Aristoteles Nicomachean Ethics - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 31
About This Presentation
Title:

Aristoteles Nicomachean Ethics

Description:

Instead, Aristoteles argues, eudaimonia is 'activity of soul in accordance with ... Make it possible for them to be 'happy' i.e., to achieve eudaimonia ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:312
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 32
Provided by: tomtre
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Aristoteles Nicomachean Ethics


1
AristotelesNicomachean Ethics
  • Human Excellence and
  • The Good Life

2
The Nicomachean Ethics
  • The Nicomachean Ethicsa work Aristoteles may
    have written for his son, Nikomakhosis one of
    the easiest to read, so its an excellent place
    to begin the study of Aristoteles philosophy
  • Despite its title, it isnt so much a work on
    what wed call ethics today as a book about the
    goal of all human striving and what it takes to
    live life supremely well
  • Accordingly, it dwells at length on the question
    of the qualities of character and intellect one
    must have to be able to do this, and its in fact
    the Greek word for having to do with
    characterethikethat gives both the work and
    the relevant science their names

3
The Nicomachean EthicsBook I
  • Book I is devoted to identifying the goal of all
    human striving and characterizing it in
    reasonably full detail
  • Aristoteles begins by saying that its generally
    agreed that its eudaimonia that all human beings
    want by naturewant, that is, whether they know
    that this is what they want or notand he then
    proceeds to argue that this is not what most
    people take it to be, namely, pleasure, honor, or
    wealth (McKeon 349-351)
  • Instead, Aristoteles argues, eudaimonia is
    activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and
    if there are more than one virtue, in accordance
    with the best and most completein a complete
    life (McKeon 357)

4
The Nicomachean EthicsBook I
  • The traditional translation of the word
    eudaimonia happinessis, I think, terribly
    misleading. Aristoteles makes it plain that what
    he means by eudaimonia is not any sort of state
    of mind, and yet thats exactly what most of us
    mean by the term happiness
  • So one must constantly remind oneself what this
    central term really means the distinctively
    human part of human life, lived supremely well
    (cf. Study Guide 30ff.)
  • Given this characterization of the goal of all
    human striving, the next question is what
    qualities of character and intellect one must
    have to be able to achieve this, and thats the
    question taken up in Books II-VI

5
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • Book II of the Nicomachean Ethics begins with the
    distinction between the moral and intellectual
    virtuesthe qualities of character and intellect
    that
  • Make those who possess them good people, and so
  • Make it possible for them to be happyi.e., to
    achieve eudaimonia
  • Aristoteles begins by observing that theres a
    difference in the way these qualities are
    acquired (Nic. Eth. II.i., 1103a15ff, McKeon
    369)
  • Excellence of intellect owes both its birth and
    its growth to teaching (and so requires both
    experience and time)
  • Excellence of character comes about as a result
    of the formation of the right habits (and so
    requires a good upbringing)

6
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • This said, Aristoteles turns his attention
    specifically to the moral virtues, the
    excellences of character, which are the sole
    subject of discussion in Books II-V, the
    intellectual virtues (or excellences of
    intellect) being the subject of Book VI
  • First, he argues that
  • none of the moral virtues arises in us by
    nature rather, we are adapted by nature to
    receive them, and are made perfect i.e., made
    into the particular people that we are by ethos
    custom, usage, manners, habit (1103a19-25),
    and consequently
  • we must conduct ourselves virtuously, and in the
    first instance, must be required to do so (by our
    parents and by good laws), if we are to become
    good (1103a26-1103b26)

7
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • Then, after discussing a variety of
    methodological considerations and answers to
    possible objections (chapters ii-iv), Aristoteles
    takes up the question what virtue isand
    specifically, what moral virtue is (chapters
    v-vi). His answer
  • Neither our virtues nor our vices are passions or
    faculties (i.e., they arent the feelings we have
    or the capacities we have to have those
    feelings) instead, theyre states of character
    the things in virtue of which we stand well or
    badly with reference to the passions or in other
    words, theyre dispositions (1105b19-1106a11),
    and this gives us the genus for the virtues (the
    moral virtues, and, for that matter, for the
    moral vices as well)
  • And as for the specific difference.

8
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • One of Aristoteles most interesting claims is
    the one that provides him with the specific
    difference he needs for his definition that each
    of the moral virtues must be seen as a mean
    between two vices one of which exceeds and one of
    which falls short of what is right in both
    passions and actions, while the virtue finds and
    chooses that which is intermediatei.e., just
    right (1107a2-6)
  • He argues for this point with considerable care
    (in the passage at 1106a25-1106b35), prefacing
    that argument with an absolutely crucial
    explanation of whats involved in the concept of
    a virtue (or excellencei.e., the concept of a
    good-making property) in general. The passage in
    question is at 1106a15-23, and with it one may
    profitably compare a discussion at the end of
    Book I of Platons Republic, (352e-354b, Rouse
    152ff).

9
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • This, then, gives Aristoteles the definition hes
    been seeking, which is formulated with precision
    at 1106b36-1107a26 (q.v.)
  • Now, as to what the virtues and vices
    specifically recognized by Aristoteles are, the
    list is in Book II, chapter vii (1107a26-1108b11
    cf. the table of contents for Nic. Eth.
    III.vi-V.xi, McKeon 340-341)
  • Courage (Bravery)
  • Rashness/Fearlessness
  • Cowardice
  • IV. Magnificence (Civic Generosity)
  • Tastelessness and Vulgarity
  • Niggardliness
  • V. Proper Pride (Arrogance? Haughtiness?)
  • Empty Vanity
  • Undue Humility
  • Of all the virtues recognized by Aristoteles,
    this one seems always to give modern readers the
    greatest difficulty see Book IV, chapter iii
  • II. Temperance (Moderation)
  • Self-indulgence
  • Insensibility
  • III. Liberality (Private Generosity)
  • Prodigality
  • Meanness

10
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • VI. The Mean Between Ambition and Unambitiousness
  • Ambition
  • Unambitiousness
  • IX. Ready Wit
  • Buffoonery
  • Boorishness
  • VII. Good Temper
  • Irascibility
  • Inirascibility
  • X. Friendliness
  • Obsequiousness and Flattery
  • Quarrelsomeness and Surliness
  • Truthfulness
  • (Straightforwardness About
  • Oneself)
  • Boastfulness
  • Mock Modesty
  • Justice (As this word has many senses, there are
    actually many virtues and vices here see Book V
    for the full analysis)

11
The Nicomachean EthicsBook II
  • This concludes the introductory discussion of the
    moral virtues (and vices)
  • As we shall see, Book III begins with a
    challenging discussion of the conditions under
    which we can be held to be responsible for our
    actions and for our character itself
  • Then, beginning with chapter 6 of Book III,
    Aristoteles provides a lengthy, detailed account
    (not assigned) of all the moral virtues and vices
    hes identified for us in Book II
  • Thats then followed, in Book VI, by the
    discussion of the intellectual virtues, and well
    turn to that next Monday

12
The Nicomachean EthicsBook III
  • Chapters i-v of Book III are devoted to a
    discussion of the conditions of responsibility
    for action, beginning with a series of
    reflections on the distinction between voluntary
    and involuntary passions and actions, the
    distinction being important, Aristoteles
    suggests, because praise and blame are bestowed
    on voluntary actions and passions whereas the
    involuntary is pardoned, and sometimes even
    pitied (1109b30-32)
  • Aristoteles maintains that since that which is
    done either under compulsion or owing to
    ignorance is involuntary, it must be action of
    which the moving principle is in the agent
    himself, the agent being aware of the
    particular circumstances of the action that is
    voluntary (1111a21-23)

13
The Nicomachean EthicsBook III
  • Chapters i-v of Book III are devoted to a
    discussion of the conditions of responsibility
    for action, beginning with a series of
    reflections on the distinction between voluntary
    and involuntary passions and actions, the
    distinction being important, Aristoteles
    suggests, because praise and blame are bestowed
    on voluntary actions and passions (those done or
    suffered on purpose) while the involuntary is
    pardoned, and sometimes even pitied (1109b30-32)
  • Aristoteles maintains that since that which is
    done either under compulsion or owing to
    ignorance is involuntary, its action of which
    the moving principle is in the agent himself, he
    being aware of the particular circumstances of
    the action that is voluntary (1111a21-23)

14
The Nicomachean EthicsBook III
  • This distinction is, as Aristoteles points out,
    indispensable for those who assign honors and
    punishments (1109b33-34), but it provides those
    who want to grasp the nature of virtue with only
    a part of what they need to understand virtue,
    we must also understand choice, for its ones
    choices that especially reveal ones character
    (1111b4-6)
  • So what is choice? Aristoteles answers this
    question by means of a process of elimination,
    arguing against a number of ideas that must have
    been advanced by his contemporaries or his
    predecessors it isnt merely to want something,
    he says, or to act in anger, or to wish for
    something, or to have some sort of opinion
    instead.

15
The Nicomachean EthicsBook III
  • Choice always involves deliberation, or at the
    very least a rational principle and thought
    (1112a16), so given the sorts of things we
    deliberate about, choice can be defined as
    deliberate desire of things i.e., actions or
    passions within our own power (1113a11)
  • And this definition further clarifies how what we
    choose is different from what we wish for its
    always ends we wish for, and always means to
    those ends we deliberate about and choose
    (1113b2-3)
  • For example while we may wish to be in good
    health, we cant simply choose to be we must do
    and put up with certain things to be and to stay
    healthy, and its about these things that we
    deliberate and ultimately make a choice

16
The Nicomachean EthicsBook III
  • Finally, Aristoteles argues in chapter v of Book
    III that since the exercise of the virtues is
    concerned with means and since means are things
    that are within our power, virtue also is
    within our own power, and so too vice
  • The thought is this since we become good or bad
    as a result of doing the things we choose to do,
    even if we cant easily change our character once
    its been formed, it was open to us at the
    beginning (1114a20) to do and put up with the
    things that would make us good and not to do or
    give in to the things that would make us bad
  • And so, Aristoteles concludes, were not only
    responsible for the things we do were at least
    partly responsible for our character as well

17
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • Aristoteles opens Book VI by suggesting, in
    effect, that an analysis of the intellectual
    virtues will actually give us two things for the
    price of one
  • Itll complete the survey of the virtues begun in
    Books III-V
  • Itll also enable us to understand the right
    rule referred to in the definition of moral
    virtue given in Book II
  • While we dont get the second of these two things
    till the end of Book VI in chapters xii-xiii,
    youll need to bear in mind that the whole
    discussion is designed to achieve both these
    goals
  • To set the stage for the discussion that follows,
    Aristoteles presents in broad outline his
    conception of the structure of the soul, which
    hes already said (at 1102a26-8) consists of two
    main parts (well get a much fuller account in
    the De Anima, Aristoteles treatise on the soul)

18
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • The Parts of the Soul
  • The rational partthe part that grasps rules or
    rational principles (intellect)
  • The scientific part (the contemplative intellect)
  • The calculative or deliberative part (the
    calculative intellect)
  • The part of this part that deliberates about
    means to ends in the sphere of action (the
    practical intellect)
  • The part of this part that deliberates about
    means to ends in the sphere of production (the
    productive intellect)
  • The irrational part
  • The sensitive part (the faculty of sensation)
  • The desiderative or appetitive part (the faculty
    of desire)see 1102b13ff on how, in a sense, the
    faculty of desire has a rational principle
  • The vegetative or nutritive part (the faculties
    of growth and nutrition)see 1102a33ff
  • Note the claim is that the various virtues are
    the virtues of the contemplative, practical, and
    productive intellects and of the faculty of desire

19
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • With this account of the various parts of the
    soul in place, the next question is this whats
    the work of each of the two main subdivisions of
    the rational part? We need to know this, because,
    as youll recall, the virtue of a thing is
    relative to its proper work (1139a15)
  • Aristoteles answer, in a nutshell is this the
    work of both parts of the intellect is the
    apprehension of truth
  • The contemplative intellect apprehends truth for
    its own sake, so the goal here is truth per se
  • The calculative intellect apprehends it with an
    eye to action (or production), so the goal here
    is choice ideally, truth in agreement with
    right desire (1139a31)
  • Even production, whose ends are subordinate to
    those of action, aims at truth in agreement with
    right desire (cf.. Nic. Eth. I. i-ii)

20
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • But then it follows that the states that are
    most strictly those in respect of which each of
    these parts will reach truth are the virtues of
    theparts (1139b12-13)
  • With this principle, we can now begin from the
    beginning (1139b14) the intellectual virtues
    must be
  • Scientific knowledge (epistemescientific
    ability)
  • Art (tekhnetechnical skill)
  • Practical wisdom (phronesisprudence or good
    judgment)
  • Intuitive reason (nousintelligence a nose for
    principles)
  • Philosophic wisdom (sophiaunderstanding of the
    highest things)
  • For these are the states by virtue of which the
    soul possesses truth by way of affirmation or
    denial (1139b16), supposition and opinion being
    omitted as capable of error

21
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • Aristoteles proceeds to discuss these, the chief
    intellectual virtues, in chapters iii-vii, and
    what finally emerges is this
  • The virtue of the contemplative intellect is
    episteme, which becomes, with the addition of
    nous, sophia
  • The virtue of the practical intellect is
    phronesis, and
  • The virtue of the productive intellect is tekhne
  • So the five reduce to threeone for each of the
    various intellects
  • Further, since choice is what gives rise to
    action, and since desire and reasoning with a
    view to an end are the things that give rise to
    choice (1139a32-33), excellence in the sphere of
    action requires both excellence of character
    (moral virtue) and phronesis

22
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • In fact, strictly, one cannot have either without
    the other (1144b30-31), for virtue makes us aim
    at the right mark, and practical wisdom makes us
    take the right means (1144a7-8)
  • One cannot determine the correct means to the end
    we ought to have before us unless one already
    desires that end (and its only moral virtue that
    ensures that one will) (1144a34), and yet
  • One will be able to aim intelligently at the mark
    virtue sets before us only if one possesses
    phronesis without this, ones moral virtue wont
    be real virtuevirtue in the strict sense
    (1144b1ff)
  • In short practical wisdom providesindeed isthe
    right rule that weve been seeking (1144b20-29)
  • Does this, then, make practical wisdom the best
    and most complete of all the virtues? Not at all.

23
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • Earlier, in declaring sophia to be nous combined
    with epistemeepisteme of the highest objects
    which has received as it were its proper
    completion (1141a18-19), Aristoteles went on to
    say this Of the highest objects, we say for it
    would be strange to think that the art of
    politics, or phronesis, is the best knowledge,
    since man is not the best thing in the world
    (1141a20-24)
  • Its sophia, then, thats the most finished of
    the forms of knowledge (1141a16)the virtue
    thats the best and most completeand so
    phronesis is not supreme over sophia, i.e., over
    the superior part of us,for it does not use it
    but provides for its coming into being it issues
    orders then for its sake, but not to it, and so
    happiness must be activity of soul in accordance
    with sophia, in a complete life.

24
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • What remains is to look more closely at
    Aristoteles definitions of each of the
    intellectual virtues, for the names alone are
    hardly adequate to the task of making it plain
    just what Aristoteles has in mind in the case of
    each
  • This is what well take up next time, so review
    chapters iii-xiii of Book VI, but with special
    attention to chapters iii-viionce again making
    careful use of the relevant material in the Study
    Guide.

25
The Nicomachean EthicsBook VI
  • The Intellectual Virtues defined
  • Sophia (Philosophic Wisdom, or Wisdom or even
    Mastery in the Sphere of Theory) Episteme Nous
  • Episteme (Scientific Knowledge, or Scientific
    Ability) A state of capacity to demonstrate
    (1139b30). See the Study Guide, pp. 45-50 for a
    detailed discussion of just what this is
  • Nous (Intuitive Reason, or Intelligence or even A
    Nose for First Principles) An acquired
    capacity to grasp first principles (i.e., the
    first principles of demonstration) (1141a6)
  • Phronesis (Practical Wisdom, or Prudence or Good
    Judgment) A state of capacity to act with regard
    to human goods involving a true course of
    reasoning (1140b20)
  • Tekhne (Art, or Technical Skill or Technical
    Expertise) A state of capacity to make involving
    a true course of reasoning (1140a9)

26
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • After completing his discussion of intellectual
    virtue in Book VI, Aristoteles turns in Books
    VII-IX to a number of interesting, but for our
    purposes less important topics
  • The nature of continence and incontinence
    (VII.i-x)
  • Widely held views regarding pleasure and the good
    (VII.xi-xiv)
  • The nature of friendship and the need for it
    (VIII-IX)
  • At the beginning of Book X, he returns to the
    topic of pleasure, finally saying what kind of
    thing it is if not quite defining it (in chapter
    iv), and formulating a criterion that can be used
    to determine the value of pleasures since its
    virtue and the good man that are the measure of
    all things, those pleasures are the best that
    accompany the noblest activities and are sought
    by the best of men (chapter v)

27
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • Finally, in chapter vi, Aristoteles returns to
    the question of the nature of happiness, last
    discussed in Book I
  • He begins be reiterating that it cannot be a
    disposition, for if it were, then even those who
    are comatose or suffering the greatest
    misfortunes could well be happy therefore, once
    again happiness must be an activity
    (1176a34-1176b1)
  • But it must also be desirable for its own sake
    and not for its effects, for it lacks nothing and
    is in and of itself enough(1176b3-7)
  • So what activitywhat kind of lifecould it
    actually be?
  • Not a life of pleasant amusements, for unless one
    is silly and utterly childish, one relaxes so
    that one may worknot the other way around
    (1176b8-1177a11)
  • But also not simply a life of virtuous action,
    for war and political activity are undertaken not
    for their own sake, but for the sake of something
    else (1177b6-15)

28
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • It must therefore be the contemplative life, for
    this is all that remains as a life of activity
    in accordance with virtue
  • If among virtuous actions political and
    military actions are distinguished by nobility
    and greatness, and these are unleisurely and aim
    at an end and are not desirable for their own
    sake, but the activity of reason, which is
    contemplative, seems both to be superior in
    serious worth and to aim at no end beyond itself,
    and to have its pleasure proper to itself, and
    if the self-sufficiency, leisureliness,
    unweariedness (so far as this is possible for
    man), and all the other attributes ascribed to
    the supremely happy man are evidently those
    connected with this activity, it follows that
    this will be the complete happiness of man, if it
    be allowed a complete term of life (for none of
    the attributes of happiness is incomplete)
    (1177b16-25)

29
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • This, at any rate, is what we must try to
    achieve
  • We must not follow those who advise us, being
    men, to think of human things, and, being mortal,
    of mortal things, but must, so far as we can,
    make ourselves immortal, and strain every nerve
    to live in accordance with the best thing in us
    for even if it be small in bulk, much more does
    it in power and worth surpass everything
    (1177b35)
  • Yet in a secondary degree the life in
    accordance with the other kind of virtuei.e.,
    moral virtue and the virtue of the calculative
    intellectis happy as well, for this too is a
    human life (1178a8-14), and even those who live
    the contemplative life need the things that
    enable them to do well in the sphere of action
    (1178a34-1178b7)
  • So who is the happiest of human beings?

30
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • Aristoteles answer the philosopher
  • He who exercises his reason and cultivates it
    seems to be both in the best state of mind and
    most dear to the gods. For if the gods have any
    care for human affairs, as they are thought to
    have, it would be reasonable both that they
    should delight in that which was best and most
    akin to them (i.e., reason) and that they should
    reward those who love and honor this most, as
    caring for the things that are dear to them and
    acting both rightly and nobly. And that all these
    attributes belong most of all to the philosopher
    is manifest. He, therefore, is the dearest to the
    gods. And he who is that will presumably be also
    the happiest so that in this way too the
    philosopher will more than any other be happy.
    (1179a23-33)
  • Yet its not enough to know all this we must do
    what it takes to become happy (1179a34-1179b4),
    and arguments alone arent enough to make men
    good (1179b4-5), so.

31
The Nicomachean EthicsBook X
  • So we must turn to political activity and become
    legislators (1180b23-28)
  • And that means we must learn to legislate
    (1180b28)
  • And that means we must determine what
    constitution is best, how each constitution must
    be ordered, and what laws and customs it must use
    if it is to be at its best (1181b22-25) so the
    end of the Nicomachean Ethics makes the
    transition to the Politics, Aristoteles work on
    just this set of questions
  • We ourselves will go in yet another
    directionthat of Aristoteles treatise On Soul,
    a work that will help us substantially in our
    effort to understand Aristoteles thought more
    deeply
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com