Title: Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative
1Jacques Louis David, The Oath of the Horatii, 1784
2Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
3KANT AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY
- Modern philosophy begins with René Descartes
(1596-1650). - However, Kant is regarded by many as the greatest
of all the modern philosophers. - Indeed, with Plato and Aristotle, Kant is often
considered to be one of the three greatest
philosophers. - Kant made great contributions in epistemology,
metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics. - The Critique of Pure Reason widely regarded as a
masterpiece, and the greatest single work in
philosophy since the Greeks, perhaps since
Aristotles Metaphysics.
4MAN, NATURE, AND RATIONALITY
- Kant notes that everything in nature works
according to laws. However, humans differ from
other parts of nature in that humans alone can
according to principles. - Thus, Kant recognizes the rationality of human
beings. - Humans are rational in having a conception of
laws, or principles. - Our rationality enables us to understand the
correctness of moral laws such as keep your
promises, and to know the difference between
right and wrong.
5FREE AGENCY
- Human beings are also free agents, that is, we
have free will, or can freely choose between
options, including moral options. That is, we
can freely choose to do right or wrong. - Because of our rationality, we can understand the
difference between right and wrong. And, because
of our rationality, we can understand moral laws
which it is our duty to accept as binding. - Our freedom to choose means then that we are
capable of freely acting on this knowledge. That
is we can freely choose to do what is proper.
6REASON AND AGENCY
- Knowing how to act morally requires reason. Thus
we must be able to deduce and understand the
principles of correct moral behavior. - Having understood what is the right thing to do,
we then act in a morally correct way when we
freely choose to act according to the moral law
which reason has recognized to be correct. - Kant calls our ability to act according to
principles, or our capacity to use our free will
to do the right thing, practical reason. - Thus, for Kant, the will puts to use or practice
the principles of reason insofar as they concern
moral behavior.
7RATIONALITY AND DESIRE
- Kant recognizes that people are not only rational
agents but we also have desires and appetites. - However, as a rational agent, a person can choose
to do what is right in spite of the influence of
desires and appetites. - When desires and appetites, or what Kant calls
subjective conditions, would lead a person not
to do the morally correct thing, or when morality
and desire conflict, the moral person acts
according to reason to do the right thing, in
spite of the influences of their desires and
appetites.
8MORAL WORTH
- For Kant, a person of moral worth does the right
thing, and does so in spite of the influence of
desire and appetite which may lead her to do the
wrong thing. - And, for Kant, moral worth is the most important
attribute which a person can have. - Moral worth is more important and more admirable
than such talents of the mind as intelligence,
wit, and judgment and is more important than
such qualities of temperament as courage,
resolution, and perseverance. - For Kant, these gifts of nature - intelligence,
courage, and so forth - may also become bad and
mischievous if the will which is to make use of
them is not good.
9GOOD WILL I
- As seen, Kant recognizes that such things as
intelligence and talent are good and valuable,
but he thinks that moral worth has absolute
value, and is more important than anything else
which we might admire in a person. - We have also seen that, for Kant, we are
obligated by reason to follow objective moral
laws even though we may not do so because of the
influence of subjective conditions, or desires
and appetites, on the will. - A persons will to do the right thing, the thing
which reason can identify as the morally correct
thing to do, is a good will, and one which does
not is not thoroughly good.
10GOOD WILL II
- A person of moral worth is a person of good will
in freely choosing to do the morally correct
thing whether or not she is under the influence
of desire to do otherwise. - And Kant says that Nothing can possibly be
conceived in the world, or even out of it, which
can be called good without qualification, except
a Good Will. - Again, things like intelligence, talent, courage,
and diligence are good, but if they are not
backed by good character or a good will, then
they can be put to bad use by a bad person. For
instance, Hitler.
11GOOD WILL III
- A good will is necessary to make sure that what
Kant calls gifts of fortune, such as wealth and
power, do not lead us astray as moral beings. - Even things which are thought to be good in many
respects, such as self-control and calm
deliberation, have no intrinsic unconditional
value, but always presuppose a good will. - Not only are such things not absolutely good, as
a good will is, but they can be put to bad use if
not backed by a good will. Thus we may admire
qualities such as self-control and calm
deliberation, but, if not backed by a good will
they may become extremely bad. For instance,
Kant says that the coolness of a villain makes
him far more dangerous than he would have been
had he lacked the self-control and calm
deliberation that coolness implies.
12GOOD WILL IV
- For Kant, a good will is not good because of what
it brings about or helps to bring about, but
because it is good in itself. - A good will, considered by itself as it is in
itself, is much more admirable than anything
which it brings about. - For instance, the good will which brings about
happiness is much more deserving of respect than
is the happiness which it produces.
13GOOD WILL V
- Even if a good will accomplishes nothing, it is
still to be admired as something which has its
whole value in itself. - So whether a good will is useful in producing
results or not, it is still of the utmost
goodness in itself. - The value of a good will then lies entirely in
itself and not in what it produces.
14GOOD WILL VI
- For Kant, a good will is good not because of
what it performs or effects, but is good in
itself. - Because the value of a good will lies entirely
within itself, it is still good whether it
results in anything which is either a good or a
bad effect of it. - The good will then has its whole value in
itself, and its usefulness or fruitlessness can
neither add to nor take away anything from this
value.
15MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES I
- Kant says that the moral worth of an action does
not lie in the effect expected from it, nor in
any principle of action which requires to borrow
its motive from this expected effect. - Thus, unlike any consequentialist theory, Kant
says that it is incorrect to look for the moral
worth of an action in its effects. - The reason for this is that expected effects of
actions, such as improving ones own condition,
as in egoism, or increasing the happiness of
everyone likely to be effected by the action, as
in utilitarianism, Kant says could have been
brought about by other causes. - And, if that were the case, then there would
have been no need of the will of a rational
being.
16MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES II
- Recall that, for Kant, it is in this will alone
that the supreme and unconditional good can be
found. - And if that is where the supreme and
unconditional good is to be found, then it is not
to be found in the consequences of an action,
whether those consequences mean a better life for
oneself, as in egoism, or in a better life for
everyone affected by the action, as in
utilitarianism. - To that end, Kant says The pre-eminent good
which we call moral can therefore consist in
nothing else than the conception of law in
itself, which certainly is possible only in a
rational being, in so far as this conception, and
not the expected effect, determines the will.
(His italics.)
17MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES III
- Thus, for Kant, the moral person does what is
right because it is right, and does not do right
because he or she is considering the likely
effects of doing right for himself or for anyone
likely to be effected by the action. - For Kant, the goodness of a good will is a good
which is already present in the person who acts
accordingly that is, a person who acts according
to moral law, and we have not to wait for it to
appear first in the result. - The goodness of an act is not then judged by its
consequences, as in a consequentialist theory,
but is due to a good will, or willing to do the
right thing because it is the right thing to do.
18MORAL MOTIVES
- For Kant it is the moral person who is to be
respected and revered. However, you are not an
intrinsically moral person if, although you do
the right thing, you do so for the wrong reason. - For instance, you may keep a promise, not ought
of knowing that it is the right thing to do, and
acting on that knowledge, but because you
perceive it to be to your benefit to do so. - A moral person is motivated to do the right thing
because he recognizes that it is the right thing
to do, and so acts out of principle.
19MORALITY IS UNIVERSAL
- According to Kant, you dont act correctly for a
subjective reason, such as pleasure or happiness,
if you are a moral person. Rather, you act out
of principle. - This means recognizing an objective right which
applies to everyone. - What is morally right for one person is morally
right for everyone, which is what is meant by
saying that morality is universal.
20DUTY I
- That morality is universal and objective, rather
than local, historical, and subjective, means
that every rational agent has an obligation to do
what is right. - Thus it is your duty to do what is morally right
as an objective matter. - Kants ethics is called deontological. The word
deontology comes from the Greek words deon for
duty and logos for science. Thus deontology
would be the science of duty.
21DUTY II
- A deontological theory of ethics stresses a
persons duty to do the morally correct thing
regardless of consequences. - For deontological ethics, some acts are morally
obligatory whether their consequences are good or
bad for human beings. - Because of lack of consideration of consequences,
a deontological theory is nonconsequentialist. - The deontologist will typically hold that his
moral standards are higher than those of the
consequentialist.
22IMPERATIVES
- An imperative is a command that I act in a
certain fashion. - Kant talks of two kinds of imperative, or two
kinds of command (of reason), namely,
hypothetical or categorical. - A hypothetical imperative concerns an action
which is good only as a means to something
else. (His italics.) A categorical imperative
concerns an action which is conceived of as good
in itself. (His italics.)
23HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVE I
- A hypothetical imperative is conditional.
- That is, it depends on certain things, and
concerns what needs to be done in order to attain
an objective. - An imperative (a command of reason to act in a
certain way) is hypothetical when it concerns an
action which is good only as a means to something
else.
24HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVE II
- For instance, if you want to begin collecting
art, then your ability to collect good art will
be dependent or conditional on your ability to
recognize good art. - It is therefore imperative that you learn
something about art so that you can tell the good
from the bad. And the hypothetical command of
reason in this case would be If you want to
build a good collection of art (the hypothetical)
then learn about art (the imperative). - Thus learning about art is good, but it is
hypothetical because it is a means to something
else, namely acquiring a good collection.
25CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE I
- Kant says that There is but one categorical
imperative, namely this Act only on that maxim
whereby thou canst at the same time will that it
should become a universal law. (His italics.) - (A maxim is a principle of conduct, such as keep
your promises.) - Kant also puts the categorical imperative this
way Act as if the maxim of thy action were to
become a universal law of nature. (His
italics.) - He further states the categorical imperative when
he says I am never to act otherwise than so that
I could also will that my maxim should become a
universal law. (His italics.)
26CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE II
- A categorical imperative is unconditional -
categorical means absolute, unqualified, or
unconditional. - Kants categorical imperative is objectively
necessary. - It concerns the necessity of a correct moral
action itself without reference to any
consequence of the action.
27CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE III
- According to Kant, all moral laws, or what he
calls imperatives of duty, such as keep your
promises, tell the truth, and repay your debts,
can be deduced from this one imperative
namely, the categorical imperative act only on
that maxim whereby you can will that it should
become a universal law. - Kant thinks that the categorical imperative is a
general law to which particular moral laws, such
as those just cited, must conform.
28CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE IV
- We have seen that Kant thinks that the goodness
of an act does not lie in its effects, but in the
conception of the moral law according to which
all rational agents should act, and so Kant is
not a utilitarian or consequentialist. - In addition, Kant says that the conception of the
correct moral law will and must determine the
will, or tell us what is the correct moral
action, and he says that this correct moral law
pertains to everyone. - If we look to moral law for correct moral
behavior, and not to the effects of actions, then
we must ask what kind of law it is to which we
are to look for morality. - The answer, for Kant, is the categorical
imperative, the general law from which, and
according to which particular moral laws can be
tested.
29TESTING MORAL LAWS I
- To test a moral act one can ask What would
happen if everyone did this? Or, Would it be
okay for anyone to do this in the same or similar
circumstances? (Cf. Thomas Nagel.) - If what I am about to do is morally correct then,
for Kant, it would be morally correct for
everyone to do the same thing in the same
circumstances. - If an action is morally correct then it is
universalizable, that is, it is good for
everyone, everywhere, everywhen.
30TESTING MORAL LAWS II
- For Kant, a particular moral principle can be
tested by asking if a rule pertaining to behavior
which goes against the principle can be
universalized. - And he says If not, then it must be rejected .
. . because it cannot enter as a principle into a
possible universal legislation cannot be a
moral law applicable to everyone. - Thus a test of a maxim or moral law such as keep
your promises is to ask if a principle
pertaining to conduct which would break the law,
such as it is okay to make a promise which you
dont intend to keep, could be universalized.
31TEST 1 MAKING FALSE PROMISES I
- Could the rule it is okay to break a promise,
or it is okay to make a false promise be
universalized? - If so, that is, if it would be okay for everyone
to make promises which they dont intend to keep,
then making false promises would fit the
categorical imperative and so would be morally
acceptable. - But can making false promises be universalized?
To answer this we must ask what would happen, or
what the consequences would be, of everyone
making promises which they do not intend to keep.
32TEST 1 MAKING FALSE PROMISES II
- Kants answer is that promises would cease to
mean anything. Thus we could never count on the
promise of another, or could never be sure that a
promise was serious and will be kept if it is
okay to make a false promise is a moral
principle. - Accordingly, the maxim it is okay to make a
false promise, as soon as it should be made a
universal law, would necessarily destroy itself. - Notice that there is no hypothetical which
precedes the statement of the moral law keep
your promises, such as if you want to be
well-liked or if you want to have a good
reputation then keep your promises.
33PRUDENCE AND DUTY I
- If we looked at promise keeping as a hypothetical
imperative which says If you want to be liked,
then keep your promises, then it might be
thought to be prudent to keep your promises given
that objective. - Hypothetical imperatives, such as, if you want a
good grade, then study hard, are said to be
prudential. - However, since a law which says that it is okay
to break promises cannot be universalized,
keeping promises is unconditional, and, as such,
is something which we have a duty to do. - The categorical imperative is moral then rather
than prudential.
34PRUDENCE AND DUTY II
- Kant grants that it may in some cases be prudent
for a person to break a promise, but the moral
question is whether it can ever be right? - Whether or not something is prudent depends on
its consequences. And Kant does not base
morality on the consequences of acts, at least
not after the consequences of considering the
possible universalization of a law, such as
making false promises, which would test a law
such as keep your promises, has been considered
and rejected.
35PRUDENCE AND DUTY III
- In knowing how to behave morally, I do not need
to look to the world and what the possible
consequences of my action might be, I only need
to look at whether or not a moral principle, such
as tell the truth, is consistent with the
categorical imperative, that is whether or not
the principle can be universalized, or whether or
not I can will that everyone ought to tell the
truth. - I only need to ask if the action which I am
considering can be willed to be a universal law,
and if it cant be then it has to be rejected.
36PRUDENCE AND DUTY IV
- Thus if the act which I am considering is making
a false promise I have to ask whether or not
making false promises can be universalized. - Since they cannot, because promises would then no
longer be believable, the maxim of making false
promises must be rejected. - For Kant, the necessity of acting from pure
respect for the practical moral law is what
constitutes duty, to which every other motive
must give place, because it is the condition of a
will being good in itself, and the worth of such
a will is above everything. (His italics.)
37TEST 2 SUICIDE I
- Is suicide okay for a depressed person if he or
she reasons as follows? - a) To stay alive would be far less good for me
than bad. b) I love myself. c) Because I love
myself I do not want to see myself suffer. d)
Therefore, I ought to commit suicide to end my
suffering.
Old Man in Sorrow (On the Threshold of Eternity)
Vincent Van Gogh, 1890
38TEST 2 SUICIDE II
- For Kant, the crucial thing for the morality of
suicide is whether or not this reasoning to the
correctness of suicide to end suffering from
self-love can become a universal law of nature.
- And he thinks that it cannot since, according to
Kant, to commit suicide out of self-love is
contradictory. It is contradictory because
self-love is the very thing which motivates us to
improve our lives. - However, the removal of life is not improvement
of life, and so self-love which provided these
contradictory options cannot be made a universal
law of nature, and consequently would be wholly
inconsistent with the supreme principle of all
duty.
39TEST 3 WASTING YOUR TALENT I
- What if one is financially independent and is
also exceptionally talented? What then does she
owe, if anything to her talent? Is it okay for
her to indulge in pleasure rather than to take
pains in enlarging and improving his happy
natural capacities? - Kant notes that it is possible for people - even
an entire culture - to neglect their talents in
fact, to devote their lives to idle amusement.
But the moral question is, is it proper?
40TEST 3 WASTING YOUR TALENT II
- Kant says that it is not, since it is not
possible to will that the neglect of talent
should become a universal law. - He cannot will that we ought to neglect our
talents since it is by means of our talents that
we develop and improve our lives, and this is
what a rational being aims for. - That is, a rational being will necessarily will
that his abilities be developed since they are
useful to him, and serve any number of purposes.
Accordingly, he cannot at the same time will that
they be neglected without contradicting himself.
41TEST 4 CONCERN FOR OTHERS I
- Kant says that the world might in fact be
composed of people who mind their own business
and take no interest in the lives of others. - However, he says that it is impossible to will
this lack of concern for others. - This is because there may be cases in which we
need the help and consideration of others.
42TEST 4 CONCERN FOR OTHERS II
- But if we will it to be a universal law that no
one should help anyone else, then we would
thereby deprive ourselves of the very assistance
which we require. - Thus in both willing it that no one should help
anyone else, while desiring it ourselves when we
are in need, we contradict ourselves. - Accordingly, it would be impossible to will a
lack of concern for others to have the universal
validity of a law of nature.
43PRUDENCE AND DUTY V
- Kant takes the above test cases to show that if
duty is a conception which is to have any import
and real legislative authority for our actions,
it can only be expressed in categorical, and not
at all in hypothetical imperatives. - Thus one does not say, if you want to be
well-liked, then help others in need, which is a
hypothetical imperative which might be thought
prudent for a person to follow. Instead, we see
that we ought to help others since a principle
which maintains that we ought not to help others
in need cannot be consistently universalized. - Helping others then fits the categorical
imperative which pertains to the universalization
of correct moral actions.
44PERSONS AND THINGS
- According to Kant, persons are rational agents
who are ends in themselves. - Thus Kant says that man and generally any
rational being exists as and end in himself, not
merely as a means to be arbitrarily used . . . - For Kant, rational beings are persons and
non-rational beings are things. - Persons are ends in themselves and have absolute
value, whereas things are means to an end and
only have relative value as means to an end.
45PERSONS AND THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE I
- Because persons are rational, they are ends in
themselves for Kant, and not merely things which
have relative value because they are only means
to something else. - The status of persons as rational agents who are
ends in themselves gives rise to a second way of
stating the categorical imperative So act as to
treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in
that of any other, in every case as an end
withal, never as means only.
46PERSONS AND THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE II
- Although persons can sometimes be used as means
to an end - as you use a teacher as a means to
the end of getting an education - persons are
never to be used merely or only as means. - Thus something like slavery is morally
reprehensible since you are treating a slave as a
thing and not as a person, you are using a slave
as a machine or an instrument of cheap labor and
not recognizing his or her essential humanity. - All rational beings are subject to the same
universal moral laws which conform to the
categorical imperative of acting on a principle
which you can will to become a universal law.
47THE KINGDOM OF ENDS I
- The community of rational beings who act under a
system of common moral laws Kant calls a kingdom. - Each person must recognize himself as an end in
himself and must recognize at the same time that
every other person too is an end in himself.
This is our duty according to Kant. - Kant says that all rational beings come under
the law that each of them must treat itself and
all others never merely as means, but in every
case at the same time as ends in themselves.
48THE KINGDOM OF ENDS II
- That is, every person is subject to the second
form of the categorical imperative, the law which
says that it is our duty to treat each person as
an end in herself and never as merely as a means
to an end. - Whenever a person is treated as a means to
something else, it must be recognized at the same
time that she is an end in herself. - According to Kant, when we all recognize each
other as ends in themselves, and not merely as
means to an end, then our community, our kingdom,
becomes a community of persons treated as ends in
themselves, or what Kant calls a kingdom of ends.
49KANT AND MORALITY I
- We know that, for Kant, respect for the moral law
is of the utmost importance. - And Kant thinks that we should not consider the
value of our own pleasure or well-being or that
of others over the moral law. - Contra at least act utilitarianism, in a contest
between increasing happiness and the moral law,
the moral law should win.
50KANT AND MORALITY II
- Some people think that Kants devotion to the
moral law can have absurd consequences. For
instance, he said that it is our duty always to
tell the truth. As such it would not seem
permissible ever to tell a lie, even to save the
life of another person! - We have an obligation to tell the truth since
lying cannot be universalized, and we have an
obligation to help others for reasons seen above
in the fourth test of the categorical imperative.
Might we not then need to lie to help another?
And doesnt this raise a problem about
conflicting duties? - However this might be dealt with, since moral
rules like telling the truth, are both
universally valid - for everyone, at every time
and at every place - and thus admit of no
exceptions - for Kant we have an absolute duty to
follow them.
51Maria von Herberts Challenge to Kant
Rae Langton (1961-)
52MARIAS PROBLEM I
- Maria von Herbert was a young woman who wrote to
Kant for advice. - Maria was in love with a young man who also loved
her until she was honest with him about her
having had a past sexual relationship with
another man. - Her honesty about the past affair causes the man
to lose his love for her, and this in turn so
depresses her that she considers suicide. - In fact, the only thing which prevents her from
committing suicide is Kants ethics, which
prohibits suicide. - The problem for Maria is that Kants philosophy
does not help her in dealing with the pain which
she now experiences.
53Edvard Munch, Ashes, 1894
54KANTS RESPONSE TO MARIA I
- Perhaps the first telling thing here regarding
Kants role in this matter is that he asks a
friend what he should do, rather than being able
to decide for himself. - Why would someone who has written works in moral
philosophy, which tell people what to do and what
not to do, need advice from someone else? - Kant writes back to Maria and tells her that the
mans indignation is justified, but that she was
right to have told the truth, since it is our
duty to tell the truth.
55KANTS RESPONSE TO MARIA II
- Kant also tells her that, with time, the man will
return to her if his love for her was genuine and
moral. If he does not return than his affection
was more physical than genuine. - Kant also tells Maria that she must meet her
misfortune with composure, and says that the
value of life, insofar as it consists of the
enjoyment we get from people, is vastly
overrated. - This quote perhaps is telling, since someone who
gets little enjoyment from others may have little
sympathy or feeling for others. - And as Langton points out, Kant thinks that Maria
deserves to have lost her love, and that her
suffering is appropriate punishment for her
immoral behavior.
56MARIAS PROBLEM II
- Maria writes again to Kant and says that she has
lost her interest in life, which is pointless,
that her soul is empty, that desire is gone, and
she says that each day interests me only to the
extent that it brings me closer to death. - Maria also asks Kant to write back to her with
specific details about how to deal with her
problems, and also asks permission to visit him. - For Langton, Marias life with its problems
constitutes a profound challenge to Kants
philosophy
57MORAL MOTIVATION, DUTY, AND FEELING
- Langton reminds us that, in Kantian ethics, an
action has moral worth when it is done for the
sake of duty it is not enough that the action
conforms with duty. - Thus, for Kant, if we do something moral we ought
to do it out of respect for duty, and not, for
instance, due to sympathy. - According to Kant, the person who treats persons
out of duty to the version of the categorical
imperative which says to treat persons as ends
and never merely as means, and yet who has no
sympathy or feelings for others, is more moral
than someone who is sympathetic. - Kant thinks that sympathy and feeling are
burdensome. It is reverence for the moral law
which is to be respected, and it must prevail
over all human inclinations and desires.
58PERSONS AND THINGS I
- Kant does not reply to Maria or honor her request
to visit him, but now considers her mentally
deranged and sends off her letters to an
acquaintance. - Langton says that evil for Kant is the reduction
of persons to things (the second version of the
categorical imperative). - Langton points out that, in the society in which
Maria lived, women must perpetually walk a
tightrope between being treated as things and
treated as persons.
59Edvard Munch, Evening on Karl Johan Street, 1892
60PERSONS AND THINGS II
- Langton points out that Maria would have had to
contend with the sexual marketplace, where human
beings are viewed as having a price, and not a
dignity, and where the price of women is fixed in
a particular way. (Her italics.) - Langton Women, as things, as items in the
sexual marketplace, have a market value that
depends in part on whether they have been used.
Virgins fetch a higher price than second hand
goods. - Langton remarks that this is to treat a person as
a thing, and that such treatment must be evil
according to Kants own philosophy. And she says
that this is a point which Kant himself did not
recognize, since he thought it was appropriate
that Maria suffer as she did for her confession.
61QUESTIONS
- Is it different now?
- Do women feel that they are sometimes or often
treated as things, sex objects? - Do men now look at women that way?
- How are women first looked at?
- Do women see themselves as the equals of men?
- Do men see women as equals?
62PERSONS AND THINGS III
- Kants ethics says that we ought always to tell
the truth, and so Maria had an obligation to tell
the truth about her past. However, Langton
suggests that, by telling the truth, Maria is
transformed from a person into a thing, used
merchandise, because of the attitudes of the
culture in which she lived. - Langton thinks that perhaps Maria can be
permitted to lie because the culture in which she
lives is evil. It is evil since it sees
unmarried women who are not virgins as things
rather than persons. - The idea is that, knowing that she will be
treated like a thing if she is honest, she may
lie in order to protect her status as a person.
63PERSONS AND THINGS IV
- But further, Langton thinks that Maria may even
have a duty to lie, on Kantian theory, since it
is part of Kants ethics that each person has a
duty of self-esteem, an obligation to respect
herself, and a duty to recognize that people are
not, like things, for sale at any price. - Marias duty not to treat herself as a thing, or
to allow herself to be treated as a thing, means
that she ought to lie to protect herself from
such treatment.
64THE KINGDOM OF ENDS
- Remember that the Kantian Kingdom of Ends is the
world in which every person respects every other
person, and where no person is treated merely as
a means rather than as an end, a community of
persons treated as ends in themselves. - Langton says that Kant thinks we should act as
if the Kingdom of Ends is with us now. He thinks
that we should rely on God to make it alright in
the end. - This is the idea that the virtuous person who is
not rewarded for his or her morality on earth
will be rewarded by God in the afterlife. - But Langton says that God will not make it all
right in the end. And the Kingdom of Ends is not
with us now. - And she adds that Perhaps we should do what we
can to bring it about.
65PERSONS AND THINGS V
- Maria von Herbert never got to visit Kant and she
finally killed herself. - In not treating her with the respect and sympathy
which she deserved, Langton thinks that Kant
ended up treating Maria as a thing rather than as
a person. - See the study questions at the end of the
article.
66The Holocaust and Moral Philosophy
Fred Sommers
67TWO ETHICAL TRADITIONS
- The German tradition in ethics focuses on reason.
The focus of this rationalist tradition is on
persons and our duties to them. - The British tradition in ethics focuses on
feeling, and on attitudes, thoughts, and
judgements as they relate to or are prompted by
feeling. The focus for the sentimentalist
tradition is on all beings that can feel pain or
pleasure and directly prohibits cruelty to all
sentient beings.
68THE SUPERIORITY OF THE BRITISH TRADITION
- Sommers will argue that the tradition based on
feeling is superior to the tradition based on
reason. - For Sommers, the German tradition in ethics
helped in the German attitude towards the Jews in
WWII. This is because Jews were reclassified as
nonpersons by the Nazis, and only persons have
respect and moral protection in the German
tradition in ethics. - For Sommers then, there must be something
defective in German moral philosophy.
69MORAL PATIENTS, DOING WRONG, AND WRONGING
- Sommers points out that there is a difference
between doing wrong and wronging. You can do
wrong by damaging a tree, but you do not thereby
wrong the tree. - Sommers quotes Geoffrey Warnocks definition of a
moral patient as Any being that a moral agent
can wrong. - Sommers According to the central (Kantian)
tradition in German moral thinking, the domain of
moral patients includes all and only moral
agents, excluding many nonrational beings as
nonpersons or things.
70RATIONALITY AND MORAL CONSIDERATION
- According to the German tradition in ethics, you
cannot wrong a nonrational being or thing.
Rather, in this tradition, we only owe respect to
persons. - Kant says that All moral philosophy rests wholly
on its pure part. When applied to man it does
not borrow the least thing from the knowledge of
man himself (anthropology), but gives laws to him
as a rational being.
71SENTIENCE AND THE BRITISH TRADITION I
- Sommers contrasts the ethics of Kant with that of
Hume, and philosophers such as William
Shaftesbury, Adam Smith, and the utilitarians who
base moral obligation on compassion and feelings
of benevolence. - For Hume and Bentham the moral community is not
based on an entitys capacity to think, but its
capacity to feel and suffer.
72SENTIENCE AND THE BRITISH TRADITION II
- For these philosophers, and the British tradition
in ethics, any sentient being can be wronged. - (Sentient - adj L sentient-, sentiens, prp of
sentire to perceive, feel (1632) 1 responsive
to or conscious of sense impressions 2 AWARE 3
finely sensitive in perception or feeling.
Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary, Tenth
Edition.) - Kant labeled this approach to ethics
anthropological, and found it impure.
73SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY I
- What Sommers likes about the empirical approach
of Hume, which is based on feeling, is that
cruelty or brutality to any sentient being is
the very paradigm of indecent, inadmissable
behavior. - Sommers According to Kant, animals are not in
the domain of moral patients and we have no
direct duty to be kind to them. We do have an
indirect duty to refrain from acts of cruelty to
animals because such behavior could corrupt our
character, and this could affect the way we
behave to rational beings to whom we do owe
respect.
74SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY II
- For Kant then, and the tradition which bases
morality on reason, the idea is not that we
should respect animals other than humans because
of their capacity to feel pain, or that
mistreating animals is not wrong in itself
because animals then suffer, but because to
mistreat an animal could adversely affect the way
we treat each other. - Thus the mistreatment of animals is not wrong
because animals are mistreated, but because the
mistreatment of animals could lead to the
mistreatment of humans.
75SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY III
- The problem with the Kantian philosophy on this
issue, for Sommers, is that anyone who would not
be corrupted by mistreating animals would not be
doing wrong to mistreat them. - For Sommers, this shows that there is something
wrong with the rationalist approach to ethics of
Kant and his followers.
76THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS I
- Recall how sympathy loses to a bad morality for
Himmler when, although he has sympathy for his
victims, he recognizes that it is his duty to
eliminate them. - Sommers recognizes that the treatment of the Jews
by the Nazis would surely have horrified Kant,
but a moral philosophy which does not directly
proscribe cruelty to nonpersons makes it
possible to mistreat any being which is not
thought to qualify as a person. - For the Nazis, Jews did not qualify as persons.
Accordingly, Sommers then points out that, If
Jews are like insects, killing them is not a
crime against humanity.
77THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS II
- Of course, the Kantian could say here that
killing or mistreating Jews is wrong for the same
reason that mistreating dogs is wrong, because of
its effect on the people who mistreat them. That
is, by mistreating Jews, even though Jews are
nonpersons, we might lead us to mistreat persons. - Sommers point though is that Kantian ethics
allows for the mistreatment of certain peoples
because they can be reclassified as nonpersons.
78THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS III
- Sommers does not think that this reclassification
of persons as nonpersons does not and will not
happen in any moral philosophy which is based on
feeling rather than on rationality. - Thus he says that A people steeped in the
sentimentalist moral philosophy such as that of
Locke, Hume, or Mill regards all sentient beings
those capable of feeling and sensation, or
pleasure and pain as moral patients. as
deserving of moral consideration. And such a
people would view an openly cruel leader like
Hitler as unacceptably immoral.
79THE DANGER OF THE GERMAN RATIONAL TRADITION I
- For Sommers, any ethics which is based on the
notions of duty and respect rather than on
kindness and compassion is wrong and dangerous. - The formal approach to ethics taken by Kant which
is based on duty to rational agents leaves other
being worthy of moral consideration outside of
the moral community. - And it leaves open the possibility that certain
beings who we would normally consider to be part
of the moral community, such as Jews, would not
be considered persons, and therefore not morally
protected.
80THE DANGER OF THE GERMAN RATIONAL TRADITION II
- Such an arbitrary drawing of moral boundaries
cannot happen for any ethics which is based on
benevolence and human compassion. - And this is the case for the British tradition in
ethics in which the focus is on basic sentience
and feeling. - Sommers concludes by saying that a moral theory
that does not absolutely, directly, and
foundationally anathematize cruelty must be ruled
out of court. - According to Sommers, the German rational
tradition does not do this, and so is not only
inferior to the British tradition, but is
dangerous.