Title: Week 12. Acquirers and questions
1GRS LX 700Language Acquisition andLinguistic
Theory
- Week 12.Acquirers and questions
2English wh-questions
- What will John bake?
- Two components to forming a (main clause)
wh-question (in English) - Move a wh-word to SpecCP.
- Move T to C (Subject-Aux InversionSAI)
3Question formation
- Declarative John will buy coffee.
- Wh-inversion What will John buy?
- Wh-fronting What will John buy?
- Yes/No-inversion Will John buy coffee?
- Greenberg (1963)
- Wh-inversion implies Wh-fronting.
- Yes/No-inversion implies Wh-inversion.
4Wh-inversion?Wh-fronting
- English, German Both.
- What will John buy?
- Japanese Korean neither.
- John will buy what?
- Finnish Wh-fronting only.
- What John will buy?
- Unattested Wh-inversion only.
- Will John buy what?
5Y/N-inversion?Wh-inversion
- English Both
- Will John buy coffee? What will John buy?
- Japanese Neither
- John will buy coffee? John will buy what?
- Lithuanian Wh-inversion only.
- John will buy coffee? What will John buy?
- Unattested Y/N-inversion only.
- Will John buy coffee? What John will buy?
6Universals and parameters
- Even if its not completely clear what accounts
for the implicational universals, inversion and
wh-fronting do seem to be independent. - A kid needs to learn what his/her language does
in each domain. - Wh-inversion implies Wh-fronting Perhaps the
only reason youd move T to C is to get a wh
feature originally on T into a position where it
can be checked by a wh-word in SpecCP
(Wh-criterion, see Guasti). - Y/N-inversion implies Wh-inversion ?
7Kids get these parameters down early
- Guasti (2000) Adam, Eve, and Sarah pretty much
never left wh-words in situ, and when they did it
was generally in a (grammatical) echo question. - Same with inversion, there seem to be very few
(on the order of 1) errors of non-inversion in
German, Italian, Swedish. - Yet Bellugi (1971)very famouslyseemed to find
something different in English Stages - SAI in yes-no questions, not in wh-questions
- Notice this runs counter to Greenbergs univeral.
- SAI in positive questions, not in negative
questions.
8Kuczaj Maratsos (1983)
- Kids seem to learn auxiliaries one by one they
appear at different times.
Form Abe Abe Ben Ben
Form Uninv Inv Uninv Inv
can 25 211 26 210
is (cop) 27 31 24 28
are (cop) 29 30 27 210
is (aux) 30 30 27 31
are (aux) 30 31 210 30
will 30 31 210 210
9Kuczaj Maratsos (1983)
- Each auxiliary seems be first used outside of
inversion contexts, only later in inversions
Form Abe Abe Ben Ben
Form Uninv Inv Uninv Inv
can 25 211 26 210
is (cop) 27 31 24 28
are (cop) 29 30 27 210
is (aux) 30 30 27 31
are (aux) 30 31 210 30
will 30 31 210 210
10Kuczaj Maratsos (1983)
- Only correctly inverted verbs (auxiliaries)
appear in child speech (no inversion of main
verbs)
Form Abe Abe Ben Ben
Form Uninv Inv Uninv Inv
can 25 211 26 210
is (cop) 27 31 24 28
are (cop) 29 30 27 210
is (aux) 30 30 27 31
are (aux) 30 31 210 30
will 30 31 210 210
11A famous non-result SAI in YNQs before SAI in
whQs
- Adam At a certain point, inversion appears in
yes-no questionsbut inversion with wh-questions
is still infrequent. Soon afterwards, inversion
is frequent for both types of questions.
YNQs YNQs WhQs WhQs
Inv Uninv Inv Uninv
30 0 1 0 3
35 198 7 9 22
38 33 5
12A famous non-result SAI in YNQs before SAI in
whQs
- Problem is, seems to be true of Adams files, but
not true generally - Several later studies with better sampling show
no identifiable stage where yes-no questions
invert while wh-questions dontin fact, even the
frequency doesnt go in one direction for all
kids.
13Stromswold (1990, table 5.5) of inversion WHQ
vs.YNQ
Child WH YN Child WH YN
Adam 88.3 96.6 Nathan 60.1 46.2
Allison 85.7 100 Nina 98.5 93.9
April 91.7 94.1 Peter 92.1 98.5
Eve 95.5 87.2 Ross 99.3 97
Mark 97.9 97.6 Sarah 92.9 91.9
Naomi 96.2 94.2 Shem 95.6 79
MEAN 93 93.7
14Conclusion really seems to be
- Kids will sometimes fail to invert.
- Kids will sometimes fail to invert more in one
construction (e.g., wh-questions) than in another
(e.g., yes/no-questions), but which one gets the
advantage seems to vary by kid.
15SAI errors doubling
- A double-auxiliary error, both an inverted and an
un-inverted auxiliary - Why did you did scare me?
- How can he can look?
- A double-tensing error (where an auxiliary
moves to I but the verb surfaces with tense). - What did you bought?
- What did you did?
16Doubling errors
- Are the kids pronouncing a loud trace of
(head-)movement? (Are they moving the auxiliary
but failing to leave the trace unpronounced?)
That would be interesting. - Are they just forgetting what they are trying to
say midway through and blending two structures?
(one with and one without movement)
17Nakayama (1987)
- The longer the subject is, the more likely a kid
is to make a doubling error the length of the VP
makes no difference. - Is the boy who is watching Mickey is happy?
- Looks like blending, rather than the (more
interesting) loud trace idea Common error
type - Is the boy who is watching M, is he happy?
18Inversion in negation
- Guasti, Thornton Wexler (BUCLD 1995) looked at
doubling in negative questions. - Previous results (Bellugi 1967, 1971, Stromswold
1990) indicated that kids tend to invert less
often in negative questions. - First True?
- Second Why?
19GTW (1995)
- Elicited negative questions
- I heard the snail doesnt like some things to
eat. Ask him what. - There was one place Gummi Bear couldnt eat the
raisin. Ask the snail where. - One of these guys doesnt like cheese. Ask the
snail who. - I heard that the snail doesnt like potato chips.
Could you ask him if he doesnt?
20GTW (1995)
- Kids got positive questions right for the most
part. - 88 of kids wh-questions had inversion
- 96 of kids yes-no questions had inversion
- Except youngest kid (38), who had inversion only
42 of the time. - Kids got negative declaratives right without
exception, with do-support and clitic nt.
21GTW (1995)
- Kids got lots of negative wh-questions wrong.
- Aux-doubling
- What kind of bread do you dont like? (310)
- Neg Aux doubling
- Why cant she cant go underneath? (40)
- No I to C raising (inversion)
- Where he couldnt eat the raisins? (40)
- Not structure
- Why can you not eat chocolate? (41)
22GTW (1995)
- But kids got negative subject wh-questions right.
- which one doesnt like his hair messed up? (40)
- as well as how-come questions.
- How come the dentist cant brush all the teeth?
(42) - Re Not structure
- Why can you not eat chocolate? (41)
- Kids only do this with object and adjunct
wh-questionsif kids just sometimes prefer not
instead of nt, we would expect them to use it
just as often with subject wh-questions.
23GTW (1995)
- So, in sum
- Kids get positive questions right
- Kids get negative declaratives right
- Kids get negative subject questions right.
- Kids get negative how-come questions right.
- Kids make errors in negative wh-questions where
inversion is required. Where inversion isnt
required (or where the sentence isnt negative),
theyre fine.
24GTW (1995)
- The kids errors all seem to have the character
of keeping negation inside the IP. - What did he didnt wanna bring to school? (41)
- What she doesnt want for her witchs brew? (38)
- Why can you not eat chocolate? (41)
- Why cant she cant go underneath? (43)
- GTW propose that this is a legitimate option
citing Paduan (Italian dialect) as a language
doesnt allow neg-gtC.
25GTW (1995)
- Re subject and how come questions
- In a subject question, we dont know that the
subject wh-word got out of IPmaybe kids left it
in IP heck, maybe even adults do. - Who left?
- Who did leave?
- How come questions dont require SAI in the adult
language./? - How come John left?
- How come did John leave?
26Auxless questions
- Guasti (2002) discusses questions like
- Where Daddy go? (Adam 23)
- What I doing? (Eve 20)
- By making some assumptions (inherited from
Rizzi), Guasti finds these problematic.
Wh-movement requires SAI, so what moved to C? - Specifically, wh-movement depends on SAI, which
happens because wh starts on T and must move
to C so it can be in a Spec-head relation with
the wh-word in SpecCP. Also subject questions
need no inversion on this story.
27Auxless questions
- Auxless questions are relatively common among
wh-questions in the 2-4 age range. - Guasti/Rizzis suggestion An auxiliary at the
head of the root can be null (similar to the null
subject story). For adults, the head of the root
is ForceP, but for kids it might be lower (FocP,
where wh-words go). - Kids who might otherwise say What I doing? will
nevertheless not say Who laughing?. Subject
wh-questions seem immune from auxiliary drop. - The Guasti/Rizzi explanation is pretty contrived,
actually. The aux need not proceed as high as
FocP for subject questions, so it ends up not
being highest. - Not really any clear alternative, though
28Early, early wh-questions
- There may be an early formulaic stage where
kids ask questions by just asking Wh(s) NP?. - OGrady (1997) Because of their formulaic
character, it seems reasonable to treat these
utterances as instantiations of a simple template
rather than the product of whatever mechanism
forms wh-questions in the adult grammar. - But why? We already have lots of reason to think
young kids know a lot about adult grammar by
then What is simpler about a simple template?
29Wh-subjects and wh-objects
- Is there a difference in the timing of emergence
between subject wh-questions and object
wh-questions? In English, there is an apparent
difference in complexity (distance of movement,
SAI).
30Early, early, early wh-questions
- Seidl and Hollich (2003) looked at headturn
preferences in really young kids. - Minimizes demands of task
- Use looking preferences to answer wh-questions.
- What hit the apple?
- What did the apple hit?
- Where is the apple?
31Seidl et al.
- Kids saw a little simplistic computer-generated
movie where, e.g., a book hit some keys. - Then there were two screens presented side by
side, one with a book displayed, one with keys
displayed. - What hit the keys? (book)
- What did the book hit? (keys)
- Where is the book? (book)
32Seidl et al.
- Graph shows differences (target minus
non-target). - 20-month-olds seemed quite capable of
comprehending all three kinds. - 15-month-olds couldnt do objects 13-month-olds
couldnt do any.
33Processing, structural distance
- The distance between the base and derived
positions for an object wh-word is greater than
the distance between the base and derived
positions for a subject wh-word. - Whati did IP John VP buy ti ?
- Whoi IP ti VP bought coffee ?
34Processing, structural distance
- Re preference for subject wh-questions perhaps
kids are sensitive to the number of phrases a
moving wh-phrase has to escape. This also makes
other predictions - Whati will IP Sue VP read ti ?
- Whati will IP Sue VP talk PP about ti ?
- Whati will IP Sue VP read NP a book PP
about ti ?
35Hildebrand (1987)
- Tested (fairly old) kids on a paradigm of
wh-questions of varying depth to see if more
embedded wh-words are harder. - In a repetition task (4-10 year olds), it was
almost uniformly true that the more deeply
embedded the wh-word was, the more errors the
kids made trying to repeat it.
36But wait
- So kids make more errors extracting from more
deeply embedded structures. Is this a fact about
the acquisition of wh-movement? Or is it just a
fact about language processing in general? - What do adults do?
- My guess Even for adults, the more complex
structures are (marginally) harder to process.
Certainly true for subject vs. object relative
clauses (the man who _ left vs. the man who I met
_). - Cf. NPAH later.
37Does child wh-movement obey the adult rules for
wh-movement?
- When the kids ask wh-questions, what structures
are they using? Are they like the adult
structures? If not, how are they different? Are
they performing movement? Are there traces? Do
the movements obey constraints (e.g., wh-island,
ECP, )?
38Do kids have wh-traces in their wh-questions?
- How do they perform on wanna-contraction?
- Who do you want to help t?
- Who do you wanna help t?
- Who do you want t to help you ?
- Who do you wanna / t help you ?
- Crain Thornton (1991) studied this
39Crain Thornton (1991)
- There are three guys in this story Cookie
Monster, a dog, and this baby. One of them gets
to take a walk, one gets to take a nap, and one
gets to eat a cookie. The rat gets to choose who
does each thing. So one gets to take a walk,
right? Ask Ratty who he wants. - Kid Who do you want to take a walk?
40Crain Thornton (1991)
- The kids (210 to 55) all knew the wanna
contraction rule - 59 of the time kids contracted to wanna with
object questions (as allowed) - 4 of the time kids contracted to wanna with
subject questions (out for adult)
41The ECP and argument-adjunct asymmetries
- Moving a wh-word out of a wh-island is better or
worse depending on whether the wh-word is an
argument (subject or object) or an adjunct. - How did he ask wh where to fix the car t ?
- What did he ask wh how to fix t ?
42De Villiers, Roeper, and Vainikka (1990)
- Kid takes a shortcut home, rips dress, that
night, kid tells parent about dress - When did she say t she ripped her dress t?
- at night that afternoon
- When did she say t wh how she ripped her dress t
t ? - at night that afternoon
- 3-6 year-olds allow short and long distance
questions for complement clauses, dont like long
distance adjunct questions out of wh-islands
43De Villiers, Roeper, and Vainikka (1990)
- And kids make the argument-adjunct distinction
the ECP makes for adults - No wh-island, arguments/adjuncts both take long
distance interpretation about 30-40 the time - Argument wh-island, neither argument nor adjuncts
can move out (2-8 LD) - Adjunct wh-islands, arguments can move out (30
LD) but not adjuncts (6 LD).
44Again, kids have a lot rightbut what do they
have wrong?
- When kids make a mistake with a question like
- When did she say how she ripped her dress?
- it will often be that they answer something like
climbing over the fenceanswering the question
How did she say t she ripped her dress? instead.
45What are kids doing when they answer a medial
wh-word?
- Are they answering the last wh-word they saw?
- Kids dont answer medial wh-words in yes-no
questions. - Did Mickey tell Minnie what he bought?
- Kids dont answer wh-words in relatives.
- How did you meet the man who sang?
46German partial wh-movement?
- Kids have been observed to produce questions with
an initial wh-word and a lower copy. - What do you think whats in her hat?
- What do you think is in her hat?
- What do you think where the marble is?
- Where do you think the marble is?
- What do you think what Cookie Monster eats?
- What do you think Cookie Monster eats?
47German partial wh-movement?
- Was hat er gesagt wie er das Kuchen machen
kann ? - What has he said how he the cake make can
- How did he say he could make the cake?
- Are kids treating the upper wh-word like a scope
marker? (Are they speaking German?) - Hard to say with confidence, but its an
interesting possibility. German partial
wh-movement does have certain restrictions.
Thornton (1990) and van Kempen (1997) showed that
kids do this only out of finite clauses, and
German only allows partial movement out of finite
clauses too.
48Processing constraints?
- OGrady (last years textbook) suggests that
another reason why kids might answer the
intermediate wh-word is that theyve already
forgotten the matrix clause (citing Phinney 1981,
who found that 3-year olds often delete the
matrix subject and verb when repeating biclausal
sentences). - Kids dont answer a medial wh-word in a yes-no
question, though..?
49Speaking Irish? French?
- Another crosslinguistic analogy we could make is
to Irish, French, and other languages that seem
to show a certain amount of wh-agreement when a
wh-word passes through SpecCP. - Ceapann tú go bhuailfidh an pÃobare an
t-amhrán.think you that play.fut the piper the
songYou think that the piper will play the
song. - Caidé aL cheapann tú aL bhuailfidh an
pÃobare?what WH think you WH play.fut the
piperWhat do you think the piper will play? - Je crois que Marie est partie.
- Qui crois-tu qui et partie?
50Speaking Irish? French?
- So, perhaps the kids non-adult use of
intermediate wh-words is actually a mis-analysis
of English. - First, they suppose it is Irish, and the
intermediate wh-words are the pronunciations of
agreeing complementizers. - A medial wh-word is never a whole wh-phrase. A
head? - Then, they suppose it is French, and limit the
agreement to subject wh-words. - Sometimes production goes from SO medial
wh-questions to just S. - Then, they get to English.
51Other constraints on wh-movement from 3-5 year
olds
- They reject adjunct extraction from NP
- Howi did the mother see his riding ti?
- But they allow argument extraction?
- Whoi did the mother show his copying ti ?
- This is de Villiers example seems ambiguous to
me between extraction and non-extraction
readings. Better might be What did the mother
show his eating? - They reject adjunct extraction from rel. clause
- Howi did the woman who knitted ti swim?
- And reject extraction from temporal adjuncts
- Who did the elephant ask before helping ti ?
52Superiority 3-5
- Adults
- Whoi ti slept where?
- Wherei did who sleep ti ?
- And the kids seem to have that down cold. (Kid
Its better if I start.) - (from deVilliers and Plunkett, unpublished as of
1995?)
53That-trace?
- Who did the pig believe that swam in the pond?
- Kids opt for the interpretation where the
questions asks which, of the animals the pig
believes, swam. - Kids dont go at all for the interpretation which
entails a violation of that-trace (the pig
believed that who swam) - (Phinney 1981)
- This is sort of mysterious, since languages
differ as to whether they respect the that-trace
filter.
54That-trace?
- Some conflicting results?
- Thornton (1990), production experiment found
that-trace violations 18 of the time subject
wh-questions were used. - McDaniel, Chiu and Maxfield (1995) found an
acceptance rate of 24 for that-trace effects.
55Grammar vs. Preferences
- These experiments are really testing preferences
not grammaticality. If they prefer the that-less
variant, we wont see that-trace violations even
if they are strictly grammatical for the kid. - Just because a structure is dispreferred (for
whatever reasonfrequency, difficulty, etc.) does
not mean that it is ungrammatical in the childs
grammar. - Preferences are not the best route to discovering
the properties of child grammar, though its hard
to design grammaticality judgment experiments..
56Questioning out of quotations
- Adult languages generally can not question out of
a quotation - Whati did the boy say Can I bring ti ?
- But English, French and German kids (3-6 years)
seem to allow it. - Why?
57Correlates to questioning out of quotations
- Kids may not quite grasp the quotation yet.
- A significant proportion of kids around the same
age range allow co-reference between a pronoun in
the quotation and the subject - Hei can sit here said Mickeyi.
- Perhaps, it has more to do with the fact that it
requires getting into someone elses head
58False beliefs
- Kids before a certain age (usually before 4) seem
unable to take another persons perspective - Little rabbit puts carrot in red basket, leaves.
Mother rabbit comes in, moves carrot to blue
basket. Little rabbit comes back. Where does he
look for the carrot? - Some kids will answer the blue basketunable to
see that the little rabbit shouldnt have known.
59False beliefs quotations
- Those same kids who answered blue basket were
also those who would do this - Mother bought cake, but wanted to surprise girl.
When asked, mother claimed to have bought paper
towels. - What did Mother say she bought?
- The blue basket kids answer cake.
60False beliefs quotations
- So, perhaps it is understanding what a quotation
is that is allowing kids to extract from
themthey treat a quotation as a regular clausal
complement.
61Weak islands
- In the adult language, there is a certain
configuration which seems to create an island for
movement of wh-adjuncts, which arguably has to do
with the logical meaning. - Coming by train is a subset of the events coming.
- John said Mary was coming by train implies John
said Mary was coming.
62Weak islands
- In weak islands the implication fails
- Negation
- John didnt say Mary was coming by train.
- John didnt say Mary was coming.
- Factives
- John forgot Mary was coming by train.
- John forgot Mary was coming.
- With quantificational adverbs
- John often eats grapes with a fork.
- John often eats grapes.
63Weak islands
- And in those cases, you cant extract wh-adjuncts
in the adult language. - Whyi did John say (ti) that Mary left (ti)?
- Whyi did John forget (ti) that Mary left (ti)?
- Whyi didnt John say (ti) that Mary left (ti)?
- Whyi does John often say (ti) that Mary left
(ti)?
64Weak islands
- Four-year-olds have been observed to fail on the
implication - Jim forgot that his aunt was arriving by train,
so he went to the bus station to pick her up Did
Jim forget that his aunt was coming? - Yes!
- Guess They havent gotten the implication
pattern down for these non-monotonic-increasing
environments.
65Weak islands
- Now If kids havent gotten the implication
pattern, and if the implication pattern is
implicated in the islandhood, do kids fail to
observe weak islands just when they also fail on
the implication pattern? - Philip and de Villiers (1992) looked into this
66Philip and de Villiers (1992)
- Kids never allow LD association out of a
wh-island (they obeyed the purely syntactic
constraint). - Whyi did the mother ask what he made ti ?
- The other facts were generally in support(de
Villiers 1995) of the conclusion that where kids
fail to make the inferences required by
non-monotone-increasing environments, they also
fail to treat them as movement islands.
67Multiple questions
- A fair amount of theoretical work has concerned
the treatment of multiple wh-questions. - E.g., the wh-typology English (move one) vs.
Japanese (move none) vs. Bulgarian (move all). - What do kids do with them?
- Well, but thats lunacyadults barely use them,
how are we going to find out about kids?
68Grebenyova (2005)
- Russian as a multiple-movement language
- chto kuda Smurf polozhil?What where S put?
- Interpretation
- PL (Pair-list) Who invited who for dinner?
- SP (Single pair) Which diplomat invited which
journalist? Who invited the roommate of who for
dinner? - Who invited who for dinner?
- English, Russian PL, SP
- Serbo-Croatian, Japanese PL, SP
69Grebenyova (2005)
- Ok, lets check CHILDES (parental speech).
Varvara (17-211). - 737 single questions.
- 1 multiple question.
- kto tebe chto podaril ?Whonom you whatacc gave?
- Not very much input here.
70Grebenyova (2005)
- Attempts to elicit multiple interrogatives.
- Story 3 characters each hide a different thing.
- Characters and items not in a natural category
- Avoiding Which x hid which Y? Who hid which X?
Which x hid what? - Add a character who doesnt hide anything (and
pointing that out). - Avoiding What did everyone hide?
- Not mentioning the names of the characters in the
lead-in - Avoiding What did they hide?
- First time single question. Decide to ask a more
difficult question next time.
71Grebenyova (2005)
- And it worked Kids (and adult controls) produced
multiple wh-questions in PL contexts (but not SP
contexts) about a third of the time in English,
about half the time in Russian. - Syntax English kids did it like adults. Russian
kids 15 of the time did it like English
kids/adults - Kto sprjatal chto?Who hid what
72Grebenyova (2005)
- Tried non-subjects and adjuncts to figure out
more about the syntax - Who hid what?
- Who did Lizard give what?
- Who did the dog find where?
- Found some wh-in-situ for kids, both notably both
for kids and adults found about two-thirds
multiple fronting and one-third partial fronting - Kogo sobaka gde nashia?Who dog where found
- Perhaps (for wh-in-situ but partial fronting?)
- Acquisition of focus?
- Mixed/confusing input (which phrases can stay in
situ)?
73?
74Stepping back a bit
- Lets take some time to look at a few results
coming out of an earlier tradition, not strictly
Principles Parameters (and not covered by
White) but still suggesting that to a certain
extent L2 learners may know something (perhaps
unconsciously) about what Language is like
(which is a certain way we might characterize the
content of UG).
75Typological universals
- 1960s and 1970s saw a lot of activity aimed at
identifying language universals, properties of
Language. - Class of possible languages is smaller than you
might think. - If a language has one property (A), it will
necessarily have another (B). - AB, AB, AB but never AB.
76(Typological) universals
- All languages have vowels.
- If a language has VSO as its basic word order,
then it has prepositions (vs. postpositions).
VSO? Adposition type Yes No
Prepositions Welsh English
Postpositions None Japanese
77Markedness
- Having duals implies having plurals
- Having plurals says nothing about having duals.
- Having duals is markedinfrequent, more complex.
Having plurals is (relative to having duals)
unmarked. - Generally markedness is in terms of comparable
dimensions, but you could also say that being VSO
is marked relative to having prepositions.
78Markedness
- Markedness actually has been used in a couple
of different ways, although they share a common
core. - Marked More unlikely, in some sense.
- Unmarked More likely, in some sense.
- You have to mark something marked unmarked is
what you get if you dont say anything extra.
79Unlikeliness
- Typological / crosslinguistic infrequency.
- VOS word order is marked.
- More complex constructions.
- ts is more marked than t.
- The non-default setting of a parameter.
- Non-null subjects?
- Language-specific/idiosyncratic features.
- Vs. UG/universal features?
80Berlin Kay 1969 Color terms
- (On the boundaries of psychophysics, linguistics,
anthropology, and with issues about its
interpretation, but still) - Basic color terms across languages.
- It turns out that languages differ in how many
color terms count as basic. (blueish,
salmon-colored, crimson, blond, are not basic).
81Berlin Kay 1969 Color terms
- The segmentation of experience by speech symbols
is essentially arbitrary. The different sets of
words for color in various languages are perhaps
the best ready evidence for such essential
arbitrariness. For example, in a high percentage
of African languages, there are only three color
words, corresponding to our white, black, red,
which nevertheless divide up the entire spectrum.
In the Tarahumara language of Mexico, there are
five basic color words, and here blue and
green are subsumed under a single term. - Eugene Nida (1959)
82Berlin Kay 1969 Color terms
- Japanese (Japan)
- Korean (Korea)
- Pomo (California)
- Spanish (Mexico)
- Swahili (East Africa)
- Tagalog (Philippines)
- Thai (Thailand)
- Tzeltal (Southern Mexico)
- Urdu (India)
- Vietnamese (Vietnam)
- Arabic (Lebanon)
- Bulgarian (Bulgaria)
- Catalan (Spain)
- Cantonese (China)
- Mandarin (China)
- English (US)
- Hebrew (Israel)
- Hungarian (Hungary)
- Ibibo (Nigeria)
- Indonesian (Indonesia)
83Eleven possible basic color terms
- White, black, red, green, yellow, blue, brown,
purple, pink, orange, gray. - All languages contain term for white and black.
- Has 3 terms, contains a term for red.
- Has 4 terms, contains green or yellow.
- Has 5 terms, contains both green and yellow.
- Has 6 terms, contains blue.
- Has 7 terms, contains brown.
- Has 8 or more terms, chosen from purple, pink,
orange, gray
84Color hierarchy
- White, black
- Red
- Green, yellow
- Blue
- Brown
- Purple, pink, orange, gray
- Even assuming these 11 basic color terms, there
should be 2048 possible setsbut only 22 (1) are
attested.
85Color terms
- BW Jalé (New Guinea) brilliant vs. dull
- BWR Tiv (Nigeria), Australian aboriginals
in Seven Rivers District, Queensland. - BWRG Ibibo (Nigeria), Hanunóo (Philippines)
- BWRY Ibo (Nigeria), Fitzroy River people
(Queensland) - BWRYG Tzeltal (Mexico), Daza (eastern Nigeria)
- BWRYGU Plains Tamil (South India), Nupe
(Nigeria), Mandarin? - BWRYGUO Nez Perce (Washington), Malayalam
(southern India)
86Color terms
- Interesting questions abound, including why this
order, why these elevenand there are potential
reasons for it that can be drawn from the
perception of color spaces which we will not
attempt here. - The point is This is a fact about Language If
you have a basic color term for blue, you also
have basic color terms for black, white, red,
green, and yellow.
87Implicational hierarchy
- This is a ranking of markedness or an
implicational hierarchy. - Having blue is more marked than having (any or
all of) yellow, green, red, white, and black. - Having green is more marked than having red
- Like a set of implicational universals
- Blue implies yellow Brown implies blue
- Blue implies green Pink implies brown
- Yellow or green imply red Orange implies brown
- Red implies black Gray implies brown
- Red implies white Purple implies brown
88L2A?
- Our overarching themeHow much is L2/IL like a
L1? - Do L2/IL languages obey the language universals
that hold of native languages? - This question is slightly less theory-laden than
the questions we were asking about principles and
parameters, although its similar - To my knowledge nobody has studied L2
acquisitions of color terms
89Question formation
- Declarative John will buy coffee.
- Wh-inversion What will John buy?
- Wh-fronting What will John buy?
- Yes/No-inversion Will John buy coffee?
- Greenberg (1963)
- Wh-inversion implies Wh-fronting.
- Yes/No-inversion implies Wh-inversion.
90Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989)
- L1 Korean (4), Japanese (6), Turkish (4)
- L2 English
- Note L1s chosen because they are neither/neither
type languages, to avoid questions of transfer. - Subjects tried to determine what was going on in
a scene by asking questions.
91Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989)
- Example Y/N Qs
- Did she finished two bottle wine?
- Is Lou and Patty known each other?
- Sue does drink orange juice?
- Her parents are rich?
- Is this story is chronological in a order?
- Does Joan has a husband?
- Yesterday is Sue did drink two bottles of wine?
92Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989)
- Example Wh-Qs
- Why Sue didnt look solution for her problem?
- Where Sue is living?
- Why did Sue stops drinking?
- Why is Pattys going robbing the bank?
- What they are radicals?
- What Sue and Patty connection?
- Why she was angry?
93Eckman et al. (1989)wh-inv?wh-fronting?result
s
Whinv Whfr
SM K 25 NO 100 YES
UA T 54 NO 100 YES
TS J 70 NO 100 YES
MK K 80 NO 100 YES
RO J 88 NO 100 YES
KO J 95 YES 100 YES
MH J 95 YES 100 YES
NE T 95 YES 100 YES
SI J 95 YES 100 YES
G T 100 YES 100 YES
MA T 100 YES 100 YES
ST J 100 YES 100 YES
TM K 100 YES 100 YES
YK J 100 YES 100 YES
94Eckman et al. (1989)YN-inv.? wh-inv.?results
YNinv WHinv
SM K 8 NO 25 NO
MK K 38 NO 80 NO
YK J 51 NO 100 YES
TS J 67 NO 70 NO
TM K 83 NO 100 YES
RO J 85 NO 88 NO
BG T 86 NO 100 YES
MA T 88 NO 100 YES
UA T 91 YES 54 NO
KO J 93 YES 95 YES
MH J 95 YES 95 YES
NE T 100 YES 95 YES
SI J 100 YES 95 YES
ST J 100 YES 100 YES
95Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989)
Yes/no inversion Wh-inversion Yes (VS) No (SV)
Yes (VS) 5 4
No (SV) 1 4
96Eckmans Markedness Differential Hypothesis
- Markedness. A phenomenon or structure X in some
language is relatively more marked than some
other phenomenon or structure Y if
cross-linguistically the presence of X in a
language implies the presence of Y, but the
presence of Y does not imply the presence of X. - Duals imply plurals.
- Wh-inversion implies wh-fronting.
- Blue implies red.
- (but what counts as a phenomenon or structure?)
97Markedness Differential Hypothesis
- MDH The areas of difficulty that a second
language learner will have can be predicted on
the basis of a comparison of the NL and TL such
that - Those areas of the TL that are different from the
NL and are relatively more marked than in the NL
will be difficult - The degree of difficulty associated with those
aspects of the TL that are different and more
marked than in the NL corresponds to the relative
degree of markedness associated with those
aspects - Those areas of the TL that are different than the
NL but are not relatively more marked than in the
NL will not be difficult. - Notice that this is assuming conscious effort
again. Perhaps it need not, depending on how you
interpret difficulty but it seems like Eckman
means it this way. - Another possible way to look at it is in terms of
parameter settings and (Subset Principle
compliant) defaults, coupled with a FT/FA type
theory
98MDH exampleWord-final segments
- Voiced obstruents most marked Surge
- Voiceless obstruents Coke
- Sonorant consonants Mountain
- Vowels least marked Coffee
- All Ls allow vowels word-finallysome only allow
vowels. Some (e.g., Mandarin, Japanese) allow
only vowels and sonorants. Some (e.g., Polish)
allow vowels, sonorants, but only voiceless
obstruents. English allows all four types.
99Eckman (1981)
Spanish L1 Spanish L1 Mandarin L1 Mandarin L1
Gloss IL form Gloss IL form
Bob b p Tag tæg
Bobby b bi And ænd
Red r?t Wet w t
Wet w t Deck d?k
Sick sIk Letter l?t r
Bleeding blidIn
c
e
c
e
e
e
e
100MDH exampleWord-final segments
- Voiced obstruents most marked Surge
- Voiceless obstruents Coke
- Sonorant consonants Mountain
- Vowels least marked Coffee
- Idea Mandarin has neither voiceless nor voiced
obstruents in the L1using a voiceless obstruent
in place of a TL voiced obstruent is still not L1
compliant and is a big markedness jump. Adding a
vowel is L1 compliant. Spanish has voiceless
obstruents, to using a voiceless obstruent for a
TL voiced obstruent is L1 compliant.
101MDH and IL
- The MDH presupposes that the IL obeys the
implicational universals too. - Eckman et al. (1989) suggests that this is at
least reasonable. - The MDH suggests that there is a natural order of
L2A along a markedness scale (stepping to the
next level of markedness is easiest). - Lets consider what it means that an IL obeys
implicational universals
102MDH and IL
- IL obeys implicational universals.
- That is, we know that IL is a language.
- So, we know that languages are such that having
word-final voiceless obstruents implies that you
also have word-final sonorant consonants, among
other things. - What would happen if we taught Japanese L2
learners of English onlyand at the outsetvoiced
obstruents?
103Generalizing with markedness scales
- Voiced obstruents most marked Surge
- Voiceless obstruents Coke
- Sonorant consonants Mountain
- Vowels least marked Coffee
- Japanese learner of English will have an easier
time at each step learning voiceless obstruents
and then voiced obstruents. - Butif taught voiced obstruents immediately, the
fact that the IL obeys implicational (markedness)
universals means that voiceless obstruents come
for free.
104Nifty!
- Does it work? Does it help?
- Answers seem to be
- Yes, it seems to at least sort of work.
- Maybe it helps.
- Learning a marked structure is harder. So, if you
learn a marked structure, you can automatically
generalize to the less marked structures, but was
it faster than learning the easier steps in
succession would have been?
105The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- Keenan Comrie (1977) observed a hierarchy among
the kinds of relative clauses that languages
allow. - The astronaut (that) I met yesterday.
- Head noun astronaut
- Modifying clause(that/who) I met yesterday.
- Compare I met the astronaut yesterday.
- This is an object relative because the place
where the head noun would be in the simple
sentence version is the object.
106The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- There are several kinds of relative clauses,
based on where the head noun comes from in the
modifying clause - The astronaut
- I met yesterday object
- who met me yesterday subject
- I gave a book to indirect object
- I was talking about obj. of P
- whose house I like Genitive (possessor)
- I am braver than obj. of comparative
107The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- Turns out Languages differ in what positions
they allow relative clauses to be formed on. - English allows all the positions mentioned to be
used to make relative clauses. - Arabic allows relative clauses to be formed only
with subjects. - Greek allows relative clauses to be formed only
with subjects or objects.
108Resumptive pronouns
- The guy who they dont know whether he wants to
come. - A student who I cant make any sense out of the
papers he writes. - The actress who Tom wondered whether her father
was rich. - In cases where relative clause formation is not
allowed, it can sometimes be salvaged by means of
a pronoun in the position that the head noun is
to be associated with.
109NPAH and resumptive pronouns
- Generally speaking, it turns out that in
languages which do not allow relative clauses to
be formed off a certain position, they will
instead allow relative clauses with a resumptive
pronoun in that position. - Arabic allows only subject relative clauses. But
for all other positions allows a resumptive
pronoun construction, analogous to - The book that John bought it.
- The tree that John is standing by it.
- The astronaut that John gave him a present.
110NPAH
- The positions off which you can relativize
appears to be an implicational hierarchy.
Lang. SUB DO IO OP GEN OCOMP
Arabic
Greek ? ?
Japanese /
Persian ()
111Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- More generally, there seems to be a hierarchy of
difficulty (or (in)accessibility) in the
types of relative clauses. - A language which allows this
- Subj gt Obj gt IO gt OPrep gt Poss gt OComp
112Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- More generally, there seems to be a hierarchy of
difficulty (or (in)accessibility) in the
types of relative clauses. - A language which allows this
- Will also allow these.
- Subj gt Obj gt IO gt OPrep gt Poss gt OComp
113Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy
- More generally, there seems to be a hierarchy of
difficulty (or (in)accessibility) in the
types of relative clauses. - A language which allows this
- Will also allow these. But not these
- Subj gt Obj gt IO gt OPrep gt Poss gt OComp
114Relation to L2A?
- Suppose that KoL includes where the target
language is on the NPAH. - Do L2ers learn the easy/unmarked/simple relative
clauses before the others? - Do L2ers transfer the position of their L1
first? - Does a L2ers interlanguage grammar obey this
typological generalization (if they can
relativize a particular point on the NPAH, can
they relativize everything higher too?)?
115NPAH and L2A?
- Probably The higher something is on the NPAH,
the easier (faster) it is to learn. - So, it might be easier to start by teaching
subject relatives, then object, then indirect
object, etc. At each step, the difficulty would
be low. - But, it might be more efficient to teach the
(hard) object of a comparisonbecause if L2ers
interlanguage grammar includes whatever the NPAH
describes, knowing that OCOMP is possible implies
that everything (higher) on the NPAH is possible
too. That is, they might know it without
instruction. (Same issue as before with the
phonology)
116NPAH in L2A
- Very widely studied implicational universal in
L2Amany people have addressed the question of
whether the IL obeys the NPAH and whether
teaching aa marked structure can help. - Eckman et al. (1989) was about this second
question
117Change from pre- to post-testEckman, Bell,
Nelson (1988)
118Transfer, markedness,
- Do (2002) looked at the NPAH going the other way,
English?Korean. - English Relativizes on all 6 positions.
- Korean Relativizes on 5 (not OCOMP)
S SU do IO OP GE
13
14 -
16 - -
29 - - -
31 - - - -
20 - - - - -
119Transfer, markedness,
- The original question Do was looking at was Do
English speakers transfer their position on the
NPAH to the IL Korean? - But look If English allows all 6 positions, why
do some of the learners only relativize down to
DO, some to IO, some to OPREP? - It looks like they started over.
120Subset principle?
A tempting analogy in some cases, parameters
seem to be ranked in terms of how permissive each
setting is.
I
E
- Null subject parameter
- Option (a) Null subjects are permitted.
- Option (b) Null subjects are not permitted.
- Italian option a, English option b.
121Reminder Subset Principle
- The idea is
- If one has only positive evidence, and
- If parameters are organized in terms of
permissiveness, - Then for a parameter setting to be learnable, the
starting point needs to be the subset setting of
the parameter. - The Subset principle says that learners should
start with the English setting of the null
subject parameter and move to the Italian setting
if evidence appears.
I
E
122Reminder Subset Principle
- The Subset Principle is basically that learners
are conservativethey only assume a grammar
sufficient to generate the sentences they hear,
allowing positive evidence to serve to move them
to a different parameter setting. - Applied to L2 Given a choice, the L2er assumes
a grammatical option that generates a subset of
the what the alternative generates. - Does this describe L2A?
- Is this a useful sense of markedness?
123Subset principle and markedness
- Based on the Subset principle, wed expect the
unmarked values (in a UG where languages are
learnable) to be the ones which produce the
smallest grammars. - Given that in L1A we dont seem to see any
misset parameters, we have at least indirect
evidence that the Subset principle is at work. Is
there any evidence for it in L2A? Do these NPAH
results constitute such evidence?
124Subset vs. Transfer
- The Subset Principle, if it operating, would say
that L2A starts with all of the defaults, the
maximally conservative grammar. - Another, mutually exclusive possibility
(parameter by parameter, anyway) is that L2A
starts with the L1 setting. - This means that for certain pairs of L1 and L2,
where the L1 has the marked (superset) value and
L2 has the unmarked (subset) value, only negative
evidence could move the L2er to the right
setting. - Or, some mixture of the two in different areas.
125NPAH and processing?
- At least a plausible alternative to the NPAH
results following from the Subset Principle is
just that relative clauses formed on positions
lower in the hierarchy are harder to process.
Consider - The astronaut
- who IP t met me yesterday SUB
- who IP I VP met t yesterday DO
- who IP I VP gave a book PP to t IO
- who IP I was VP talking PP about t OPREP
- whose house IP I VP like DP t s house GEN
- who IP I am AP brave degP -er thanP than t
OCOMP
126NPAH and processing?
- If its about processing, then the reason L2ers
progress through the hierarchy might be that
initially they have limited processing
roomtheyre working too hard at the L2 to be
able to process such deep extractions. - Why are they working so hard?
- (Well, maybe L2A is like learning history?)
127NPAH and processing?
- Is the NPAH itself simply a result of processing?
- The NPAH is a typological generalization about
languages not about the course of acquisition. - Does Arabic have a lower threshhold for
processing difficulty than English? Doubtful. - The NPAH may still be real, still be a markedness
hierarchy based in something grammatical, but it
turns out to be confounded by processing. - So finding evidence of NPAH position transfer is
very difficult.
128Subset problems?
- One problem, though, is that many of the
parameters of variation we think of today dont
seem to be really in a subset-superset relation.
So there has to be something else going on in
these cases anyway. - V?T
- Yes vSVAO, SAVO
- No SVAO, vSAVO
- Anaphor type
- Monomorphemic vLD, Non-subject
- Polymorphemic LD, vNon-subject
129?