral property of "having doneno serious
    crimes
  • R "not deserving lifeimprisonment."
  • Implications for lone criminal?
  • C "intelligent" and "aware
  • R "being such that one ought to be allowed to
    make decisions to direct one's own life."
  • Implications for young children and others?

44
Machans Arguments from Whats Normal
  • A being has moral rights (presumably making it
    wrong to harm it) only if it a moral nature, a
    capacity to see the difference between right
    and wrong and choose accordingly.
  • It is this moral capacity that establishes a
    basis for rights, not the fact that animals, like
    us, have interests or can feel pain.
  • Humans are of the kind of being that have such
    a moral nature and animals are not thus humans
    have rights and animals do not.

45
What about humans who seem to lack this moral
capacity?
  • We must consider humans as they exist normally,
    not abnormally and focus on the healthy cases,
    not the special or exceptional or borderline
    ones.
  • We do need to deal with borderline cases. But we
    can do so only by applying and adapting the
    knowledge we acquire from the normal case. We
    cant start with the exception and infer the
    rule.

46
The suggested argument
  • Humans who lack moral capacities are human.T!
  • If someone is human, then they have all the
    (moral) properties that normal, healthy,
    typical humans have.
  • Therefore, these humans have moral capacities,
    and so they have rights.
  • Reply 2 is, at least, unsupported, and is an
    instance of a generally false principle for moral
    non-moral properties. (e.g., 4 limbs Ted Bundy)

47
Matthew Liao, Virtually All Human Beings as
Rightholders The Species-Norm Account
  • to be a rightholder (a being with the highest
    moral status), something need not
  • be a moral agent
  • have the potential to be a moral agent
  • be of the kind (species) that normally is a moral
    agent
  • be actually sentient, conscious, etc. or even
    have the potential, i.e., that its possible in
    some sense
  • Could be tinkered into a pro-animal exper. view.

48
The correct answer is
  • A being has rights iff the entity has
    incorporated into it the genetic basis for the
    species capacity for moral agency (i.e. the
    relevant bits of DNA that normally allow for
    moral agency) or the functional equivalent
    thereof (e.g. software and/or hardware that would
    normally allow for moral agency in an artificial
    being). The intrinsic value that resides in the
    relevant genetic bits grounds rightholding even
    when that genetic material is blocked from
    developing and cannot allow for moral agency.
  • If X is like that, then X has moral rights.

49
Liaos reasoning in favor of the view, it seems
  1. There are moral duties only if there are moral
    agents. T
  2. There are moral agents only if there are beings
    with the genetic basis for moral agency. OK
    accept this for sake of argument
  3. Therefore, there are moral duties only if there
    are beings with the genetic basis for moral
    agency.
  4. Therefore (?), any being with the genetic basis
    for moral agency is a rightholder.

50
A parallel argument
  1. There are moral duties only if there are living
    beings, or beings that can perceive, or . T
  2. There are living beings, or beings that can
    perceive only if there are beings with the
    genetic basis for life, perception, etc. OK
  3. Therefore, there are moral duties only if there
    are beings with the genetic basis for life,
    perception, etc.
  4. Therefore (?), any being with the genetic basis
    for life, perception, is a rightholder.

51
Objections from Chris Grau, FIU
  • If the species-norm account is true, then
  • A cabbage that has "integrated" the relevant
    genetic bits but is damaged such that the
    capacity for moral agency is permanently blocked.
    (this cabbage has rights even though it lacks
    moral agency and the potential for it.)
  • A (future) computer with the relevant hardware.
    software "integrated" but blocked. This computer
    has rights even though it would lack both moral
    agency and the potential for moral agency.
  • Cabbage or computer vs. sentient animals and
    sentient humans lacking the relevant genetic
    material for moral agency?
  • The species norm account seems entirely ad hoc.

52
Conclusions / Summary
  • Presented a basic method for thinking about moral
    issues demonstrated its use applied it to some
    recent arguments defending current animal use
    and/or criticizing pro-animal arguments.
  • Suggested that these arguments are weak.
  • My hope since these methods are generally
    useful, perhaps future defenders of current uses
    of animals will utilize them for better
    arguments.
  • To make moral progress and contribute to
    reasonable debate it is important that this is
    done.

53
For an overview of the recent literature on
ethics and animals issues, see Angus Taylors
Ethics Animals An Overview of the
Philosophical Debate (Broadview, 2003). For
arguments from utilitarianism, see, among other
sources, Peter Singers Practical Ethics, 2nd
Edition (Cambridge UP, 1993) and his Animal
Liberation, 3rd Edition (Harper, 2001) although
the former is, strictly speaking, not an argument
from utilitarianism. From rights-based
deontology, see, among other sources, Tom Regans
The Case for Animal Rights, 2nd Edition (U
California Press, 2004), as well as his more
accessible Empty Cages Facing the Challenge of
Animal Rights (Rowman Littlefield, 2004) for
Rawlsian-style ideal contractarianism, see among
other sources, Mark Rowlands Animals Like Us
(Verso, 2002) from virtue ethics, see among
other sources, Rosalind Hursthouses Ethics,
Humans and Other Animals (Routledge, 2000), from
common-sense morality, see, among other sources,
Mark Bernsteins Without a Tear Our Tragic
Relationship With Animals (U Illinois Press,
2004) and David DeGrazias Animal Rights A Very
Short Introduction (Oxford, 2002) for religious
moralities, see, among other sources, Matthew
Scullys Dominion The Power of Man, the
Suffering of Animals, and the Call to Mercy (St.
Martins, 2003) from feminism, see Carol Adams
and Josephine Donavan (eds.) Beyond Animal
Rights A Feminist Caring Ethic for the Treatment
of Animals (Continuum, 1996).
54
Stuart Derbyshire,an animal experimentation
advocate
  • It is not possible to advocate animal welfare
    and at the same time give animals untested drugs
    or diseases, or slice them open to test a new
    surgical procedure. . .
  • The Scientist, 3/06, Time to Abandon the Three
    Rs
  • Submitting to refinement, reduction, and
    replacement risks the future of animal research
  • Once the perspective of the animal is adopted,
    it is inevitable that all experimentation will be
    seen negatively, as no animal experiments are in
    the interest of the animal
  • - Why Animals Rights Are Wrong (p. 39)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com