COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice

Description:

This is a hawk-dove game. Winner type replaces loser type. ... payoff, there is an evolutionarily stable solution that is 50/50 hawks and doves. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:18
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 39
Provided by: Ken673
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice


1
COS 444 Internet AuctionsTheory and Practice
Spring 2009 Ken Steiglitz
ken_at_cs.princeton.edu
2
the bigger picture, all single item
Myerson 1981 optimal, not efficient asymmetric
bidders
3
Moving to asymmetric bidders
  • Efficiency item goes to bidder with highest
    value
  • Very important in some situations!
  • Second-price auctions remain efficient in
    asymmetric (IPV) case. Why?
  • First-price auctions do not

4
Inefficiency in FP with asymmetric bidders
5
New setup Myerson 81, also BR 89
wins Nobel prize for this and related work, 2007
  • Vector of values v
  • Allocation function Q (v )
  • Qi (v ) is prob. i wins item
  • Payment function P (v )
  • Pi (v ) is expected payment of i
  • Subsumes Ars easily (check SP, FP)
  • The pair (Q , P ) is called a
  • Direct Mechanism

6
New setup Myerson 81
  • Definition When agents who participate in a
    mechanism have no incentive to lie about their
    values, we say the mechanism is incentive
    compatible.
  • The Revelation Principle In so far as
    equilibrium behavior is concerned, any auction
    mechanism can be replaced by an
    incentive-compatible direct mechanism.

7
Revelation Principle
  • Proof Replace the bid-taker with a direct
    mechanism that computes equilibrium values for
    the bidders. Then a bidder can bid equilibrium
    simply by being truthful, and there is never an
    incentive to lie. ?
  • This principle is very general and includes
    any sort of negotiation!

8
(No Transcript)
9
Asymmetric bidders
  • We can therefore restrict attention to
    incentive-compatible direct mechanisms!
  • Note In the asymmetric case, expected surplus is
    no longer vi F(z) n-1 - P(z)
  • (bidding as if value z )
  • Next we write expected surplus in the
    asymmetric case

10
Asymmetric bidders
  • Notation v-i vector v with the i th
  • Value omitted. Then the prob. that i wins is
  • Where V-i is the space of all vs except vi and
  • F (v-i ) is the corresponding distribution

11
Asymmetric bidders
  • Similarly for the expected payment of bidder i
  • Expected surplus is then

12
A yet more general RET
  • Differentiate wrt z and set to zero when z
    vi
  • as usual
  • But now take the total derivative wrt vi when z
    vi
  • And so

13
yet more general RE
  • Integrate
  • Or, using S vQ P ,
  • ?In equilibrium, expected payment of every bidder
    depends only on allocation function Q !

14
Optimal allocation
  • Average over vi and proceed as in RS81
  • where

?no longer a common F
15
Optimal allocation, cont
  • The total expected revenue is
  • For participation, Pi (0 ) 0, and seller
    chooses Pi (0) 0 to max surplus. Therefore

16
Optimal allocation, cont
When Pi (0 ) 0 we say bidders are individually
rational They dont participate in auctions if
the expected payment with zero value is positive.
17
Optimal allocation
  • The optimal allocation can now be seen by
    inspection!
  • For each vector of vs, Look for the maximum
    value of MRi (vi ). Say it occurs at i i , and
    denote it by MR .
  • If MR gt 0, then choose that Qi to be 1 and all
    the other Qs to be 0 (bidder i gets the item)
  • If MR 0, then hold on to the item (seller
    retains item)

18
Optimal allocation (inefficient!)
19
Payment rule
  • Hint must reduce to second-price when bidders
    are symmetric
  • Therefore Pay the least you can while still
    maintaining the highest MR
  • This is incentive compatible that is, bidders
    bid truthfully! Why?

20
Vickrey 61 yet again
21
Wrinkle
  • For this argument to work, MR must be an
    increasing function. We call F s with increasing
    MRs regular. (Uniform is regular)
  • Its sufficient for the inverse hazard rate
  • (1 F) / f to be decreasing.
  • Can be fixed See Myerson 81 (ironing)
  • Assume MR is regular in what follows

22
  • Notice also that this asks a lot of bidders in
    the asymmetric case. In the direct mechanism the
    bidders must understand enough to be truthful,
    and accept the fact that the highest value
    doesnt always win.
  • Or, think of MRi(vi) as is bid
  • As usual in game-theoretic settings,
    distributions are common knowledge---at least the
    hypothetical auctioneer must know them.

23
In the symmetric caseArs are optimal mechanisms!
  • By the revelation principle, we can restrict
    attention to direct mechanisms
  • An optimal direct mechanism in the symmetric case
    awards item to the highest-value bidder, and so
    does any auction in Ars
  • All direct mechanisms with the same allocation
    rule have the same revenue
  • Therefore any auction in Ars has the same
    allocation rule, and hence revenue, as an optimal
    (general!) mechanism

Includes any sort of negotiation whatsoever!
24
Efficiency
  • Second-price auctions are efficient --- i.e.,
    they allocate the item to the buyer who values it
    the most. (Even in asymm. case, truthful is
    dominant.)
  • Weve seen that optimal (revenue-maximizing)
    auctions in the asymmetric case are in general
    inefficient.
  • It turns out that second-price auctions are
    optimal in the class of efficient auctions. They
    generalize in the multi-item case to the
    Vickrey-Clark-Groves (VCG) mechanisms. More
    later.

25
Laboratory Evidence
  • Generally, there are three kinds of empirical
    methodologies
  • Field observations
  • Field experiments
  • Laboratory experiments
  • ?Problem people may not behave the same way in
    the lab as in the world
  • ?Problem people differ in behavior
  • ?Problem people learn from experience

26
Laboratory Evidence
  • Conclusions fall into two general categories
  • Revenue ranking
  • Point predictions (usually revenue relative to
    Nash equilibrium)

For more detail, see J. H. Kagel, "Auctions A
Survey of Experimental Research", in The Handbook
of Experimental Economics, J. Kagel and A. Roth
(eds.), Princeton Univ. Press, 1995.
27
Best revenue-ranking results for IPV model
  • Second-Price gt English Kagel et al. (87)
  • English ? truthfulNash Kagel et al. (87)
  • First-Price ? Second-Price
  • First-Price gt Dutch Coppinger et al. (80)
  • First-Price gt Nash Dyer et al. (89)
  • Thus, generally,
  • sealed versions gt open versions!

28
  • A violation of theory is the
    scientists best news!
  • Lets discuss some of the violations
  • Second-Price gt English. These are (weakly)
    strategically equivalent. But
  • English ? truthful Nash.
  • What hint towards an explanation does the
    weakly give us?

29
  • First-Price gt Dutch. These are strongly
    strategically equivalent. But recall
    Lucking-Reileys pre-eBay internet test with
    Magic cards, where Dutch gt FP by 30!
  • Whats going on here?

30
  • See also Kagel Levin 93 for experiments with
    3rd-price auctions that test IPV theory
  • More about experimental results for common-value
    auctions later
  • We next focus for a while on a widely accepted
    point prediction
  • One explanation, as weve seen, is
  • risk aversion
  • But is here is an alternative explanation

First-price gt Nash
31
Spite MSR 03 MS 03
  • Suppose bidders care about the surplus of other
    bidders as well their own.
  • Simple example Two bidders, second-price,
    values iid unifom on 0,1. Suppose bidder 2 bids
    truthfully, and suppose bidder 1s utility is not
    her own surplus, but the difference ? between
    hers and her rivals.

32
Spite
  • Now bidder 1 wants to choose her bid b1 to
    maximize the expectation of
  • where I is the indicator function, 1 when
    true, 0 else.
  • Taking expectation over v2

33
Spite
  • Maximizing wrt b1 yields best response to
    truthful bidding
  • Intuition?

34
Spite
  • Maximizing wrt b1 yields best response to
    truthful bidding
  • Intuition by overbidding, 1 loses surplus when
    2s bid is between v1 and her bid. But, this is
    more than offset by forcing 2 to pay more when he
    wins.
  • Notice that bidder 2 still cannot increase his
    absolute surplus. (Why not?) He must take a hit
    to compete in a pairwise knockout tournament.

35
Spite
  • Some results from MSR 03 take the case when
    bidders want to maximize the difference between
    their own surplus and that of their rivals.
    Values distributed as F, n bidders. Then
  • ? FP equilibrium is the same as in the
    risk-averse CRRA case with ? ½ (utility is t1/2
    ). Thus there is overbidding.
  • ? SP equilibrium is to overbid according to

36
Spite
  • ? Revenue ranking is SP gt FP.
  • (Not a trivial proof. Is there a simpler
    one?)
  • Thus, this revenue ranking is the opposite of the
    prediction in the risk-averse case, where there
    is overbidding in FP but not in SP. (Testable
    prediction.)
  • This explains overbidding in both first- and
    second-price auctions, while risk-aversion
    explains only the first. (Testable prediction.)
  • Raises a question do you think people bid
    differently against machines than against people?

37
Spiteful behavior in biology
  • This model can also explain spiteful behavior in
    biological contexts, where individuals fight for
    survival one-on-one MS 03. Example
  • This is a hawk-dove game.
  • Winner type replaces loser type.
  • In a large population where the success of an
    individual is determined by average individual
    payoff, there is an evolutionarily stable
    solution that is 50/50 hawks and doves.
  • If winners are determined by relative payoff in
    each 1-1 contest, the hawks drive out the doves.
  • Thus, there is an Invasion of the Spiteful
    Mutants!

38
Invasion of the spiteful mutants
  • To see this, suppose in the large population
    there is a fraction ? of Hs and (1-? ) of Ds.
  • The average payoff to an H in a contest is
  • and to a D
  • The first is greater than the second iff ?lt1/2. A
    50/50 mixture is an equilibrium.
  • But if the winner of a contest is determined by
    who has the greater payoff, an H always replaces
    a D!
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com