Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 31
About This Presentation
Title:

Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1

Description:

For g differentiable, this is when 2g / x t 0 ... A function g : X x T R satisfies the strict single crossing differences property ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:189
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 32
Provided by: danq6
Category:
Tags: advanced | econ | micro | theory

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1


1
Econ 805Advanced Micro Theory 1
  • Dan Quint
  • Fall 2007
  • Lecture 4 Sept 18 2007

2
Today Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For
Equilibrium
  • Problem set 1 online (due 9 a.m. Wed Oct 3)
    email list
  • Last lecture integral form of the Envelope
    Theorem holds in equilibrium of any Independent
    Private Value auction where
  • The highest type wins the object
  • The lowest possible type gets expected payoff 0
  • Today necessary and sufficient conditions for a
    particular bidding function to be a symmetric
    equilibrium in such an auction
  • Time permitting, stochastic dominance

3
Todays General Results
  • Consider a symmetric independent private values
    model of some auction, and a bid function b T ?
    R
  • Define g(x,t) as one bidders expected payoff,
    given type t and bid x, if all the other bidders
    bid according to b
  • Under fairly broad (but not all) conditions
  • everyone bidding according to b is an
    equilibrium
  • b strictly increasing and g(b(t),t)
    g(b(t),t) òtt FN-1(s) ds

4
Necessary Conditions
5
With symmetric IPV, b strictly increasing implies
the envelope theorem
  • If everyone bids according to the same bid
    function b,
  • And b is strictly increasing,
  • Then the highest type wins,
  • And so the envelope theorem holds
  • So what were really asking here is when a
    symmetric bid function must be strictly increasing

6
When must bid functions be increasing?
  • Equilibrium strategies are solutions to the
    maximization problem maxx g(x,t)
  • What conditions on g makes every selection x(t)
    from x(t) nondecreasing?
  • Recall supermodularity and Topkis
  • If g(x,t) has increasing differences in (x,t),
    then the set x(t) is increasing in t (in the
    strong set order)
  • For g differentiable, this is when 2g / x t
    ³ 0
  • But let t t if x is not single-valued, this
    still allows some points in x(t) to be above
    some points in x(t), so it wouldnt rule out
    equilibrium strategies which are decreasing at
    some points

7
Single crossing and single crossing differences
properties (Milgrom/Shannon)
  • A function h T ? R satisfies the strict single
    crossing property if for every t t,
  • h(t) ³ 0 ? h(t) 0
  • (Also known as, h crosses 0 only once, from
    below)
  • A function g X x T ? R satisfies the strict
    single crossing differences property if for every
    x x, the function h(t) g(x,t) g(x,t)
    satisfies strict single crossing
  • That is, g satisfies strict single crossing
    differences if
  • g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t)
    0
  • for every x x, t t
  • (When gt exists everywhere, a sufficient
    condition is for gt to be strictly increasing in
    x)

8
What single-crossing differences gives us
  • Theorem. Suppose g(x,t) satisfies strict single
    crossing differences. Let S Í X be any subset.
    Let x(t) arg maxx Î S g(x,t), and let x(t) be
    any (pointwise) selection from x(t). Then x(t)
    is nondecreasing in t.
  • Proof. Let t t, x x(t) and x x(t).
  • By optimality, g(x,t) ³ g(x,t) and g(x,t) ³
    g(x,t)
  • So g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 and g(x,t)
    g(x,t) 0
  • If x x, this violates strict single crossing
    differences

Milgrom (PATW) theorem 4.1, or a special case
of theorem 4 in Milgrom/Shannon 1994
9
Strict single-crossing differences will hold in
most symmetric IPV auctions
  • Suppose b T ? R is a symmetric equilibrium of
    some auction game in our general setup
  • Assume that the other N-1 bidders bid according
    to bg(x,t) t Pr(win bid x) E(pay
    bid x)
  • t W(x) P(x)
  • For x x,
  • g(x,t) g(x,t) W(x) W(x) t
    P(x) P(x)
  • When does this satisfy strict single-crossing?

10
When is strict single crossing satisfied
byg(x,t) g(x,t) W(x) W(x) t
P(x) P(x) ?
  • Assume W(x) ³ W(x) (probability of winning
    nondecreasing in bid)
  • g(x,t) g(x,t) is weakly increasing in t, so if
    its strictly positive at t, its strictly
    positive at t t
  • Need to check that if g(x,t) g(x,t) 0, then
    g(x,t) g(x,t) 0
  • This can only fail if W(x) W(x)
  • If b has convex range, W(x) W(x), so strict
    single crossing differences holds and b must be
    nondecreasing (e.g. T convex, b continuous)
  • If W(x) W(x) and P(x) ¹ P(x) (e.g.,
    first-price auction, since P(x) x), then
    g(x,t) g(x,t) ¹ 0, so theres nothing to check
  • But, if W(x) W(x) and P(x) P(x), then
    bidding x and x give the same expected payoff,
    so b(t) x and b(t) x could happen in
    equilibrium
  • Example. A second-price auction, with values
    uniformly distributed over 0,1 È 2,3. The
    bid function b(2) 1, b(1) 2, b(vi) vi
    otherwise is a symmetric equilibrium.
  • But other than in a few weird situations, b will
    be nondecreasing

11
b will almost always be strictly increasing
  • Suppose b(-) were constant over some range of
    types t,t
  • Then there is positive probability
  • (N 1) F(t) F(t) FN 2(t)
  • of tying with one other bidder by bidding b
    (plus the additional possibility of tying with
    multiple bidders)
  • Suppose you only pay if you win let B be the
    expected payment, conditional on bidding b and
    winning
  • Since t t, either t B or B t, so
    either you strictly prefer to win at t or you
    strictly prefer to lose at t
  • Assume that when you tie, you win with
    probability greater than 0 but less than 1
  • Then you can strictly gain in expectation either
    by reducing b(t) by a sufficiently small amount,
    or by raising b(t) by a sufficiently small
    amount
  • (In addition when T has point mass
    second-price first-price)

12
So to sum up, in well-behaved symmetric IPV
auctions, except in very weird situations,
  • any symmetric equilibrium bid function will be
    strictly increasing,
  • and the envelope formula will therefore hold
  • Next when are these sufficient conditions for a
    bid function b to be a symmetric equilibrium?

13
Sufficiency
14
What are generally sufficient conditions for
optimality in this type of problem?
  • A function g(x,t) satisfies the smooth single
    crossing differences condition if for any x x
    and t t,
  • g(x,t) g(x,t) 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t) 0
  • g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0 ? g(x,t) g(x,t) ³ 0
  • gx(x,t) 0 ? gx(x,td) ³ 0 ³ gx(x,t d)
    for all d 0
  • Theorem. (PATW th 4.2) Suppose g(x,t) is
    continuously differentiable and has the smooth
    single crossing differences property. Let x
    0,1 ? R have range X, and suppose x is the sum
    of a jump function and an absolutely continuous
    function. If
  • x is nondecreasing, and
  • the envelope formula holds for every t,
  • g(x(t),t) g(x(0),0) ò0t gt(x(s),s) ds
  • then x(t) Î arg maxx Î X g(x,t)
  • (Note that x only guaranteed optimal over X, not
    over all X)

15
But
  • Establishing smooth single-crossing differences
    requires a bunch of conditions on b
  • We can use the payoff structure of an IPV auction
    to give a simpler proof
  • Proof is taken from Myerson (Optimal Auctions),
    which were doing on Thursday anyway

16
Claim
  • Theorem. Consider any auction where the highest
    bid gets the object. Assume the type space T
    has no point masses. Let b T ? R be any
    function, and define g(x,t) in the usual way. If
  • b is strictly increasing, and
  • the envelope formula holds for every t,
  • g(b(t),t) g(b(0),0) ò0t FN-1(s) ds
  • then g(b(t),t) ³ g(b(t),t), that is, no bidder
    can gain by making a bid that a different type
    would make.
  • If, in addition, the type space T is convex, b
    is continuous, and neither the highest nor the
    lowest type can gain by bidding outside the range
    of b, then everyone bidding b is an equilibrium.

17
Proof.
  • Note that when you bid b(s), you win with
    probability FN-1(s) let z(s) denote the expected
    payment you make from bidding s
  • Suppose a bidder had a true type of t and bid
    b(t) instead of b(t)
  • The gain from doing this is
  • g(b(t), t) g(b(t), t) t FN-1(t) z(t)
    g(b(t),t)
  • (t t) FN-1(t) t FN-1(t) z(t)
    g(b(t),t)
  • (t t) FN-1(t) g(x(t),t) g(x(t),t)
  • Suppose t t. By assumption, the envelope
    theorem holds, so
  • (t t) FN-1(t) òtt FN-1(s) ds
  • òtt FN-1(s) FN-1(t) ds
  • But F is increasing (weakly), so FN-1(t) ³
    FN-1(s) for every s in the integral, so this is
    (weakly) negative
  • Symmetric argument holds for t
  • So the envelope formula is exactly the condition
    that there is never a gain to deviating to a
    different types equilibrium bid

18
Proof.
  • All thats left is deviations to bids outside the
    range of b
  • With T convex and b continuous, the bid
    distribution has convex support, so we only need
    to check deviations to bids above and below the
    range of b
  • Assume (for notational ease) that T 0,T
  • If some type t deviated to a bid B b(T), his
    expected gain would be
  • g(B,t) g(b(t),t) g(B,t) g(b(T),t)
    g(b(T),t) g(b(t),t)
  • The second term is nonpositive (another types
    bid isnt a profitable deviation)
  • We also know g(x,t) t Pr(win bid x) z(x)
    has increasing differences in x and t, so for B
    b(T), if g(B,t) g(b(T),t) 0, g(B,T)
    g(b(T),t) 0
  • So if the highest type T cant gain by bidding
    above b(T), no one can
  • By the symmetric argument, we only need to check
    the lowest types incentive to bid below b(0)
  • (If b was discontinuous or T had holes, we would
    need to also check deviations to the holes in
    the range of b)
  • QED

19
So basically, in well-behaved symmetric IPV
auctions,
  • b T ? R is a symmetric equilibrium if and only
    if
  • b is increasing, and
  • b (and the g derived from it) satisfy the
    envelope formula

20
Up next
  • Recasting auctions as direct revelation
    mechanisms
  • Optimal (revenue-maximizing) auctions
  • Might want to take a look at the Myerson paper,
    or the treatment in one of the textbooks
  • If you dont know mechanism design, dont worry,
    well go over it
  • Meanwhile, since theres time

21
A Few Slides on Second-OrderStochastic Dominance
22
When is one probability distribution less risky
than another?
  • Two random variables X and Y with the same mean,
    with distributions F and G
  • Three conditions to consider
  • 1. Every risk-averse utility maximizer prefers
    X to Y, i.e., E u(X) ³ E u(Y) for every
    nondecreasing, concave u, or ò- u(s) dF(s) ³
    ò- u(s) dG(s) (also called SOSD)
  • 2. Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, or Y
    X noise r.v. Z s.t. Y d X Z, with
    E(ZX) 0 for every value of X
  • 3. For every x,ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
  • Rothschild-Stiglitz (1970) 1 2 3

23
What does this tell us?
  • Risk-averse buyers greatly impact auction design
    changes equilibrium strategies well get to
    that in a few lectures (Maskin and Riley)
  • Risk-averse sellers have less impact
    equilibrium strategies are the same, all that
    changes is sellers valuation of different
    distributions of revenue
  • Claim. With symmetric IPV, a risk-averse seller
    prefers a first-price to a second-price auction

24
Proof well show revenue in second-price auction
is MPS of revenue in first-price
  • Recall that revenue in a second-price auction is
    v2, and revenue in a first-price auction is E(v2
    v1)
  • Let X, Y, and Z be random variables derived from
    bidders valuations, as follows
  • X g(v1)
  • Z v2 g(v1)
  • Y v2
  • where g(t) ò0t s dFN-1(s) / FN-1(t) E(v2 v1
    t)
  • Note that Y X Z, andE(Z Xg(t)) E(v2
    v1 t) E(v2 v1 t) 0
  • So Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, so any
    risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y
  • But X is the revenue in the first-price auction,
    and Y is the revenue in the second-price auction
    Q.E.D.

25
A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
  • Well use the extremal method or basis
    function method
  • Well rewrite our generic (increasing concave)
    function u(s) as a positive sum of basis
    functions
  • u(s) ò- w(q) h(s,q) dq
  • with w(q) ³ 0, where these basis functions are
    themselves increasing and concave
  • Then well show that X SOSD Y if and only if
  • ò- h(x,q) dF(x) ³ ò- h(y,q) dG(y)
  • for all the basis functions
  • (Only if is trivial, since h(s,q) is increasing
    and concave if just involves multiplying this
    inequality by w(q) and integrating over q)

26
A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
  • Well do the special case of u twice
    differentiable. Our basis functions will be a
    constant, a linear term, and the
    functions h(x,q) min(x,q)
  • Claim is that u(x) a bx ò0 (-u(q))
    h(x,q) dq
  • Note that -u(q) is nonnegative, since u is
    concave
  • To see the equality, integrate by parts, with db
    -u dq, a hò a db a b ò b da
    h(x,q)u(q)q- ò- u(q) 1qxu() constant ò-x u(q) dq
  • Since X and Y have the same mean,
  • ò- (abx) dF(x) ò- (aby) dG(y)

27
A cool proof SOSD º ò-x F(s) ds ò-x G(s) ds
everywhere
  • So all thats left is to determine when
  • ò- h(s,q) dF(s) ³ ò- h(s,q) dG(s)
  • Integrate by parts u h(s,q), dv dF(s), LHS
    becomesh(,q) F() h(-,q) F(-) ò- F(s)
    hs(s,q) ds q 0 ò- F(s) 1sò- q F(s) ds
  • Similarly, the right-hand side becomes q ò- q
    G(s) ds
  • So EsF h(s,q) ³ EsG h(s,q) ò- q F(s)
    ds ò- q G(s) ds
  • So X SOSD Y if and only if this holds for every q

28
(I dont expect to get to) First-Order
Stochastic Dominance
29
When is one probability distribution better
than another?
  • Two probability distributions, F and G
  • F first-order stochastically dominates G if
  • ò- u(s) dF(s) ³ ò- u(s) dG(s)
  • for every nondecreasing function u
  • So anyone whos maximizing any increasing
    function prefers the distribution of outcomes F
    to G
  • (Very strong condition.)
  • Theorem. F first-order stochastically dominates
    G if and only if F(x) G(x) for every x.

30
Proving FOSD º F(x) G(x) everywhere
  • Proof for differentiable u. Rewrite it using a
    basis consisting of step functions dq(s)
    0 if s
  • Up to an additive constant, u(s) ò- u(q)
    dq(s) dq
  • To see this, calculate u(s) u(s) ò- u(q)
    (dq(s) dq(s)) dq òss u(q) dq
  • So F FOSD G if and only if ò- dq(s) dF(s) ³
    ò- dq(s) dG(s) for every q

31
Proving FOSD º F(x) G(x) everywhere
  • But ò- dq(s) dF(s) Pr(s ³ q) 1 F(q)and
    similarly ò- dq(s) dG(s) 1 G(q)
  • So if F(x) G(x) for all x, EsF u(s) ³ EsG
    u(s)
  • for any increasing u
  • Only if is because dq(x) is a valid increasing
    function of x
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com