Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative

1 / 80
About This Presentation
Title:

Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative

Description:

... machine or an instrument of cheap labor and not recognizing his or her essential ... Sommers quotes Geoffrey Warnock's definition of a moral patient as 'Any being ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:260
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 81
Provided by: JeffSt6

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative


1
Jacques Louis David, The Oath of the Horatii, 1784
2
Good Will, Duty, and the Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
3
KANT AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY
  • Modern philosophy begins with René Descartes
    (1596-1650).
  • However, Kant is regarded by many as the greatest
    of all the modern philosophers.
  • Indeed, with Plato and Aristotle, Kant is often
    considered to be one of the three greatest
    philosophers.
  • Kant made great contributions in epistemology,
    metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics.
  • The Critique of Pure Reason widely regarded as a
    masterpiece, and the greatest single work in
    philosophy since the Greeks, perhaps since
    Aristotles Metaphysics.

4
MAN, NATURE, AND RATIONALITY
  • Kant notes that everything in nature works
    according to laws. However, humans differ from
    other parts of nature in that humans alone can
    according to principles.
  • Thus, Kant recognizes the rationality of human
    beings.
  • Humans are rational in having a conception of
    laws, or principles.
  • Our rationality enables us to understand the
    correctness of moral laws such as keep your
    promises, and to know the difference between
    right and wrong.

5
FREE AGENCY
  • Human beings are also free agents, that is, we
    have free will, or can freely choose between
    options, including moral options. That is, we
    can freely choose to do right or wrong.
  • Because of our rationality, we can understand the
    difference between right and wrong. And, because
    of our rationality, we can understand moral laws
    which it is our duty to accept as binding.
  • Our freedom to choose means then that we are
    capable of freely acting on this knowledge. That
    is we can freely choose to do what is proper.

6
REASON AND AGENCY
  • Knowing how to act morally requires reason. Thus
    we must be able to deduce and understand the
    principles of correct moral behavior.
  • Having understood what is the right thing to do,
    we then act in a morally correct way when we
    freely choose to act according to the moral law
    which reason has recognized to be correct.
  • Kant calls our ability to act according to
    principles, or our capacity to use our free will
    to do the right thing, practical reason.
  • Thus, for Kant, the will puts to use or practice
    the principles of reason insofar as they concern
    moral behavior.

7
RATIONALITY AND DESIRE
  • Kant recognizes that people are not only rational
    agents but we also have desires and appetites.
  • However, as a rational agent, a person can choose
    to do what is right in spite of the influence of
    desires and appetites.
  • When desires and appetites, or what Kant calls
    subjective conditions, would lead a person not
    to do the morally correct thing, or when morality
    and desire conflict, the moral person acts
    according to reason to do the right thing, in
    spite of the influences of their desires and
    appetites.

8
MORAL WORTH
  • For Kant, a person of moral worth does the right
    thing, and does so in spite of the influence of
    desire and appetite which may lead her to do the
    wrong thing.
  • And, for Kant, moral worth is the most important
    attribute which a person can have.
  • Moral worth is more important and more admirable
    than such talents of the mind as intelligence,
    wit, and judgment and is more important than
    such qualities of temperament as courage,
    resolution, and perseverance.
  • For Kant, these gifts of nature - intelligence,
    courage, and so forth - may also become bad and
    mischievous if the will which is to make use of
    them is not good.

9
GOOD WILL I
  • As seen, Kant recognizes that such things as
    intelligence and talent are good and valuable,
    but he thinks that moral worth has absolute
    value, and is more important than anything else
    which we might admire in a person.
  • We have also seen that, for Kant, we are
    obligated by reason to follow objective moral
    laws even though we may not do so because of the
    influence of subjective conditions, or desires
    and appetites, on the will.
  • A persons will to do the right thing, the thing
    which reason can identify as the morally correct
    thing to do, is a good will, and one which does
    not is not thoroughly good.

10
GOOD WILL II
  • A person of moral worth is a person of good will
    in freely choosing to do the morally correct
    thing whether or not she is under the influence
    of desire to do otherwise.
  • And Kant says that Nothing can possibly be
    conceived in the world, or even out of it, which
    can be called good without qualification, except
    a Good Will.
  • Again, things like intelligence, talent, courage,
    and diligence are good, but if they are not
    backed by good character or a good will, then
    they can be put to bad use by a bad person. For
    instance, Hitler.

11
GOOD WILL III
  • A good will is necessary to make sure that what
    Kant calls gifts of fortune, such as wealth and
    power, do not lead us astray as moral beings.
  • Even things which are thought to be good in many
    respects, such as self-control and calm
    deliberation, have no intrinsic unconditional
    value, but always presuppose a good will.
  • Not only are such things not absolutely good, as
    a good will is, but they can be put to bad use if
    not backed by a good will. Thus we may admire
    qualities such as self-control and calm
    deliberation, but, if not backed by a good will
    they may become extremely bad. For instance,
    Kant says that the coolness of a villain makes
    him far more dangerous than he would have been
    had he lacked the self-control and calm
    deliberation that coolness implies.

12
GOOD WILL IV
  • For Kant, a good will is not good because of what
    it brings about or helps to bring about, but
    because it is good in itself.
  • A good will, considered by itself as it is in
    itself, is much more admirable than anything
    which it brings about.
  • For instance, the good will which brings about
    happiness is much more deserving of respect than
    is the happiness which it produces.

13
GOOD WILL V
  • Even if a good will accomplishes nothing, it is
    still to be admired as something which has its
    whole value in itself.
  • So whether a good will is useful in producing
    results or not, it is still of the utmost
    goodness in itself.
  • The value of a good will then lies entirely in
    itself and not in what it produces.

14
GOOD WILL VI
  • For Kant, a good will is good not because of
    what it performs or effects, but is good in
    itself.
  • Because the value of a good will lies entirely
    within itself, it is still good whether it
    results in anything which is either a good or a
    bad effect of it.
  • The good will then has its whole value in
    itself, and its usefulness or fruitlessness can
    neither add to nor take away anything from this
    value.

15
MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES I
  • Kant says that the moral worth of an action does
    not lie in the effect expected from it, nor in
    any principle of action which requires to borrow
    its motive from this expected effect.
  • Thus, unlike any consequentialist theory, Kant
    says that it is incorrect to look for the moral
    worth of an action in its effects.
  • The reason for this is that expected effects of
    actions, such as improving ones own condition,
    as in egoism, or increasing the happiness of
    everyone likely to be effected by the action, as
    in utilitarianism, Kant says could have been
    brought about by other causes.
  • And, if that were the case, then there would
    have been no need of the will of a rational
    being.

16
MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES II
  • Recall that, for Kant, it is in this will alone
    that the supreme and unconditional good can be
    found.
  • And if that is where the supreme and
    unconditional good is to be found, then it is not
    to be found in the consequences of an action,
    whether those consequences mean a better life for
    oneself, as in egoism, or in a better life for
    everyone affected by the action, as in
    utilitarianism.
  • To that end, Kant says The pre-eminent good
    which we call moral can therefore consist in
    nothing else than the conception of law in
    itself, which certainly is possible only in a
    rational being, in so far as this conception, and
    not the expected effect, determines the will.
    (His italics.)

17
MORALITY AND CONSEQUENCES III
  • Thus, for Kant, the moral person does what is
    right because it is right, and does not do right
    because he or she is considering the likely
    effects of doing right for himself or for anyone
    likely to be effected by the action.
  • For Kant, the goodness of a good will is a good
    which is already present in the person who acts
    accordingly that is, a person who acts according
    to moral law, and we have not to wait for it to
    appear first in the result.
  • The goodness of an act is not then judged by its
    consequences, as in a consequentialist theory,
    but is due to a good will, or willing to do the
    right thing because it is the right thing to do.

18
MORAL MOTIVES
  • For Kant it is the moral person who is to be
    respected and revered. However, you are not an
    intrinsically moral person if, although you do
    the right thing, you do so for the wrong reason.
  • For instance, you may keep a promise, not ought
    of knowing that it is the right thing to do, and
    acting on that knowledge, but because you
    perceive it to be to your benefit to do so.
  • A moral person is motivated to do the right thing
    because he recognizes that it is the right thing
    to do, and so acts out of principle.

19
MORALITY IS UNIVERSAL
  • According to Kant, you dont act correctly for a
    subjective reason, such as pleasure or happiness,
    if you are a moral person. Rather, you act out
    of principle.
  • This means recognizing an objective right which
    applies to everyone.
  • What is morally right for one person is morally
    right for everyone, which is what is meant by
    saying that morality is universal.

20
DUTY I
  • That morality is universal and objective, rather
    than local, historical, and subjective, means
    that every rational agent has an obligation to do
    what is right.
  • Thus it is your duty to do what is morally right
    as an objective matter.
  • Kants ethics is called deontological. The word
    deontology comes from the Greek words deon for
    duty and logos for science. Thus deontology
    would be the science of duty.

21
DUTY II
  • A deontological theory of ethics stresses a
    persons duty to do the morally correct thing
    regardless of consequences.
  • For deontological ethics, some acts are morally
    obligatory whether their consequences are good or
    bad for human beings.
  • Because of lack of consideration of consequences,
    a deontological theory is nonconsequentialist.
  • The deontologist will typically hold that his
    moral standards are higher than those of the
    consequentialist.

22
IMPERATIVES
  • An imperative is a command that I act in a
    certain fashion.
  • Kant talks of two kinds of imperative, or two
    kinds of command (of reason), namely,
    hypothetical or categorical.
  • A hypothetical imperative concerns an action
    which is good only as a means to something
    else. (His italics.) A categorical imperative
    concerns an action which is conceived of as good
    in itself. (His italics.)

23
HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVE I
  • A hypothetical imperative is conditional.
  • That is, it depends on certain things, and
    concerns what needs to be done in order to attain
    an objective.
  • An imperative (a command of reason to act in a
    certain way) is hypothetical when it concerns an
    action which is good only as a means to something
    else.

24
HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVE II
  • For instance, if you want to begin collecting
    art, then your ability to collect good art will
    be dependent or conditional on your ability to
    recognize good art.
  • It is therefore imperative that you learn
    something about art so that you can tell the good
    from the bad. And the hypothetical command of
    reason in this case would be If you want to
    build a good collection of art (the hypothetical)
    then learn about art (the imperative).
  • Thus learning about art is good, but it is
    hypothetical because it is a means to something
    else, namely acquiring a good collection.

25
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE I
  • Kant says that There is but one categorical
    imperative, namely this Act only on that maxim
    whereby thou canst at the same time will that it
    should become a universal law. (His italics.)
  • (A maxim is a principle of conduct, such as keep
    your promises.)
  • Kant also puts the categorical imperative this
    way Act as if the maxim of thy action were to
    become a universal law of nature. (His
    italics.)
  • He further states the categorical imperative when
    he says I am never to act otherwise than so that
    I could also will that my maxim should become a
    universal law. (His italics.)

26
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE II
  • A categorical imperative is unconditional -
    categorical means absolute, unqualified, or
    unconditional.
  • Kants categorical imperative is objectively
    necessary.
  • It concerns the necessity of a correct moral
    action itself without reference to any
    consequence of the action.

27
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE III
  • According to Kant, all moral laws, or what he
    calls imperatives of duty, such as keep your
    promises, tell the truth, and repay your debts,
    can be deduced from this one imperative
    namely, the categorical imperative act only on
    that maxim whereby you can will that it should
    become a universal law.
  • Kant thinks that the categorical imperative is a
    general law to which particular moral laws, such
    as those just cited, must conform.

28
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE IV
  • We have seen that Kant thinks that the goodness
    of an act does not lie in its effects, but in the
    conception of the moral law according to which
    all rational agents should act, and so Kant is
    not a utilitarian or consequentialist.
  • In addition, Kant says that the conception of the
    correct moral law will and must determine the
    will, or tell us what is the correct moral
    action, and he says that this correct moral law
    pertains to everyone.
  • If we look to moral law for correct moral
    behavior, and not to the effects of actions, then
    we must ask what kind of law it is to which we
    are to look for morality.
  • The answer, for Kant, is the categorical
    imperative, the general law from which, and
    according to which particular moral laws can be
    tested.

29
TESTING MORAL LAWS I
  • To test a moral act one can ask What would
    happen if everyone did this? Or, Would it be
    okay for anyone to do this in the same or similar
    circumstances? (Cf. Thomas Nagel.)
  • If what I am about to do is morally correct then,
    for Kant, it would be morally correct for
    everyone to do the same thing in the same
    circumstances.
  • If an action is morally correct then it is
    universalizable, that is, it is good for
    everyone, everywhere, everywhen.

30
TESTING MORAL LAWS II
  • For Kant, a particular moral principle can be
    tested by asking if a rule pertaining to behavior
    which goes against the principle can be
    universalized.
  • And he says If not, then it must be rejected .
    . . because it cannot enter as a principle into a
    possible universal legislation cannot be a
    moral law applicable to everyone.
  • Thus a test of a maxim or moral law such as keep
    your promises is to ask if a principle
    pertaining to conduct which would break the law,
    such as it is okay to make a promise which you
    dont intend to keep, could be universalized.

31
TEST 1 MAKING FALSE PROMISES I
  • Could the rule it is okay to break a promise,
    or it is okay to make a false promise be
    universalized?
  • If so, that is, if it would be okay for everyone
    to make promises which they dont intend to keep,
    then making false promises would fit the
    categorical imperative and so would be morally
    acceptable.
  • But can making false promises be universalized?
    To answer this we must ask what would happen, or
    what the consequences would be, of everyone
    making promises which they do not intend to keep.

32
TEST 1 MAKING FALSE PROMISES II
  • Kants answer is that promises would cease to
    mean anything. Thus we could never count on the
    promise of another, or could never be sure that a
    promise was serious and will be kept if it is
    okay to make a false promise is a moral
    principle.
  • Accordingly, the maxim it is okay to make a
    false promise, as soon as it should be made a
    universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.
  • Notice that there is no hypothetical which
    precedes the statement of the moral law keep
    your promises, such as if you want to be
    well-liked or if you want to have a good
    reputation then keep your promises.

33
PRUDENCE AND DUTY I
  • If we looked at promise keeping as a hypothetical
    imperative which says If you want to be liked,
    then keep your promises, then it might be
    thought to be prudent to keep your promises given
    that objective.
  • Hypothetical imperatives, such as, if you want a
    good grade, then study hard, are said to be
    prudential.
  • However, since a law which says that it is okay
    to break promises cannot be universalized,
    keeping promises is unconditional, and, as such,
    is something which we have a duty to do.
  • The categorical imperative is moral then rather
    than prudential.

34
PRUDENCE AND DUTY II
  • Kant grants that it may in some cases be prudent
    for a person to break a promise, but the moral
    question is whether it can ever be right?
  • Whether or not something is prudent depends on
    its consequences. And Kant does not base
    morality on the consequences of acts, at least
    not after the consequences of considering the
    possible universalization of a law, such as
    making false promises, which would test a law
    such as keep your promises, has been considered
    and rejected.

35
PRUDENCE AND DUTY III
  • In knowing how to behave morally, I do not need
    to look to the world and what the possible
    consequences of my action might be, I only need
    to look at whether or not a moral principle, such
    as tell the truth, is consistent with the
    categorical imperative, that is whether or not
    the principle can be universalized, or whether or
    not I can will that everyone ought to tell the
    truth.
  • I only need to ask if the action which I am
    considering can be willed to be a universal law,
    and if it cant be then it has to be rejected.

36
PRUDENCE AND DUTY IV
  • Thus if the act which I am considering is making
    a false promise I have to ask whether or not
    making false promises can be universalized.
  • Since they cannot, because promises would then no
    longer be believable, the maxim of making false
    promises must be rejected.
  • For Kant, the necessity of acting from pure
    respect for the practical moral law is what
    constitutes duty, to which every other motive
    must give place, because it is the condition of a
    will being good in itself, and the worth of such
    a will is above everything. (His italics.)

37
TEST 2 SUICIDE I
  • Is suicide okay for a depressed person if he or
    she reasons as follows?
  • a) To stay alive would be far less good for me
    than bad. b) I love myself. c) Because I love
    myself I do not want to see myself suffer. d)
    Therefore, I ought to commit suicide to end my
    suffering.

Old Man in Sorrow (On the Threshold of Eternity)
Vincent Van Gogh, 1890
38
TEST 2 SUICIDE II
  • For Kant, the crucial thing for the morality of
    suicide is whether or not this reasoning to the
    correctness of suicide to end suffering from
    self-love can become a universal law of nature.
  • And he thinks that it cannot since, according to
    Kant, to commit suicide out of self-love is
    contradictory. It is contradictory because
    self-love is the very thing which motivates us to
    improve our lives.
  • However, the removal of life is not improvement
    of life, and so self-love which provided these
    contradictory options cannot be made a universal
    law of nature, and consequently would be wholly
    inconsistent with the supreme principle of all
    duty.

39
TEST 3 WASTING YOUR TALENT I
  • What if one is financially independent and is
    also exceptionally talented? What then does she
    owe, if anything to her talent? Is it okay for
    her to indulge in pleasure rather than to take
    pains in enlarging and improving his happy
    natural capacities?
  • Kant notes that it is possible for people - even
    an entire culture - to neglect their talents in
    fact, to devote their lives to idle amusement.
    But the moral question is, is it proper?

40
TEST 3 WASTING YOUR TALENT II
  • Kant says that it is not, since it is not
    possible to will that the neglect of talent
    should become a universal law.
  • He cannot will that we ought to neglect our
    talents since it is by means of our talents that
    we develop and improve our lives, and this is
    what a rational being aims for.
  • That is, a rational being will necessarily will
    that his abilities be developed since they are
    useful to him, and serve any number of purposes.
    Accordingly, he cannot at the same time will that
    they be neglected without contradicting himself.

41
TEST 4 CONCERN FOR OTHERS I
  • Kant says that the world might in fact be
    composed of people who mind their own business
    and take no interest in the lives of others.
  • However, he says that it is impossible to will
    this lack of concern for others.
  • This is because there may be cases in which we
    need the help and consideration of others.

42
TEST 4 CONCERN FOR OTHERS II
  • But if we will it to be a universal law that no
    one should help anyone else, then we would
    thereby deprive ourselves of the very assistance
    which we require.
  • Thus in both willing it that no one should help
    anyone else, while desiring it ourselves when we
    are in need, we contradict ourselves.
  • Accordingly, it would be impossible to will a
    lack of concern for others to have the universal
    validity of a law of nature.

43
PRUDENCE AND DUTY V
  • Kant takes the above test cases to show that if
    duty is a conception which is to have any import
    and real legislative authority for our actions,
    it can only be expressed in categorical, and not
    at all in hypothetical imperatives.
  • Thus one does not say, if you want to be
    well-liked, then help others in need, which is a
    hypothetical imperative which might be thought
    prudent for a person to follow. Instead, we see
    that we ought to help others since a principle
    which maintains that we ought not to help others
    in need cannot be consistently universalized.
  • Helping others then fits the categorical
    imperative which pertains to the universalization
    of correct moral actions.

44
PERSONS AND THINGS
  • According to Kant, persons are rational agents
    who are ends in themselves.
  • Thus Kant says that man and generally any
    rational being exists as and end in himself, not
    merely as a means to be arbitrarily used . . .
  • For Kant, rational beings are persons and
    non-rational beings are things.
  • Persons are ends in themselves and have absolute
    value, whereas things are means to an end and
    only have relative value as means to an end.

45
PERSONS AND THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE I
  • Because persons are rational, they are ends in
    themselves for Kant, and not merely things which
    have relative value because they are only means
    to something else.
  • The status of persons as rational agents who are
    ends in themselves gives rise to a second way of
    stating the categorical imperative So act as to
    treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in
    that of any other, in every case as an end
    withal, never as means only.

46
PERSONS AND THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE II
  • Although persons can sometimes be used as means
    to an end - as you use a teacher as a means to
    the end of getting an education - persons are
    never to be used merely or only as means.
  • Thus something like slavery is morally
    reprehensible since you are treating a slave as a
    thing and not as a person, you are using a slave
    as a machine or an instrument of cheap labor and
    not recognizing his or her essential humanity.
  • All rational beings are subject to the same
    universal moral laws which conform to the
    categorical imperative of acting on a principle
    which you can will to become a universal law.

47
THE KINGDOM OF ENDS I
  • The community of rational beings who act under a
    system of common moral laws Kant calls a kingdom.
  • Each person must recognize himself as an end in
    himself and must recognize at the same time that
    every other person too is an end in himself.
    This is our duty according to Kant.
  • Kant says that all rational beings come under
    the law that each of them must treat itself and
    all others never merely as means, but in every
    case at the same time as ends in themselves.

48
THE KINGDOM OF ENDS II
  • That is, every person is subject to the second
    form of the categorical imperative, the law which
    says that it is our duty to treat each person as
    an end in herself and never as merely as a means
    to an end.
  • Whenever a person is treated as a means to
    something else, it must be recognized at the same
    time that she is an end in herself.
  • According to Kant, when we all recognize each
    other as ends in themselves, and not merely as
    means to an end, then our community, our kingdom,
    becomes a community of persons treated as ends in
    themselves, or what Kant calls a kingdom of ends.

49
KANT AND MORALITY I
  • We know that, for Kant, respect for the moral law
    is of the utmost importance.
  • And Kant thinks that we should not consider the
    value of our own pleasure or well-being or that
    of others over the moral law.
  • Contra at least act utilitarianism, in a contest
    between increasing happiness and the moral law,
    the moral law should win.

50
KANT AND MORALITY II
  • Some people think that Kants devotion to the
    moral law can have absurd consequences. For
    instance, he said that it is our duty always to
    tell the truth. As such it would not seem
    permissible ever to tell a lie, even to save the
    life of another person!
  • We have an obligation to tell the truth since
    lying cannot be universalized, and we have an
    obligation to help others for reasons seen above
    in the fourth test of the categorical imperative.
    Might we not then need to lie to help another?
    And doesnt this raise a problem about
    conflicting duties?
  • However this might be dealt with, since moral
    rules like telling the truth, are both
    universally valid - for everyone, at every time
    and at every place - and thus admit of no
    exceptions - for Kant we have an absolute duty to
    follow them.

51
Maria von Herberts Challenge to Kant
Rae Langton (1961-)
52
MARIAS PROBLEM I
  • Maria von Herbert was a young woman who wrote to
    Kant for advice.
  • Maria was in love with a young man who also loved
    her until she was honest with him about her
    having had a past sexual relationship with
    another man.
  • Her honesty about the past affair causes the man
    to lose his love for her, and this in turn so
    depresses her that she considers suicide.
  • In fact, the only thing which prevents her from
    committing suicide is Kants ethics, which
    prohibits suicide.
  • The problem for Maria is that Kants philosophy
    does not help her in dealing with the pain which
    she now experiences.

53
Edvard Munch, Ashes, 1894
54
KANTS RESPONSE TO MARIA I
  • Perhaps the first telling thing here regarding
    Kants role in this matter is that he asks a
    friend what he should do, rather than being able
    to decide for himself.
  • Why would someone who has written works in moral
    philosophy, which tell people what to do and what
    not to do, need advice from someone else?
  • Kant writes back to Maria and tells her that the
    mans indignation is justified, but that she was
    right to have told the truth, since it is our
    duty to tell the truth.

55
KANTS RESPONSE TO MARIA II
  • Kant also tells her that, with time, the man will
    return to her if his love for her was genuine and
    moral. If he does not return than his affection
    was more physical than genuine.
  • Kant also tells Maria that she must meet her
    misfortune with composure, and says that the
    value of life, insofar as it consists of the
    enjoyment we get from people, is vastly
    overrated.
  • This quote perhaps is telling, since someone who
    gets little enjoyment from others may have little
    sympathy or feeling for others.
  • And as Langton points out, Kant thinks that Maria
    deserves to have lost her love, and that her
    suffering is appropriate punishment for her
    immoral behavior.

56
MARIAS PROBLEM II
  • Maria writes again to Kant and says that she has
    lost her interest in life, which is pointless,
    that her soul is empty, that desire is gone, and
    she says that each day interests me only to the
    extent that it brings me closer to death.
  • Maria also asks Kant to write back to her with
    specific details about how to deal with her
    problems, and also asks permission to visit him.
  • For Langton, Marias life with its problems
    constitutes a profound challenge to Kants
    philosophy

57
MORAL MOTIVATION, DUTY, AND FEELING
  • Langton reminds us that, in Kantian ethics, an
    action has moral worth when it is done for the
    sake of duty it is not enough that the action
    conforms with duty.
  • Thus, for Kant, if we do something moral we ought
    to do it out of respect for duty, and not, for
    instance, due to sympathy.
  • According to Kant, the person who treats persons
    out of duty to the version of the categorical
    imperative which says to treat persons as ends
    and never merely as means, and yet who has no
    sympathy or feelings for others, is more moral
    than someone who is sympathetic.
  • Kant thinks that sympathy and feeling are
    burdensome. It is reverence for the moral law
    which is to be respected, and it must prevail
    over all human inclinations and desires.

58
PERSONS AND THINGS I
  • Kant does not reply to Maria or honor her request
    to visit him, but now considers her mentally
    deranged and sends off her letters to an
    acquaintance.
  • Langton says that evil for Kant is the reduction
    of persons to things (the second version of the
    categorical imperative).
  • Langton points out that, in the society in which
    Maria lived, women must perpetually walk a
    tightrope between being treated as things and
    treated as persons.

59
Edvard Munch, Evening on Karl Johan Street, 1892
60
PERSONS AND THINGS II
  • Langton points out that Maria would have had to
    contend with the sexual marketplace, where human
    beings are viewed as having a price, and not a
    dignity, and where the price of women is fixed in
    a particular way. (Her italics.)
  • Langton Women, as things, as items in the
    sexual marketplace, have a market value that
    depends in part on whether they have been used.
    Virgins fetch a higher price than second hand
    goods.
  • Langton remarks that this is to treat a person as
    a thing, and that such treatment must be evil
    according to Kants own philosophy. And she says
    that this is a point which Kant himself did not
    recognize, since he thought it was appropriate
    that Maria suffer as she did for her confession.

61
QUESTIONS
  • Is it different now?
  • Do women feel that they are sometimes or often
    treated as things, sex objects?
  • Do men now look at women that way?
  • How are women first looked at?
  • Do women see themselves as the equals of men?
  • Do men see women as equals?

62
PERSONS AND THINGS III
  • Kants ethics says that we ought always to tell
    the truth, and so Maria had an obligation to tell
    the truth about her past. However, Langton
    suggests that, by telling the truth, Maria is
    transformed from a person into a thing, used
    merchandise, because of the attitudes of the
    culture in which she lived.
  • Langton thinks that perhaps Maria can be
    permitted to lie because the culture in which she
    lives is evil. It is evil since it sees
    unmarried women who are not virgins as things
    rather than persons.
  • The idea is that, knowing that she will be
    treated like a thing if she is honest, she may
    lie in order to protect her status as a person.

63
PERSONS AND THINGS IV
  • But further, Langton thinks that Maria may even
    have a duty to lie, on Kantian theory, since it
    is part of Kants ethics that each person has a
    duty of self-esteem, an obligation to respect
    herself, and a duty to recognize that people are
    not, like things, for sale at any price.
  • Marias duty not to treat herself as a thing, or
    to allow herself to be treated as a thing, means
    that she ought to lie to protect herself from
    such treatment.

64
THE KINGDOM OF ENDS
  • Remember that the Kantian Kingdom of Ends is the
    world in which every person respects every other
    person, and where no person is treated merely as
    a means rather than as an end, a community of
    persons treated as ends in themselves.
  • Langton says that Kant thinks we should act as
    if the Kingdom of Ends is with us now. He thinks
    that we should rely on God to make it alright in
    the end.
  • This is the idea that the virtuous person who is
    not rewarded for his or her morality on earth
    will be rewarded by God in the afterlife.
  • But Langton says that God will not make it all
    right in the end. And the Kingdom of Ends is not
    with us now.
  • And she adds that Perhaps we should do what we
    can to bring it about.

65
PERSONS AND THINGS V
  • Maria von Herbert never got to visit Kant and she
    finally killed herself.
  • In not treating her with the respect and sympathy
    which she deserved, Langton thinks that Kant
    ended up treating Maria as a thing rather than as
    a person.
  • See the study questions at the end of the
    article.

66
The Holocaust and Moral Philosophy
Fred Sommers
67
TWO ETHICAL TRADITIONS
  • The German tradition in ethics focuses on reason.
    The focus of this rationalist tradition is on
    persons and our duties to them.
  • The British tradition in ethics focuses on
    feeling, and on attitudes, thoughts, and
    judgements as they relate to or are prompted by
    feeling. The focus for the sentimentalist
    tradition is on all beings that can feel pain or
    pleasure and directly prohibits cruelty to all
    sentient beings.

68
THE SUPERIORITY OF THE BRITISH TRADITION
  • Sommers will argue that the tradition based on
    feeling is superior to the tradition based on
    reason.
  • For Sommers, the German tradition in ethics
    helped in the German attitude towards the Jews in
    WWII. This is because Jews were reclassified as
    nonpersons by the Nazis, and only persons have
    respect and moral protection in the German
    tradition in ethics.
  • For Sommers then, there must be something
    defective in German moral philosophy.

69
MORAL PATIENTS, DOING WRONG, AND WRONGING
  • Sommers points out that there is a difference
    between doing wrong and wronging. You can do
    wrong by damaging a tree, but you do not thereby
    wrong the tree.
  • Sommers quotes Geoffrey Warnocks definition of a
    moral patient as Any being that a moral agent
    can wrong.
  • Sommers According to the central (Kantian)
    tradition in German moral thinking, the domain of
    moral patients includes all and only moral
    agents, excluding many nonrational beings as
    nonpersons or things.

70
RATIONALITY AND MORAL CONSIDERATION
  • According to the German tradition in ethics, you
    cannot wrong a nonrational being or thing.
    Rather, in this tradition, we only owe respect to
    persons.
  • Kant says that All moral philosophy rests wholly
    on its pure part. When applied to man it does
    not borrow the least thing from the knowledge of
    man himself (anthropology), but gives laws to him
    as a rational being.

71
SENTIENCE AND THE BRITISH TRADITION I
  • Sommers contrasts the ethics of Kant with that of
    Hume, and philosophers such as William
    Shaftesbury, Adam Smith, and the utilitarians who
    base moral obligation on compassion and feelings
    of benevolence.
  • For Hume and Bentham the moral community is not
    based on an entitys capacity to think, but its
    capacity to feel and suffer.

72
SENTIENCE AND THE BRITISH TRADITION II
  • For these philosophers, and the British tradition
    in ethics, any sentient being can be wronged.
  • (Sentient - adj L sentient-, sentiens, prp of
    sentire to perceive, feel (1632) 1 responsive
    to or conscious of sense impressions 2 AWARE 3
    finely sensitive in perception or feeling.
    Merriam-Websters Collegiate Dictionary, Tenth
    Edition.)
  • Kant labeled this approach to ethics
    anthropological, and found it impure.

73
SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY I
  • What Sommers likes about the empirical approach
    of Hume, which is based on feeling, is that
    cruelty or brutality to any sentient being is
    the very paradigm of indecent, inadmissable
    behavior.
  • Sommers According to Kant, animals are not in
    the domain of moral patients and we have no
    direct duty to be kind to them. We do have an
    indirect duty to refrain from acts of cruelty to
    animals because such behavior could corrupt our
    character, and this could affect the way we
    behave to rational beings to whom we do owe
    respect.

74
SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY II
  • For Kant then, and the tradition which bases
    morality on reason, the idea is not that we
    should respect animals other than humans because
    of their capacity to feel pain, or that
    mistreating animals is not wrong in itself
    because animals then suffer, but because to
    mistreat an animal could adversely affect the way
    we treat each other.
  • Thus the mistreatment of animals is not wrong
    because animals are mistreated, but because the
    mistreatment of animals could lead to the
    mistreatment of humans.

75
SENTIENCE AND THE MORAL COMMUNITY III
  • The problem with the Kantian philosophy on this
    issue, for Sommers, is that anyone who would not
    be corrupted by mistreating animals would not be
    doing wrong to mistreat them.
  • For Sommers, this shows that there is something
    wrong with the rationalist approach to ethics of
    Kant and his followers.

76
THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS I
  • Recall how sympathy loses to a bad morality for
    Himmler when, although he has sympathy for his
    victims, he recognizes that it is his duty to
    eliminate them.
  • Sommers recognizes that the treatment of the Jews
    by the Nazis would surely have horrified Kant,
    but a moral philosophy which does not directly
    proscribe cruelty to nonpersons makes it
    possible to mistreat any being which is not
    thought to qualify as a person.
  • For the Nazis, Jews did not qualify as persons.
    Accordingly, Sommers then points out that, If
    Jews are like insects, killing them is not a
    crime against humanity.

77
THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS II
  • Of course, the Kantian could say here that
    killing or mistreating Jews is wrong for the same
    reason that mistreating dogs is wrong, because of
    its effect on the people who mistreat them. That
    is, by mistreating Jews, even though Jews are
    nonpersons, we might lead us to mistreat persons.
  • Sommers point though is that Kantian ethics
    allows for the mistreatment of certain peoples
    because they can be reclassified as nonpersons.

78
THE NAZI TREATMENT OF THE JEWS III
  • Sommers does not think that this reclassification
    of persons as nonpersons does not and will not
    happen in any moral philosophy which is based on
    feeling rather than on rationality.
  • Thus he says that A people steeped in the
    sentimentalist moral philosophy such as that of
    Locke, Hume, or Mill regards all sentient beings
    those capable of feeling and sensation, or
    pleasure and pain as moral patients. as
    deserving of moral consideration. And such a
    people would view an openly cruel leader like
    Hitler as unacceptably immoral.

79
THE DANGER OF THE GERMAN RATIONAL TRADITION I
  • For Sommers, any ethics which is based on the
    notions of duty and respect rather than on
    kindness and compassion is wrong and dangerous.
  • The formal approach to ethics taken by Kant which
    is based on duty to rational agents leaves other
    being worthy of moral consideration outside of
    the moral community.
  • And it leaves open the possibility that certain
    beings who we would normally consider to be part
    of the moral community, such as Jews, would not
    be considered persons, and therefore not morally
    protected.

80
THE DANGER OF THE GERMAN RATIONAL TRADITION II
  • Such an arbitrary drawing of moral boundaries
    cannot happen for any ethics which is based on
    benevolence and human compassion.
  • And this is the case for the British tradition in
    ethics in which the focus is on basic sentience
    and feeling.
  • Sommers concludes by saying that a moral theory
    that does not absolutely, directly, and
    foundationally anathematize cruelty must be ruled
    out of court.
  • According to Sommers, the German rational
    tradition does not do this, and so is not only
    inferior to the British tradition, but is
    dangerous.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)