Title: L4
1L4 The Schroedinger equation
- A particle of mass m on the x-axis is subject to
a force F(x, t) - The program of classical mechanics is to
determine the position of the particle at any
given time x(t). Once we know that, we can
figure out the velocity v dx/dt, the momentum p
mv, the kinetic energy T (1/2)mv2, or any
other dynamical variable of interest. - How to determine x(t) ? Newton's second law F
ma. - For conservative systems - the only kind that
occur at microscopic level - the force can be
expressed as the derivative of a potential energy
function, F -dV/ dx, and Newton's law reads m
d2x/dt2 -dV/ dx - This, together with appropriate initial
conditions (typically the position and velocity
at t 0), determines x(t).
2- A particle of mass m, moving along the x axis, is
subject to a force - F(x, t) -dV/ dx
- Quantum mechanics approaches this same problem
quite differently. In this case what we're
looking for is the wave function, Y (x, t), of
the particle, and we get it by solving the
Schroedinger equation - In 3 dimensions,
? 10-34 Js
3The statistical interpretation
- What is this "wave function", and what can it
tell you? After all, a particle, by its nature,
is localized at a point, whereas the wave
function is spread out in space (it's a function
of x, for any given time t). How can such an
object be said to describe the state of a
particle? - Born's statistical interpretation
-
-
- Quite likely to find the particle near A, and
relatively unlikely near B. - The statistical interpretation introduces a kind
of indeterminacy into quantum mechanics, for even
if you know everything the theory has to tell you
about the particle (its wave function), you
cannot predict with certainty the outcome of a
simple experiment to measure its position - all quantum mechanics gives is statistical
information about the possible results - This indeterminacy has been profoundly disturbing
4Realism, ortodoxy, agnosticism - 1
- Suppose I measure the position of the particle,
and I find C. Question Where was the particle
just before I made the measurement? - There seem to be three plausible answers to this
question - 1. The realist position The particle was at C.
This seems a sensible response, and it is the one
Einstein advocated. However, if this is true QM
is an incomplete theory, since the particle
really was at C, and yet QM was unable to tell us
so. The position of the particle was never
indeterminate, but was merely unknown to the
experimenter. Evidently Y is not the whole story
some additional information (a hidden variable)
is needed to provide a complete description of
the particle
5Realism, ortodoxy, agnosticism - 2
- Suppose I measure the position of the particle,
and I find C. Question Where was the particle
just before I made the measurement? - 2. The orthodox position The particle wasn't
really anywhere. It was the act of measurement
that forced the particle to "take a stand.
Observations not only disturb what is to be
measured, they produce it .... We compel the
particle to assume a definite position. This view
(the so-called Copenhagen interpretation) is
associated with Bohr and his followers. Among
physicists it has always been the most widely
accepted position. Note, however, that if it is
correct there is something very peculiar about
the act of measurement - something that over half
a century of debate has done precious little to
illuminate.
6Realism, ortodoxy, agnosticism - 3
- Suppose I measure the position of the particle,
and I find C. Question Where was the particle
just before I made the measurement? - 3. The agnostic position Refuse to answer. This
is not as silly as it sounds - after all, what
sense can there be in making assertions about the
status of a particle before a measurement, when
the only way of knowing whether you were right is
precisely to conduct a measurement, in which case
what you get is no longer "before the
measurement"? It is metaphysics to worry about
something that cannot, by its nature, be tested.
One should not think about the problem of whether
something one cannot know anything about exists
7Realism, ortodoxy, or agnosticism?
- Suppose I measure the position of the particle,
and I find C. Question Where was the particle
just before I made the measurement? - Until recently, all three positions had their
partisans. But in 1964 John Bell demonstrated
that it makes an observable difference if the
particle had a precise (though unknown) position
prior to the measurement. Bell's theorem made it
an experimental question whether 1 or 2 is
correct. The experiments have confirmed the
orthodox interpretation a particle does not have
a precise position prior to measurement it is
the measurement that insists on one particular
number, and in a sense creates the specific
result, statistically guided by the wave
function. - Still some agnosticism is tolerated
8Collapse of the wavefunction
- Suppose I measure the position of the particle,
and I find C. Question Where will be the
particle immediately after? - Of course in C. How does the orthodox
interpretation explain that the second
measurement is bound to give the value C?
Evidently the first measurement radically alters
the wave function, so that it is now sharply
peaked about C. The wave function collapses upon
measurement (but soon spreads out again,
following the Schroedinger equation, so the
second measurement must be made quickly). There
are, then, two entirely distinct kinds of
physical processes "ordinary", in which Y
evolves under the Schroedinger equation, and
"measurements", in which Y suddenly collapses.
9Normalization
- Y (x, t)2 is the probability density for
finding the particle at point x at time t. - The integral of Y (x, t)2 over space must be
1 (the particle has to be somewhere). - The wave function is supposed to be determined by
the Schroedinger equation--we can't impose an
extraneous condition on Y without checking that
the two are consistent. - Fortunately, the Schroedinger equation is linear
if Y is a solution, so too is A Y , where A is
any (complex) constant. What we must do, then, is
pick this undetermined multiplicative factor so
that The integral of Y (x, t)2 over space must
be 1 This process is called normalizing the wave
function. - Physically realizable states correspond to the
"square-integrable" solutions to Schroedinger's
equation.
10Will a normalized function stay as such?
11Expectation values
- For a particle in state Y, the expectation value
of x is - It does not mean that if you measure the position
of one particle over and over again, this is the
average of the results - On the contrary, the first measurement (whose
outcome is indeterminate) will collapse the wave
function to a spike at the value obtained, and
the subsequent measurements (if they're performed
quickly) will simply repeat that same result. - Rather, ltxgt is the average of measurements
performed on particles all in the state Y, which
means that either you must find some way of
returning the particle to its original state
after each measurement, or you prepare an
ensemble of particles, each in the same state Y,
and measure the positions of all of them ltxgt is
the average of them.
12Momentum
13More on operators
- One could also simply observe that Schroedingers
equations works as if - (exercise apply on the plane wave). In 3
dimensions,
Compound operators
14Angular momentum
15The uncertainty principle (qualitative)
x(m)
- Imagine that you're holding one end of a long
rope, and you generate a wave by shaking it up
and down rhythmically. - Where is that wave? Nowhere, precisely - spread
out over 50 m or so. - What is its wavelength? It looks like 6 m
- By contrast, if you gave the rope a sudden jerk
you'd get a relatively narrow bump traveling down
the line. This time the first question (Where
precisely is the wave?) is a sensible one, and
the second (What is its wavelength?) seems
difficult - it isn't even vaguely periodic, so
how can you assign a wavelength to it?
x(m)
16The uncertainty principle (qualitative, II)
x(m)
x(m)
- The more precise a wave's x is, the less precise
is l , and vice versa. A theorem in Fourier
analysis makes this rigorous - This applies to any wave, and in particular to
the QM wave function. l is related to p by the de
Broglie formula - Thus a spread in l corresponds to a spread in p,
and our observation says that the more precisely
determined a particle's position is, the less
precisely is p - This is Heisenberg's famous uncertainty
principle. (we'll prove it later, but I want to
anticipate it now)
17Exercise
- A particle is represented at t0 by the
wavefunction - Y (x, 0) A(a2-x2) x lt a (agt0).
- 0 elsewhere
- a Determine the normalization constant A
- b, c What is the expectation value for x and for
p at t0?
18Exercise (cont.)
- A particle is represented at t0 by the
wavefunction - Y (x, 0) A(a2-x2) x lt a (agt0).
- 0 elsewhere
- d, e Compute ltx2gt, ltp2gt
- f, g Compute the uncertainty on x, p
- h Verify the uncertainty principle in this case
19L5 The time-independent Schroedinger equation
- Supponiamo che il potenziale U sia indipendente
dal tempo
20(No Transcript)
21- y, soluzione della prima equazione (eq.agli
autovalori detta equazione di S. stazionaria), e
detta autofunzione
223 comments on the stationary solutions 1
- 1. They are stationary states. Although the wave
function itself - does (obviously) depend on t, the probability
density does not - the time dependence cancels
out. The same thing happens in calculating the
expectation value of any dynamical variable
233 comments on the stationary solutions 2
- 2. They are states of definite energy. In
mechanics, the total energy is called the
Hamiltonian - H(x, p) mv2/2 V(x).
- The corresponding Hamiltonian operator, obtained
by the substitution p -gt -i ? ?/ ?x, is -
243 comments on the stationary solutions 3
- 3. They are a basis. The general solution is a
linear combination of separable solutions. The
time-independent Schroedinger equation might
yield an infinite collection of solutions, each
with its associated value of the separation
constant thus there is a different wave function
for each allowed energy. - The S. equation is linear a linear combination
of solutions is itself a solution. - It so happens that every solution to the
(time-dependent) S. equation can be written as a
linear combination of stationary solutions. - To really play the game, mow we must input some
values for V
25The infinite square well
26Infinite square well, 2
27Infinite square well, 3
But
28Infinite square well, 4
29(No Transcript)
30Free particle (V0, everywhere)
31(however, for any finite volume V, however large,
y is normalizable)
32(No Transcript)
33- Let us assume that f(k) is narrowly peaked about
some particular value k0. Since the integrand is
negligible except in the vicinity of k0, we may
Taylor-expand the function w(k) about that point
and keep only the leading terms
34L6 - Gradino di potenziale
- E lt U0
- E gt U0
35a. E lt U0
36b. E gt U0
37Barriera di potenziale
38Finite squarewell
39(No Transcript)
40(No Transcript)
41(No Transcript)
42(No Transcript)
43L7 Loscillatore armonico 1-d
44(No Transcript)
45(No Transcript)
46Operatori di creazione e distruzione
47(No Transcript)