Title: Political Economy: Critique of Neoclassical Economics
1Political Economy Critique of Neoclassical
Economics
- Wrong answers to the wrong questions Demand
2Why Political Economy?
- Reject questions asked by mainstream economics
- Neoclassical economics asks the wrong questions
- Assumptions of individual utility/profit
maximisation omit social interaction, social
conflict, gender issues, etc. - Equilibrium hangup ignores dynamic processes
- Internally inconsistencies in mainstream
economics - Provides wrong answers to questions it does ask
- Demand theory cant derive downward sloping
market curve - Profit maximising firms dont produce where
marginal revenue equals marginal cost - General equilibrium cant be in equilibrium
- How do neoclassical economists cope?
3Why Political Economy?
- Ignore the problem!
- Capital aggregation problem (Cambridge
Controversies) ignored - Income distribution adding up problem (Shaikh)
ignored - Assume the problem away
- Assume identical consumers to avoid demand curve
aggregation problem (SMD conditions) - In a nutshell assume a miracle
4But it all looks so neat!
- Great appeal of neoclassical economics an
apparently coherent picture of a complex system - Individual preferences generate demand curves
- Profit maximising generates supply curves
- Intersection determines prices outputs
- Markets harmonise in general equilibrium
- Welfare maximised by free market
- Great weakness of neoclassical economics
- All steps in above process have logical flaws
- Firstly, a recap of the neoclassical vision
- With this bloke turning up whenever the theory
glosses over a crucial problem
5Consumer demand
- Consumers demand determined by preferences
- A rational consumer
- Does not let income affect tastes
- Always prefers more to less
- Gets less utility out of each additional unit
(diminishing marginal utility) - Can always tell which bundle he/she prefers
- End result
- Tastes can be represented by indifference map
- Prices incomes determine budget
- Interaction of these determines demand curve
- Fall in price necessarily increases consumers
welfare
6Consumer demand
Z
- Indifference curves show tastes
X
Biscuits
- Points on Z preferred to X
- Prices Income gives budget
- Budget line II banana price p1 cheaper than p2
for line I
Y
W
q1
q2
q3
II
III
I
Bananas
- Hey presto
- downward sloping demand curve!
- consumer welfare ? as P ?
- Points of tangency give maximum utility at given
relative prices
p1
p2
Price of Bananas
Consumer Surplus
- Price/quantity combos show the demand curve
p3
q1
Bananas
q2
q3
7Consumer demand
Z
- A caveat income substitution effects
- Can get upward-sloping demand curve if (positive)
income effect outweighs (negative) substitution
effect - Solution Hicksian compensated demand curve
- Notionally reduce income back to original
indifference curve
X
Y
W
q1
q2
q3
II
III
I
Bananas
- Hicksian demand curve necessarily slopes down
p1
p2
Price of Bananas
p3
q1
Bananas
q2
q3
8Consumer demand
- Now add lots of consumers together
- And we get a downward sloping demand curve where
consumer welfare rises as price falls
Price of Bananas
The demand curve
Bananas
- Now stage two the upward-sloping supply curve
9Supply
- Producers are short run profit maximisers
- Goods produced by combining factors of production
- In the short run, the quantity of one factor is
fixed - Output is increased by adding more of the
variable factor (labour) to the fixed factor
(capital) - Production function therefore displays
diminishing marginal productivity output
eventually rises at diminishing rate - Falling marginal product
- Rising marginal cost
10Supply
- Marginal product can initially rise
- But ultimately it falls
- Falling marginal product mean rising marginal cost
Zero marginal product
Banana Output
Rising marginal product
Maximum marginal product
A
B
Labour Input
- Divide cost of input (constant wage) by
additional amount produced (falling) and you have
rising marginal cost
Marginal Product
Infinite marginal cost
Lowest marginal cost
A
B
Labour Input (capital fixed)
11Supply
- Firms profit maximise by equating marginal
revenue marginal cost because that identifies
the biggest gap between total revenue and total
cost
Slope of TRMR
Slope of TCMC
- Marginal revenue falls with rising output for a
monopoly - But a competitive firm is so small that, as a
price taker, it doesnt affect market price. So
its total revenue is a straight line
Maximum profitwhere MRMC
12Supply
- Since price is constant for a competitive firm,
marginal revenue equals price
- Competitive firm maximises profit by supplying on
marginal cost curve - Marginal cost curve becomes firms supply curve
- Sum of all firms MC curves is industry supply
curve
13Supply Demand
- Houston, we have equilibrium
- With maximum social welfare
P
S
PMgtMC
Consumer Surplus
- But assuming all markets are competitive, we can
have general equilibrium
PCMC
Producer Surplus
D
MR
QM
Q
QC
14General equilibrium
- All markets in instantaneous equilibrium
- Complete coordination of all markets without
external intervention
Was equilibrium good for you too?
- Social welfare maximised by the free market
- But now lets check the fine print
15Consumer Demand
- Adding lots of consumers together
- With one individual
- unambiguous link between preferences
(indifference curves) demand curve - Fall in price unambiguously benefits consumer
- With more than one individual
Biscuits
- Houston, we have a problem
Bananas
16Consumer Demand
- Two different incomparable sets of indifference
curves - Point of tangency for one wont be for the other
- Income effect may work in opposite directions for
two consumers (one might consume less as price
falls, the other more) - Income effects of changing prices
- Change in relative prices changes income/wealth
- One-person analysis assumes prices can be changed
without affecting income - Cant assume same for 2 or more persons
- Cant alter prices without affecting incomes
17Consumer Demand
Z
- E.g., banana price rise increases wealth
- With one consumer, no problem keeping prices
income/wealth separate
X
Biscuits
- With two consumers, even if their tastes are
identical, can no longer separate prices from
incomes/wealth
Y
W
q1
q2
q3
II
III
I
Bananas
- Any shape of market demand curve can result
- Two outcomes of these dilemmas
p1
- Demand rises as price rises
p2
Price of Bananas
p3
q1
Bananas
q2
q3
q3
q1
18Consumer Demand
- (1) Standard individual law of demand (that
demand rises as price falls) does not apply at
market level - Market demand curves can have any shape at all
- every polynomial is an excess demand function
for a specified commodity in some n commodity
economy every real-valued function is
approximately an excess demand function.
(Sonnenschein 1972 550) - (2) To guarantee that a market demand curve
slopes down like an individual demand curve,
consumers effectively need to be identical and
have tastes that dont change with income
19Consumer Demand
- If
- (1) The marginal propensity to consume a good is
the same for all consumers - i.e., you have the same marginal propensity to
buy Da Vincis original manuscripts as Bill
Gates - Bill Gates has the same marginal propensity to
buy methylated spirits as a derelict AND - (2) The marginal propensity to consume a good
doesnt change with income - When Bill Gates earned 100 a week, he spent the
last 10 on pizza - Now that he earns 100,000,000 a week, he spends
10,000,000 on pizza - Then the market demand curve will slope downwards
20Consumer Demand
- Conditions in effect amount to
- All consumers are identical
- All commodities are identical
- i.e., model only works with one consumer one
commodity - When scaled to gt 1 consumer and gt 1 commodity,
aggregation effects mean what applies at
individual level doesnt apply at aggregate - Result is general
- Doesnt depend on perverse utility functions
- Makes it impossible to derive meaningful
aggregate (market) laws from principle of
individual utility maximisation
21Consumer Demand
- market demand functions need not satisfy in any
way the classical restrictions which characterize
consumer demand functions The importance of the
above results is clear strong restrictions are
needed in order to justify the hypothesis that a
market demand function has the characteristics of
a consumer demand function. Only in special cases
can an economy be expected to act as an
idealized consumer. The utility hypothesis
tells us nothing about market demand unless it is
augmented by additional requirements. (Shafer
Sonnenschein 1982 671-2 emphasis added)
22Consumer Demand
- Maybe class-based analysis is necessary?
- If we are to progress further we may well be
forced to theorise in terms of groups who have
collectively coherent behaviour. Thus demand and
expenditure functions if they are to be set
against reality must be defined at some
reasonably high level of aggregation. The idea
that we should start at the level of the isolated
individual is one which we may well have to
abandon. (Kirman 1989 138) - Post Keynesians Marxists work in terms of
groups (workers, capitalists, bankers) rather
than individuals
23Consumer Demand
- In general market demand curves (derived from
neoclassical theory) look like this
Price of Bananas
The demand curve
Bananas
- Even if consumers utility maximise!
- Which they dont
24Indifference Curves
- Seen any good indifference curves lately?
- Dilemma indifference curves play crucial role in
theory, but unobservable - Samuelson suggested a solution revealed
preference - Induce consumers preference map from their
purchasing decisions. - What we want to find is
25Indifference Curves
- What we can know is what a consumer actually buys
at different prices
- Samuelson argued we can infer the indifference
map from these
- Using revealed preference the axioms of
rational behaviour - Consumer can rank all bundles in terms of
preference/indifference - More preferred to less
- If A pref B B pref C then A pref C
Biscuits
Y
W
X
q1
q2
q3
P2
P3
P1
Bananas
26Indifference Curves
- All points in box preferred to A (non-satiation)
- Can build up map of consumers tastes by
offering different bundles of goods at different
prices, seeing which bundles chosen - reveal preferences
- If A preferred to B C at one price, must be
preferred at any price (completeness
transitivity tastes independent of income) - A must be on higher curve than B or C
27Indifference Curves
- Sippel (1997) attempted to do just this reveal
preferences of experimental subjects - 10 sets of Budget relative prices presented
- Budgets/prices chosen to test aspects of theory
(e.g., Homogeneity degree zerodouble prices
incomes, should be no change in consumption - Choose from 8 goods at each budget/price combo
- Computer automatically calculated budget cost
- Consume choices in next hour from one of ten sets
28Indifference Curves
- Unlimited amount of time to choose
- 60 minutes to consume one choice set
29Indifference Curves
- Key propositions being tested
- Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference WARP
- If A ? B then never B ? A
- If consumer chooses bundle A once when B also
affordable, then consumer will always choose A
instead of B, regardless of relative prices - Strong Axiom of Revealed Preference SARP
- If A ? B B ? C then never C ? A
- Formal definition of a utility maximiser
- Generalised Axiom of Revealed Preference GARP
- If A ? B B ? C then pC A ? pC C
- If A ? B B ? C then A more expensive than set C
at prices when C declined in favour of B
30Indifference Curves
- Results first experiment (12 subjects)
- 11 of 12 subjects violated SARP WARP
- 5 out of 12 violated weaker test GARP
- Results second experiment (30 subjects)
- 22 of 30 subjects violated SARP WARP
- 19 of 30 violated weaker test GARP
31Indifference Curves
- Sippels interpretation of results
- In general not too favourable to the
neoclassical theory of consumer behaviour (p.
1438) but - Low number of inconsistencies (median 2 out of
45but average higher) - Subjects did try to select a combination of
goods that came as close as possible to what they
really liked to consume given their respective
budget constraints (1439) - They spent a considerable amount of time on
their decisions (typically 30-40 minutes) - How serious are violations of axioms?
32Indifference Curves
- Use waste of income from inconsistent choice as
guide to how significant were deviations from
rationality - Afriat index ratio (pB A / pB B) when (from
previous experimental round) A ? B - Where consumer chooses A when B affordable, use
formula A ? B if (e pA A) ? (pA B) - Consumer deemed to prefer A over B if A (say)
11 more expensive than B consumer still
chooses A (here e0.9) - Like having thicker indifference curves
33Indifference Curves
- With thicker indifference curves, more
combinations are shown as indifferent
Biscuits
C
A
B
- Choosing A or B appears rational for e.95 but
not for e1
Bananas
- The good news number of apparent violations of
GARP dropped significantly for elt1 - The bad news even throwing a darttotally
random choiceappeared rational for elt0.95! - For e.9, random choice appeared more rational
than what human subjects did!
34Indifference Curves
35Indifference Curves
- Several other careful attempts to interpret
results - But overall judgment
- We conclude that the evidence for the utility
maximisation hypothesis is at best mixed. While
there are subjects who do appear to be
optimising, the majority of them do not we
call the universality of the maximising principle
into question. (1442) - So if people arent maximising their utility,
what are they doing? - Are they being irrational?
No!
- Its the neoclassical definition of rational
behaviour that is irrational!
36How rational is optimising?
- Neoclassical model a toy model of behavior
- Only 2 commodities, unspecified quantities
- Lets make it real
- Shopping in a supermarket with 1,000 different
commodities - Decide whether to or not to buy one unit of each
- How many bundles do you have to consider?
- For the textbook toy model, only 4
- (0 bananas, 0 biscuits 1 banana, 0 biscuits 0
bananas, 1 biscuit 1 banana, 1 biscuit) - In the supermarket?
37How rational is optimising?
- Number of choices is
- Number of units being considered 1 (0 or 1)
- Raised to the power of how many goods
- 2 in textbook modelso only 4 combinations
- 2 goods, 22 4 combinations
- supermarket 1,000 goods
- How many combinations?
38How rational is optimising?
- 21000, or roughly 10300.
- So is that big, or what?
- Spelling it out in full, its
- 10,720, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000, 000,
000 combinations!
So is that big, or what?
39How rational is optimising?
- How big a brain would you need to remember that
many combinations? - Pretend each neurone could remember the utility
of 100,000,000,000 combinations - Your grey matter weighs about a kilo
100,000,000,000 neurones, each weighing
1/100,000,000 grams - Quick quiz a brain this big would weigh
- (1) More than your brain?
- (2) More than an elephant?
- (3) More than the planet?
- (4) More than the Sun?
- (5) More than the Galaxy?
- (6) More?
40How rational is optimising?
- (6) 10224 times as much as the entire universe!
- If you could recall utility of each combination
in 1/10,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,00
0,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,
000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000th of a
second, how long would it take to remember the
maximum? - 10200 seconds 10180 times the age of the
universe! - Whats going on?
- The curse of dimensionality number of
combinations grows exponentially as more options
considered - Impossible to consider even tiny fraction of
options in effectively finite time - Dimensionality overwhelmed Sippels subjects,
even with just 8 commodities experimental setup
replicating neoclassical theory
41How rational is optimising?
- Rational behavior is not considering all options,
but - Reducing number you do consider in a way that
- Makes deciding in finite time possible
- Doesnt obviously rule out good combinations
- We use heuristics sensible rules of thumb
- We do consider our budgets when deciding tastes
- We use habit, convention, culture
- Buy much the same combination each week
- We segment our purchases x on food, y on
clothing - Tastes evolve over time (with marketing trying to
manipulate development)
42How rational is optimising?
- These non-optimising behaviors make choice
possible - E.g., segmentation rather than optimise over
everything in supermarket, segment into fruit,
meat, spices, hygiene, etc. - Say 1000 products in supermarket, 100 in each
segment - Unsegmented optimising Buy/not buy 10300
combinations - Segmented optimising Buy/not buy 1031
combinations10269 less could remember
everything with a brain weighing only 1 million
tonnes! - More than segmentation needed! But optimising
behaviour is clearly not rational
43What should economists do instead?
- Abandon ambition to build coherent model of
aggregate (market) behavior from isolated
individuals - Model at some reasonably high level of
aggregation (Kirman)classes (capitalists,
bankers, workers) or - Model actual behavior at individual level
- Satisficing (Herbert Simons) rather than
optimising multi-agent modelling - Generate non-coherent model of aggregate
behaviour (waves of demand, non-equilibrium
dynamics, co-evolution of products and demand) - These approaches being taken by Marxist, Post
Keynesian, Evolutionary economists but not by
neoclassicals (best offer game theory)
44Political economy attitude
- Methodological individualism of neoclassical
economics fails on own grounds - Internally inconsistent
- Does not reach results they desire
- Socially coherent approach of Marxists, Post
Keynesians, Evolutionary, Feminist economists
superior - Methodological individualism should be abandoned
in favour of analysis of social groups/classes,
income distribution between classes, etc. - Next week, theory of the firm