Pascals Wager and James Will to Believe - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 35
About This Presentation
Title:

Pascals Wager and James Will to Believe

Description:

... the standpoint of practical reason, the only rational thing to do is to believe in God. ... success of the exiles in their strange new home that was to be. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:88
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 36
Provided by: spry
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Pascals Wager and James Will to Believe


1
Pascals Wager and James Will to Believe
  • Blaise Pascal was a 17th Century French
    Philosopher and Mathematician.
  • Developed the Probability Calculus.
  • Lived a lascivious lifestyle until he had a
    profound religious vision, at which point he
    became a very devout Christian.
  • Developed his Wager as an appeal to former
    friends, who were still living a lascivious
    lifestyle.
  • Pascal believed his Wager shows that, from the
    standpoint of practical reason, the only rational
    thing to do is to believe in God.

2

3
  • Comments
  • If someone likes to go for broke, then he should
    believe because that choice has the best positive
    payoff.
  • If someone likes to play it safe, then he
    should believe because that choice has the least
    negative payoff.
  • Why cant I just not believe and be agnostic?
  • Being agnostic is the same as not believing.

4
  • When Pascal talks about believing in God, hes
    NOT just talking about believing that God exists.
  • Hes talking about adopting the lifestyle that
    goes with believing that God exists.
  • One cannot live agnostically.
  • One either lives a religious lifestyle or not.

5
  • We are . . . embarked . . . , as on a ship.
    The ship is our life. The sea is time. We are
    moving past a port that claims to be our true
    home . . . . This home port . . . is not just
    an idea (that God exists). It is a marriage
    proposal from this God. Not to say yes is
    eventually to say no. Suppose Romeo proposes to
    Juliet, and she says neither yes nor no, but
    wait. Suppose the wait lasts and lasts until
    she dies. Then, her wait becomes no. Death
    turns agnosticism into atheism. For, death turns
    tomorrow into never.
  • Peter Kreeft, Christianity for Modern Pagans

6
  • How can there be a finite gain if I believe in
    God and he doesnt exist?
  • You will be faithful, honest, humble, grateful,
    generous, a sincere friend, truthful.
  • Blaise Pascal, Pensées, No.233
  • The Wager is too mercenary.
  • The Wager can easily be recast to appeal to a
    higher motive than the fear of Hell. One could
    wager as follows

7
  • If God exists as the Supreme Being, he
    deserves all my allegiance and faith. I dont
    know whether he exists or not. Therefore, to
    avoid the terrible injustice of refusing God his
    rights, I will believe.
  • Peter Kreeft, Christianity for Modern Pagans

8
  • Faith in God is not something that you can just
    turn on, like turning on the hot water.
  • You want to find faith, and you do not know the
    road. You want to be cured of unbelief, and you
    ask for the remedy Learn from those who were
    once . . . like you and now wager all they have.
  • Blaise Pascal, Pensées, No. 233

9
  • In The Brothers Karamazov, Madame Hohlokov
    comes to Father Zossima distraught at losing
    her childish faith by exposure to science and
    philosophy . . . . Wise old Zossima tells her
    that it is not possible simply to go back to her
    childhood, forget her doubts and believe naively
    . . . . But, there is . . . a way to become
    certain. It is the way of active love, acting as
    if she believed, loving her neighbors
    indefatigably.

10
  • Then, she will see the image of God in the souls
    of her neighbors. Love will grow eyes in her
    heart, but only if she exercises it, only if she
    loves in action, not just in thought . . . . I
    can tell you nothing more comforting than this.
    says Father Zossima For, love in action is a
    harsh and dreadful thing compared with love in
    dreams
  • Peter Kreeft, Christianity for Modern Pagans

11
  • In the end, Pascal is asking non-believers to
    try the religious lifestyle for awhile, since, as
    the Wager shows, it clearly pays.
  • Pascal is confident that, given a fair chance,
    genuine faith will grow.
  • I tell you You would soon have faith, if you
    give up a life of pleasure. Now, it is up to you
    to begin. If I could give you faith, I would,
    but I cannot . . . . You can easily give up
    your pleasure and test whether I am telling the
    truth.
  • Blaise Pascal, Pensées, No. 240

12
  • Final Thoughts
  • Does Pascal underestimate the difficulty of
    trying to live a religious lifestyle when one
    does not already believe?
  • Pascal himself did not come to faith until he had
    his religious vision.
  • Is his challenge unfair to sincere non-believers?

13
  • William James vs. the Evidentialist Objection
  • Recall Pascals Position
  • From the standpoint of speculative reason, one
    can neither prove nor disprove Gods existence.
  • One, however, should believe in God because, from
    the standpoint of practical reason, believing in
    God has the best pay-off.

14
  • One who raises the Evidentialist Objection
    maintains that, since there is insufficient
    evidence for Gods existence, one should not
    believe in God. One should be agnostic.
  • This claim rests on the more basic claim that
    one should never believe in anything without
    sufficient evidence for the existence of that
    thing.
  • In the words of one of the most prominent
    Evidentialist Objectors

15
  • It is morally wrong always, everywhere, and
    for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient
    evidence.
  • William Clifford, The Ethics of Belief
  • Rationale behind Cliffords Ethics of Belief
  • Clifford tells a story
  • A ship owner was about to send to sea an
    emigrant ship. He knew that she was old and not
    over-well built at the first,

16
  • that she had seen many seas and climes and often
    had needed repairs. Doubts had been suggested to
    him that possibly she was not seaworthy. These
    doubts preyed upon his mind and made him unhappy
    he thought that perhaps he ought to have her
    thoroughly overhauled and refitted, even though
    this should put him to great expense. Before the
    ship sailed, however,

17
  • he succeeded in overcoming these melancholy
    reflections. He said to himself that she had
    gone safely through so many voyages and weathered
    so many storms, that it was idle to suppose she
    would not come safely home from this trip also.
    He would put his trust in Providence, which could
    hardly fail to protect all these unhappy families
    that were leaving their fatherland to seek for
    better times elsewhere.

18
  • He would dismiss from his mind all ungenerous
    suspicions about the honesty of builders and
    contractors. In such ways he acquired a sincere
    and comfortable conviction that his vessel was
    thoroughly safe and seaworthy. He watched her
    departure with a light heart and benevolent
    wishes for the success of the exiles in their
    strange new home that was to be. And he got his
    insurance money when she went down in mid-ocean
    and told no tales.
  • William Clifford, The Ethics of Belief

19
  • One thing to note is that Cliffords dramatic
    tale is really irrelevant to his claim.
  • Clifford claims that it is always morally wrong
    to believe on insufficient evidence.
  • The ship owner in the story, however, does not
    believe on insufficient evidence. He believes
    contrary to sufficient evidence.

20
  • There is sufficient evidence the ship is not
    seaworthy, but, despite this evidence, the ship
    owner believes it is seaworthy.
  • Credulity
  • Despite the rather inflammatory story with which
    he begins, Cliffords real reason for maintaining
    one should never believe on insufficient evidence
    is NOT that doing so might lead to false beliefs
    that produce disasters.

21
  • Whats really horrible about believing on
    insufficient evidence is that doing so makes a
    person credulous, i.e. makes him such that he
    will believe anything at all.
  • If I let myself believe anything on
    insufficient evidence, there may be no great harm
    done by the mere belief it may be true after
    all, or I may never have occasion to exhibit it
    in outward acts. But, I cannot help doing this
    great wrong

22
  • towards Man That I make myself credulous. The
    danger to society is not merely that it should
    believe wrong things, though that is great
    enough but that it should become credulous, and
    lose the habit of testing things and inquiring
    into them for then it must sink back into
    savagery.
  • William Clifford The Ethics of Belief

23
  • The Will to Believe
  • Essay written in response to Cliffords by the
    great Harvard philosopher and psychologist
    William James
  • Contra Clifford, James maintains it is sometimes
    morally permissible to believe on insufficient
    evidence.
  • James maintains two conditions must be met in
    order for it to be permissible to believe
    something on insufficient evidence.

24
  • The matter must be intellectually undecidable,
    i.e. it must be very unlikely that you will ever
    have enough evidence to settle the matter one way
    or another.
  • The choice in question must represent a genuine
    option.
  • Living, i.e each alternative must have some
    initial plausibility. For example, in the
    contemporary West Be a Protestant or be a
    Catholic is a living option. In the
    contemporary West Be a Manichean or be a
    Christian is not a living option.

25
  • Forced, i.e. one must choose one alternative or
    another. There is no third alternative, e.g.
    Accept my love or live without it.
  • Momentous, i.e. the benefits that would accrue
    by choosing truly are very significant and
    unique. One cannot gain these benefits in any
    other way

26
  • If I were Dr. Nansen and proposed to you to
    join my North Pole expedition, your option would
    be momentous for this would probably be your
    only similar opportunity, and your choice now
    would either exclude you from the North Pole sort
    of immortality altogether or put at least the
    chance of it into your hands. He who refuses to
    embrace a unique opportunity loses the prize as
    surely as if he tried and failed.
  • William James, The Will to Believe

27
  • James claims that the choice between believing
    in God and not believing in Him is both
    intellectually undecidable and a genuine option.
  • Both alternatives have initial plausibility.
  • The choice is forced, for, as Pascal pointed out,
    one cannot live agnostically.
  • Also, as Pascal also pointed out, the benefits of
    believing truly in God are infinite.

28
  • James response to Cliffords charge of
    encouraging credulity
  • James points out that humans have two epistemic
    goals.
  • To attain truth
  • To avoid falsehood
  • Clifford concentrates on the latter goal to the
    exclusion of the former.
  • Does Clifford, however, have sufficient evidence
    for doing this? No, says James.

29
  • Better go without belief forever than believe a
    lie! merely shows Cliffords own preponderant
    private horror of becoming a dupe. He may be
    critical of many of his desires and fears, but
    this fear he slavishly obeys. He cannot imagine
    any one questioning its binding force. For my
    own part, I have also a horror of being duped
    but I can believe that worse things than being
    duped may happen to a man in this world.

30
  • So Cliffords exhortation has to my ears a
    thoroughly fantastic sound. It is like a general
    informing his soldiers that it is better to keep
    out of battle forever than to risk a single
    wound. Not so are victories either over enemies
    or over nature gained. Our errors are surely not
    such awfully solemn things. In a world where we
    are so certain to incur them in spite of all our
    caution, a certain lightness of heart seems
    healthier than this excessive nervousness on
    their behalf.
  • William James, The Will to Believe

31
  • When faced with an intellectually undecidable and
    genuine option, someone of a less morose, more
    optimistic, nature that Cliffords might choose
    to believe.
  • Better risk loss of truth than chance of error
    that is your faith-vetoers exact position. He
    is actively playing his stake as much as the
    believer is he is backing the field against the
    religious hypothesis,

32
  • just as the believer is backing the religious
    hypothesis against the field. To preach
    skepticism to us as a duty until sufficient
    evidence for religion be found, is tantamount
    therefore to telling us, when in presence of the
    religious hypothesis, that to yield to our fear
    of its being error is wiser and better than to
    yield to our hope that it may be true. It is not
    intellect against all passions, then it is only
    intellect with one passion laying down its law.
    And by what, forsooth, is the supreme wisdom of
    this passion warranted?
  • William James, The Will to Believe

33
  • James sees belief in God as the more hopeful
    choice, and, as such it appeals to him.
  • If it does not appeal to Clifford thus, so be
    it. But, let him not become a vetoer of James
    will to believe.
  • James concludes his essay with by quoting
    another thinker, Fitz James Stephen

34
  • If a man chooses to turn his back altogether on
    God and the future, no one can prevent him no
    one can show beyond reasonable doubt that he is
    mistaken. If a man thinks otherwise and acts as
    he thinks, I do not see that any one can prove
    that he is mistaken. Each must act as he thinks
    best and if he is wrong, so much the worse for
    him. We stand on a mountain pass in the midst of
    whirling snow

35
  • and blinding mist, through which we get glimpses
    now and then of paths which may be deceptive. If
    we stand still we shall be frozen to death. If
    we take the wrong road we shall be dashed to
    pieces. We do not certainly know whether there
    is any right one. What must we do? Be strong
    and of a good courage. Act for the best, hope
    for the best, and take what comes. . . . If
    death ends all, we cannot meet death better.
  • Fitz James Stephens, Liberty, Equality, and
    Fraternity
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com