Title: Inductive Thinking
1Inductive Thinking
- Inductive arguments are those in which the
premises are intended to provide support, but not
conclusive evidence, for the conclusion. - To use the example we have been using in the
book, in deduction we argue that All fish have
gills, tuna are fish, therefore tuna have gills.
In induction we argue that Tuna, salmon, cod,
sharks, perch, trout, and other fish have gills,
therefore all fish have gills.
2Inductive Thinking II
- To be even more precise, in using deductive
arguments we make explicit in the conclusion what
is implicit in the premises. In inductive
arguments, we extend the premises and make a
claim beyond the cases that are given. Induction
hazards an educated guess based on strong but not
on absolute proof about some general conclusion
that can be drawn from the evidence. - However we characterize induction, we can see
that it is not nearly as reliable as deduction
because the conclusion is never certain.
3Inductive Thinking III
- In the previous example, it is probably true that
all fish have gills, but we have not examined all
species of fish, so we never know that our claim
is true. The same can be said for the statement
that the sun will rise every day, which is based
on all recorded instances in the past but not on
all possible instances. - Because inductive arguments do not guarantee that
their conclusions are true, we evaluate them
according to the strength of the support they
provide for their conclusion.
4Inductive Thinking IV
- An inductive argument is strong when its premises
provide evidence that its conclusion is more
likely true than false. An inductive argument is
weak when its premises do not provide evidence
that its conclusion is more likely true than
false. - Instead of striving for certainty, we have to
settle for a high degree of probability. Used
properly, induction can lead to extremely
reliable generalizations, as science has
repeatedly shown. For example, Charles Darwin
established the theory of evolution using
inductive reasoning.
5Causation
- One of the most basic, most common, and most
important kinds of knowledge we seek is knowledge
of cause and effect. Why didnt my alarm clock
go off when it was supposed to? Why did I get a
D on my critical thinking exam? We want to
know the cause of what happened. In the absence
of a good account, we will often accept a bad one
- as in the case of superstition and mythology.
Some people have believed that they can appease
the gods by sacrificing a virgin. Some people
believe that if a black cat crosses their path,
bad luck will follow, and so forth.
6Causation II
- Our text points out that to bring rain we may not
do a rain dance, but we are only half-joking when
we say, Of course it rained I just washed my
car. - In all of these cases, a false connection has
been established between two events such that we
assume that one event is responsible for the
other when they are actually unrelated. - It can be difficult to recognize genuine causal
connections and distinguishing them from mere
temporal succession. - In our reasoning we need to separate a necessary
train of happenings from an accidental one.
7Causation III
- We can say that some events are subsequent,
meaning that they just happen to follow, while
others are consequent they occur because of the
earlier event. The trick is to differentiate
between the two, and to identify a causal
connection only when one event compels the
another to occur. - We can, for example, justifiably assert that the
following causal sequences took place the water
boiled because the temperature was raised to 212
F every time I let go of the chalk, the chalk
falls to the floor.In these cases the sequence
was necessary, not accidental given one event,
the other had to happen.
8Causation IV
- In Lewis Carrolls Through the Looking Glass the
following scene occurs in which causal
connections and temporal sequences are
deliberately confused. - Please turn to page 181-182 of the text and read
the conversation between Alice and the Queen. - Obviously, the order in which things happen make
a difference here because the events are causally
related. It may not matter whether the Queen
speaks and then smiles or smiles and then speaks,
but when it comes to a wound followed by a pain,
the second must occur after the first because it
is a consequence of it. The Queens mistake is
to see just a series of events where there are
actually causal relations, and causes and effects
cannot be reversed.
9Causation V
- To take another example, one that the philosopher
David Hume liked, every time you have seen one
billiard ball strike another, it has caused the
other to move. So, you assume there is a
cause-and-effect relationship there. You have
witnesses the same pairing of events over and
over again it is no mere coincidence. But,
Hume asks us, when you think about it, what have
you really seen? Just the pairing of two events,
one billiard ball striking the other and then the
other billiard ball moving. You have witnessed
what Hume called constant conjunction. The two
events always happen one before the other they
are constantly conjoined. You never see
necessary connection or causal power.
Because of Hume, we cans say, I see a
cause-effect connection, but only by claiming,
I can prove it.
10Causation VI
- To make the same point, the philosopher Bertrand
Russell asks you to consider yourself in the
position of a chicken on a farm. Every day that
you can remember, the farmer wifes has
approached you and then fed you. You have come
to associate the two in terms of cause and
effect. But then comes the day when the farmers
wife approaches you and doesnt feed you.
Instead, she wrings your neck. The moral of the
story is that we need to be careful in assuming a
cause-and-effect relationship between two things.
11Mills Methods
- The nineteenth-century English philosopher John
Stuart Mill (11806-1873) considerably refined the
process of identifying causal connections. John
Stuart Mill began learning Greek at the age of
three. By eight, he was reading Plato. He was
extremely influential in the development of
utilitarian ethics, but also crucial in the
establishment of the first womens rights
organization. - Mill specified four methods that can be used to
recognize cause-effect chains that of agreement,
difference, agreement and difference, and
concomitant variations.
12Mills Method of Agreement
- The method of agreement is described by Mill as
follows - If two or more instances of the phenomenon under
investigation have only one circumstance in
common, the circumstance in which alone all the
instances agree, is the cause (or effect) of the
given phenomenon. - For example, consider an individual doing
research on why some students are successful in
an especially difficult subject, say,
mathematical logic. In reviewing the data, the
researcher finds many circumstances in which
students are successful in mathematical logic,
such as instructors using particular approaches
to teaching the subject or assigning particular
tests. However, the researcher discovers that in
all instances in which students are successful
they are highly motivated.
13Mills Method of Agreement II
- High student motivation is the only condition
that is common to all instances of student
success in mathematical logic. From this
observation, using the method of agreement, the
researcher concludes that the necessary condition
for student success in mathematical logic is high
motivation.
14Mills Method of Agreement III
- Please turn to page 183 of your textbook.
- Although this method can be useful, if suffers
from a major defect that there is very often
more than one common factor. In the example of
the students, they may have drank from the same
water fountain, been to the same party the night
before, been exposed to someone with a contagious
disease, and so forth. This having been said,
Mills methods are a form of inductive reasoning.
There was a recent out break of E. coli at a
county fair. Health officials were able to
determine that water was the source of the deadly
E. coli by using causal reasoning like Mills.
15Method of Difference
- The method of difference is described by Mill as
follows - If an instance in which the phenomenon under
investigation occurs, and an instance in which it
does not occur, have every circumstance in common
save for one, that one occurring only in the
former the circumstance in which alone the two
instances differ, is the effect, or the cause, or
an indispensable part of the cause, of the
phenomenon.
16Method of Difference II
- In our previous example about the dining hall,
suppose that none of the students became ill
except for the one who ate pumpkin pie for
dessert. She had eaten the appetizer and the
main course just as the other students did who
did not become ill. - Prior factors Effect
- a, c, e, f, h no illness occurred
- a, d, e, g, i no illness occurred
- b, d, e, f, h no illness occurred
- b, c, e, g, j illness occurred
- Therefore j is the cause
17Method of Difference III
- The problem with this approach is that, just as
the areas of agreement can be numerous, so can
the differences. Because of the number of
variables involved, we can never be sure when we
have found the consequential difference. Even
though pumpkin pie may have been the cause, it
may not have been the cause. There could have
been additional variables. For instance, she
could have broken up with her boyfriend that day,
drank alcohol the night before, and so forth.
The possibilities are numerous.
18Joint Method of Agreement and Difference
- To try and fill the gaps in both methods Mill
suggests a third approach called the joint method
of agreement and difference. Here we judge as
the cause that element which all preceding events
have in common (agreement) after factoring out
any common elements that did not result in the
subsequent event (difference). We are then left
with the one common element present only in
positive instances, and that is taken as the
cause.
19Joint Method of Agreement and Difference II
- Prior factors Effect
- a, c, e, f, h illness occurred
- a, d, e, g, h illness occurred
- b, d, e, f, h illness occurred
- b, c, e, g, i no illness occurred
- a, d, e, g, 1 no illness occurred
- a, d, e, f, 1 no illness occurred
- Therefore h is the cause
20Joint Method of Agreement and Difference III
- Both e and h are present in cases where illness
occurred, but by extending the number of cases
further, e drops out as a possible cause. e is
present even when there is no illness, so it
cannot be the cause. H, on the other hand, is
present only (and always) when illness occurred,
so it must be the cause. - So, as in the case of the method of difference,
when pumpkin pie appears to be the cause then we
can ask if there is anyone who ate pumpkin pie
that did not get sick. If we find such persons
then we can eliminate pumpkin pie as the cause of
the illness.
21Method of concomitant variations
- The last approach, the method of concomitant
variations, is usually employed when a continuous
flow of events is involved and we cannot control
for the negative occurrences. Here we try to
establish causation by recognizing a correlation
in the way one set of event varies in relation to
another. That is, we see a correlation in degree
and regularity between two events, such that we
infer that the first must be causally related to
the second.
22(No Transcript)
23Method of concomitant variations II
- For example, people have observed that the height
of the tide depends upon the phases of the moon.
When the moon is full the tide is highest a
half-moon is followed by a medium tide and a low
tide seems to be related to a quarter or a
crescent moon. Because of the consistency and
predictability of the relation, we can infer a
cause-effect link the larger the moon, the
higher the tide.
24Method of concomitant variations III
- Other examples are the age of a tree and its
thickness and the darkness of our tan and the
length of time we were in the sun. Economists
will use this method in declaring that as
mortgage rates decline investment in homes
increases. Freudians psychologists will argue
that peoples freedom varies inversely with their
neuroses the more neurotic they are, the less
they are in charge of their lives.
25Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
- Aside from Mills formal methods, one basic way
of proving causal connections is to ask whether
the second event could have occurred without the
first. If it could not, then the first event can
be named as a cause. In technical terms this
means identifying the first event as a necessary
condition for the second., a sine qua non or
indispensable prior factor. Consider this
example from a Moore and Parker Critical Thinking
text - The presence of oxygen is a necessary condition
for combustion. - This tells us that we cant have combustion
without oxygen, or If we have combustion (C),
then we must have oxygen (O). Notice that the
necessary condition becomes the consequent of a
conditional If C then O.
26Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
- A sufficient condition guarantees whatever it is
a sufficient condition for. Being born in the
United States is a sufficient condition for U.S.
citizenship thats all one needs to be a U.S.
citizen. Sufficient claims are expressed as the
antecedents of conditional claims, so we could
say If John was born in the United States (B),
then John is a U.S. citizen (C) If C then P. - You should also notice the connection between
if and only if on the one hand and necessary
and sufficient conditions on the other. The word
if, by itself, introduces a sufficient
condition the phrase only if introduces a
necessary condition. So, the claim X is a
necessary condition for Y could be symbolized
if X then Y.
27- Some other examples would be
- In sports, having a positive attitude is a
necessary condition for winning you cant win
without it. However, it may not be sufficient.
You also need good training, strength, skill,
stamina, a mutually supportive team, and so
forth. - It is sometimes said that to be happy we need
good health. However, good health may be a
necessary condition but it is not a sufficient
condition for happiness. We would probably be
unhappy if we were not healthy, but just being
healthy is not enough to make us happy. As for
what the sufficient conditions are for happiness,
that has been a quest of philosophers and
humankind for centuries.
28- Sometimes conditions are not the same as causes.
In the case of a fire, a spark is both a
(necessary) condition and a cause, but if I lend
a friend my car which he then drives into a tree,
injuring himself, my lending him the car did not
cause the accident even though it was a necessary
condition for it.
29Proximate and Remote Causes
- A distinction often made among causal connections
is between a proximate and a remote cause. A
proximate cause is that which immediately
triggers an event. It functions as the factor
that precipitates some happening. For example,
the proximate cause of a persons death could be
heart failure. - A remote cause on the other had, is the
background cause that ultimately produces a
certain effect these causes are usually
multiple. They stretch backward in time as links
in the cause-effect chain, and contribute to the
inevitable and final outcome.
30Proximate and Remote Causes II
- For example, the proximate cause of a death might
have been heart failure but the remote causes
could have been a gunshot wound, preceded by a
jealous quarrel. - At a criminal trial the prosecuting attorney will
often stress the proximate cause while the
defense attorney will draw attention to the
remote ones. For example, a prosecutor might
emphasize that the accused was caught stealing a
toy. The defense attorney might argue that it
was Christmas, the person was unemployed, she
didnt have any friends or family, she was to far
down on the waiting list for some of the toys for
tots type programs, and so forth.
31Proximate and Remote Causes III
- Each attorneys case seems convincing because
each is referring to a different type of cause. - Some causes are certainly main ones and others
are peripheral, but rarely do we find one event
that can be labeled as the cause.
32Proximate and Remote Causes IV
- Imagine that you are a child and that your father
enters the living room and asks what caused the
large mirror over the fireplace to break. The
proximate cause was that the mirror, a very
fragile object, was struck with sufficient force
by another object of sufficient rigidity. But
your father is not interested in the proximate
cause of the mirrors breaking. He is looking
for something else.
33Proximate and Remote Causes V
- The second type of cause that we can identify is
a remote cause. A remote cause of a given event
is part of the chain of events that led to the
occurrence of that event. Typically, for any
given event, there are many remote causes. For
example, the remote cause of the broken mirror
might have been a shoe flying through the air.
This is an event within the chain of events that
led to the mirrors breaking. But this does not
satisfy your father either. So you tell him that
if your sister had not let go of the shoe, the
mirror would not have broken. You have
identified another remote cause, yet it, too,
does not satisfy your father.
34Proximate and Remote Causes VI
- The nature of the information sought determines
how far back in the chain of events one needs to
go in seeking a remote cause. In the case of the
broken mirror, your father continues to question
you and eventually discovers that you were
sitting on the fireplace mantel reading aloud
your sisters diary, which she had always kept
hidden. Finally, your father has the answer he
has been looking for.
35Problems in Determining Causation
- Distinguishing cause and effect. In the method
of concomitant variations, as well as in other
methods, it is sometimes hard to determine which
factor is the cause and which the effect. - For example, George seems unusually jittery and
remarks that he did not sleep well. His wife
thinks Georges insomnia (the feature about
George in question) was caused by his jitters
(the only relevant difference). She may fail to
consider the possibility that Georges being
jittery was the effect of his poor sleeping
rather than the cause. - Do the times create great leaders, or do great
leaders create the times?
36Problems in Determining Causation II
- Causation and correlation. Sometimes, two things
or events are clearly associated or linked.
Where you find X, you will also find Y. A
relationship such as this, in which two things
are frequently, or even constantly, found
together is a correlation. In a correlation, two
things share a mutual relationship where one is
found, the other is often, or always, found. By
contrast, in the relationship of causation, one
thing produces or brings about the other.
Sometimes, a correlation is an indicator of a
cause-and-effect relationship.
37Problems in Determining Causation III
- From the text,
- Chance correlations must be guarded against. For
example, Arizona has a high death rate from lung
disease. However, that does not mean the climate
is unhealthy, but only that many people with lung
disease move to Arizona (for the clean air). In
the same way, in Holland the more storks there
are, the greater the number of babies. Does that
mean storks bring babies, as mother told us? No,
it is rather that as the number of buildings
grown with the population, more nesting areas are
available for storks. Storks do not bring
babies, but babies do bring storks.
38Problems in Determining Causation IV
- The logical and the psychological. A third
problem has to do with our tendency to attribute
causation to events that are connected only
periodically, not constantly. The prime example
is that of gambling. The steady gambler is the
steady loser since the odds are always with the
house. However, gamblers are rewarded sometimes
and that reinforces their belief that they have a
winning system (or good luck). A behavioral
psychologist tells us that intermittent
reinforcement is a very powerful tool.
39Problems in Determining Causation V
- From a logical perspective, the fact that the
gambler usually loses is proof against the
gamblers idea that her system works, but from a
psychological viewpoint the occasional win
confirms the gamblers belief. Obviously, it is
more realistic to look at this situation from a
logical perspective.
40Summary
- Steps for identifying genuine causal
relationships from mere temporal sequences.
First we must apply Mills four methods - Agreement
- Difference
- Agreement and difference
- Concomitant variations
- Then we should differentiate between
- 1. Necessary and sufficient conditions
- 2. Proximate and remote causes
- Finally, we should be careful to distinguish
- Cause from effect
- Causation from correlation
- The logical from the psychological
41Similes and Metaphors
- Similes and metaphors are figures of speech that
are basically poetic devices that draw together
events, objects, or ideas, which are otherwise
dissimilar, in a striking comparison. - Similes, from the Latin, meaning likeness, use
the terms as or like to make the comparison
explicit, whereas metaphors, from the Greek
meaning transfer, dispense with the indicator
terms and imply the connection by substituting
the language of the one for the other.
42Analogies
- Whereas similes and metaphors compare things that
are essentially different except for one
similarity, analogical arguments compare things
that are alike in all essential respects and then
claimed to be alike in some further respect. - From the Greek, ana logon, according to a
ratio, analogies declare a relationship between
two things, a parallel connection, usually
between ideas or a set of ideas. - In mathematics, for example 5 is to 10 as 10 is
to X . X being 20. - Or, up is to down as right is to?
- Left, because the relationship is one of
opposites. - These are analogy questions.
43Analogies II
- An analogy is a comparison of things based on
similarities those things share. - Although analogies are interesting and important
for many reasons, including their use in poetry,
we shall focus on one their importance in
constructing inductive arguments. - Arguments from analogy claim that certain
similarities are evidence that there is another
similarity.
44Analogies III
- Extended beyond mathematics, analogical reasoning
has had an extremely wide application. - For instance, physical scientists have argued
that the atomic nucleus is like a miniature solar
system, so whatever physical forces disrupt the
one will disrupt the other. - Just prior to the Revolutionary War some
royalists argued that the colonies were like the
children of the mother country, and just as
children should remain loyal to their parents,
the colonies should not revolt against England.
On the other hand, the revolutionaries argued
that the colonies were like fruit in an arbor,
and when the fruit is ripe it is natural that it
should drop from the tree.
45Analogies IV
- These examples illustrate the nature of
analogical argument, but the last example also
shows one of its basic weaknesses. That is,
almost anything can be proven by carefully
selecting the comparison. - If we want to argue for the blessings of old age
we can compare it to the maturing of a fine wine
or say that one achieves senior status in the
community acquires patience and wisdom, free from
the tyranny of passions. - On the other hand, we could show the sadness of
old age by comparing it to a house that is
decrepit and crumbling, a pitiful ruin dimply
reflecting its former dignity.
46Analogies V
- The English theologian William Paley (1743-1805)
presented one of the best known analogical
arguments. Paley tried to support the view of
St. Thomas Aquinas that the world exhibits
evidence of a purposeful design and therefore
proves the existence of an intelligent designer,
that is, God. - Paley did this by comparing the world to the
mechanism of a watch. If we were on a deserted
island and found a watch ticking away in perfect
order, we would assume that a watchmaker had
produced the watch. The odds of all the random
parts coming together and forming a functioning
watch by pure dumb luck seems unlikely. In the
same way, it is unlikely that just dumb luck and
a big bang could create a world such as this that
is well-organized and functional.
47Analogies VI
- However, we could also compare the world to an
organism rather than a mechanism, one with
biological parts that can become diseased with
systems, vital organs, and limbs that develop and
degenerate and with energy and matter at the
core, not mind or spirit. The blind watchmaker.
48Analogy and Induction
- In an inductive generalization, we generalize
from a sample of a class or population to the
entire class or population. - In an analogical argument, we generalize from a
sample of a class or population to another member
of the class or population.
49Criteria for determining the strength of
analogical arguments
- The two cases must be alike in all essential
respects, and the greater the relevant
similarities the more probable the argument. - For example
- Jim and Tim are both burly and play football.
- Jim also wrestles.
- So, Tim must also wrestle.
- This is obviously a weak analogy. It would be
made stronger if it was noted that they are best
friends, rarely do anything apart, attend a
college that gives scholarships only to athletes
who play more than one sport, and so forth.
50Criteria for determining the strength of
analogical arguments II
- The greater the number of cases compared, the
stronger the probability of the conclusion. - For example Jims Buick leaks oil. Therefore,
Tims Buick will leak oil, also. - This case is not enough to make a fair statement.
If we tested 5,000 Buick cars and all of them
leaked oil, then we would have a stronger case.
51Criteria for determining the strength of
analogical arguments III
- The greater the dissimilarity of the cases used
as the base of the analogy, the higher the
probability of the conclusion. - Example in the book If we say that a company is
like a football team in that they are both
organizations of individuals devoted to the
achievement of a common goal, and just as
teamwork is necessary in winning football so
teamwork is essential to business success. - If the characteristics applied to high school
teams, as well as college teams, professional and
amateur, and so forth, that is stronger evidence
than citing just one football team.
52Criteria for determining the strength of
analogical arguments IV
- That is to say, if all subsets exhibit the same
characteristics plus the factor of teamwork, then
the argument that business (which is similar to
them) should do likewise and becomes more
powerful. - If all three rules are followed, the likelihood
of the analogy being correct is increased
considerably, although we can never be certain of
our conclusion.
53Legal Reasoning
- Many of the arguments used by lawyers in the
United States and Canada to support a trial are
analogical arguments. The reason is that the
legal systems of these countries were derived
many years ago from the English system, and an
essential feature of the English system is its
dependence on precedent. According to the
requirement of precedent, similar cases must be
decided similarly.
54Legal Reasoning II
- Consider a law that we are all familiar with,
the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution,
which provides for freedom of speech and
religious expression. Suppose that you decide,
in reliance on the First Amendment, to pass out
religious pamphlets on a downtown street corner.
Suppose further that most of the people your hand
your pamphlets to merely glance at them and then
throw them on the street and that the gathering
litter makes the area look like a garbage dump.
55Legal Reasoning III
- To prevent the litter, the police tell you that
you can hand out your pamphlets only in the
vicinity of trash cans. You object that such a
restriction violates your First Amendment rights,
and you take the issue to court. - In presenting your case, your lawyer will argue
that the case is analogous to a number of other
cases where the state attempted to limit not the
content of religious expression, but the time,
place, and manner of its expression. Your lawyer
will attempt to show that your case is analogous
to cases in which the government failed to prove
that the restriction was so tailored.
56Moral Reasoning
- As in law, arguments from analogy are also useful
in deciding moral questions. Find examples of
arguments from analogy in the Moral Reasoning
handout.
57Common Areas of Argument from Analogy
- Arguments from analogy are found in many areas of
study and have many practical applications. Once
again, lets consider law - American law has its roots in English common law,
so legal decisions are often made on the basis of
precedence. For example, in deciding whether or
not the free speech guaranteed by the First
Amendment applies to cyberspace communications, a
judge would be expected to appeal to earlier and
analogous free speech cases.
58Common Areas of Argument from Analogy II
- In deciding whether another case is analogous, we
must apply our rules to test the strength of
analogous arguments - The two cases must be alike in all respects, and
the greater the number of similarities, the more
probable the argument. - Are there a good number of relevant similarities,
and few, if any, relevant dissimilarities? Is
the conclusion of the judicial ruling properly
specific?
59Common Areas of Argument from Analogy II
- Arguments from analogy are often effective in
matters of ethics. One strategy used in moral
reasoning is to argue that a controversial issue
is analogous to one that is not controversial. In
her article A Defense of Abortion, Judith
Jarvis Thompson argues in favor of the morality
of abortion. Using a creative scenario, Thomson
argues that a person would have no moral
obligation to stay connected to a famous
violinist who was linked to he kidneys without
her knowledge or consent. She then argues by
analogy that a woman similarly has no moral duty
to carry her pregnancy to term. There are some
similarities here. There are also
dissimilarities. The question is, how relevant
are they? Does the analogy work? Please turn to
page 319 in the textbook.
60Reductio ad absurdum
- From Moore and Parker One common strategy for
establishing the truth of a claim is showing that
its contradictory implies something false,
absurd, or contradictory. This strategy, called
indirect proof, is based on the same idea as
remarks like this If Phillips is conservative,
then Im the King of England. Obviously, this
is just a way of saying that Phillips is not
conservative, because it is clear that I am not
the King of England.
61Reductio ad absurdum II
- If we want to argue that a claim is true by using
indirect proof, we begin with its contradictory.
To argue either for P or for not-P, we begin with
the other one and try to show that it implies a
false claim. - For example, if we wanted to prove that your
critical thinking instructor is not wealthy, we
would start by assuming the opposite, that is,
your critical thinking instructor is wealthy.
This can be shown to imply that she can buy Dodge
Vipers, mansions, designer clothes, and so forth.
Because this is all obviously ridiculous, we
have proven that, sadly, your critical thinking
instructor is not wealthy.
62Reductio ad absurdum III
- This pattern of reasoning is sometimes called
reductio ad absurdum (reducing to an absurdity,
or RAA, for short), because it involves showing
that a claim implies a false, absurd, or
contradictory result. Once again, the strategy
is this - To prove P,
- Assume not-P.
- Show that a false, absurd, or contradictory
result follows from not-P. - Conclude that not-P must be false.
- Conclude that P must be true.
63Reductio ad absurdum III
- In the case of reducing analogies to an
absurdity, we need to show that the analogy has
many dissimilarities, so that to assume
similarities between the two things might be
ridiculous.