Nihilism - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Nihilism

Description:

Title: How do we know what is good from evil? Author: ShockPa Last modified by: ShockPa Created Date: 12/30/2006 11:26:49 PM Document presentation format – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:213
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 37
Provided by: ShockPa
Category:
Tags: book | hope | nihilism

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Nihilism


1
Nihilism
  • By Robert G. Edwards II
  • Paul R. Shockley

2
(No Transcript)
3
Nihilism
  • The term comes from the Latin nihil, which means
    nothing.
  • It is a theory that claims there is no meaning or
    value to life, though this is often amended to
    mean that there is no overarching meaning or
    value under which all persons are subjected.

4
Nihilism
  • There is often a distinction made between
    ontological nihilism (the metaphysical claim
    about the nothingness of reality) and existential
    nihilism (makes claims about the lack of meaning
    in human existence).
  • It is guided by the rejection of objective moral
    values and the hope of the eternal.

5
Nihilism
  • It is often associated with philosopher Friedrich
    Nietzsche (1844-1900), who claimed that God was
    dead.
  • Others are the French existentialist Jean-Paul
    Sartre (1905-1980) and Albert Camus
    (1913-1960).
  • Both Sartre and Camus were affected by the
    catastrophic world wars.

6
Nihilism
  • The two of them proposed
    the utter hopelessness of life.
  • Camus compared life to the Greek myth of Sisyphus
    who was eternally condemned by the gods to push a
    heavy ball up a slope, only to have them kick
    back down.
  • Sartre suggested that there was no purpose to the
    accident of human existence.

7
Nihilism
  • Nietzsche was the son of devout Lutheran parents.
    His father was a Lutheran minister and his
    mother was the daughter of a Lutheran
    minister.
  • He studied theology and philology for one year
    before giving up his faith. He continued his
    studies in philology and was given an associate
    professorship at the age of 24.

8
Nihilism
  • He believed that humanity needed a Socratic
    figure that was free from all moral constraints
    and universal standards.
  • He distinguished between master morality and
    slave morality.
  • Master morality is basically affirmative and
    defines itself by its own terms good is defined
    as that which is noble, powerful and beautiful
    belonging to greatness.

9
Nihilism
  • Slave morality is basically negative and claims
    otherworldly values ordained by God. It is
    resentful and defines good as humility and
    pity.
  • It uses the vindictive term evil to castigate
    those opposed to it.
  • Nietzsche claimed that Jews and Christians had
    poisoned all of Europe with this morality.
  • He proposed a transvaluation of all values in
    order to move us beyond good and evil.
  • This transvaluation of values is possible when
    the ressentiment of the lower classes for the
    superior becomes so great that they find
    compensation only in imagining or creating a
    different moral code.

10
Nihilism
  • The creative genius must begin by declaring the
    death of God.
  • This allows all values related to slave morality
    to collapse and the individual to be free to
    create his/her own values.
  • The individual is freed to become an Übermensche
    as humans are to apes, who acknowledges the will
    to power.
  • All human relationships are to be understood in
    terms of power.

11
For Nietzsche, life is simply the will to power.
  • True morality is that which conforms to nature
    and condemns that which has oppressed the
    unfettered spirit of humanity.
  • He condemns as bad whatever is contrary to the
    conformity of nature.
  • Nature is essentially the will to power it is
    brutal, harsh, cruel, frightful, tragic, and
    beautiful.
  • We must say yes to life as it is.

12
The moral person lives dangerously by
increasing its mastery.
  • Morality is located in nature and its process
    it is empirical, what we will it is not
    metaphysical.
  • Struggle, through which individuals achieve a
    degree of power commensurate with their abilities
    is the basic fact of human existence.
  • Morality is not located in forms it does not
    have a starting point it is a nature-process.
  • It is earthly as opposed to spiritual it is
    empirical, not metaphysical. Moral terms are
    vacuous.

13
Nietzsche
  • Nietzsche posits the will to power as the
    dominant value that human, like all creatures
    caught in the evolutionary struggle for survival,
    desire most.
  • Genuine morality is based on this will to power,
    but there is a constant tendency on the part of
    the mediocre, the herd, to convert morality and
    promulgate a morality that promotes the passive
    virtues of self-denial, tolerance, humility, and
    resignation. This slave morality is opposed to
    the higher life of the excellent and noble, who
    will eventually win out in the struggle.

14
Criticisms
  • While some believe that an advantage of
    Nietzsches views is his critique of social
    structures, his position is self-defeating it
    cant stand up to logical strength.
  • Perspectivalism is also self-defeating.
  • Nietzsches ideas have had destructive
    consequences in history.
  • It promotes hatred, bigotry, and discrimination.
  • Radical empiricism is unwarranted.

15
Consider the following
16
The Moral Law Argument by William Lane Craig in
debate with Paul Kurtz titled, Goodness without
God is good enough which took place at Franklin
Marshall College, Oct. 24, 2001.
  • If the Theist is wrong, this doesnt mean the
    humanist is right by default. Nihilism must be
    considered as well. Nihilism says there is no
    basis for morality.
  • If Theism is true, then we have a sound
    foundation for morality.
  • a. If Theism is true, then we have an
    objective basis for moral values.
  • b. If Theism is true, then we have
    objective moral duties.
  • c. If Theism is true, then we have
    objective moral accountability.
  • If Theism is false, then there is no sound
    foundation for morality.
  • a. If Theism is false, then why think human
    values are special?
  • b. If Theism is false, then where is the basis
    for objectivity duty?
  • c. If Theism is false, then what is the basis
    for moral accountability?

17
The Standard of Justice
As an atheist my argument against God was that
the universe seemed so cruel and unjust. But how
had I got this idea of just and unjust? A man
does not call a line crooked unless he has some
idea of a straight line. What was I comparing
this universe with when I called it unjust?
Straight Line Standard
C.S. Lewis Mere Christianity, p 45.
18
We know it, but we can deny it.
  • It seems then we are forced to believe in
    a real Right and Wrong. First, human beings all
    over the earth have this curious idea that they
    ought to behave in a certain way. Second, they do
    not in fact behave in that way. The truth is, we
    believe in decency so much that we cannot bear to
    face the fact that we are breaking it, and
    consequently we try to shift the responsibility.

C.S. Lewis Mere Christianity, p 21.
19
How to use the Moral Law Argument in Discussion
of Evil
  • Consider the following argument from Ravi
    Zacharias
  • One of the strongest arguments against the
    existence of God is the presence of evil and
    suffering in the world. Can you not the see what
    is brought in through the back door in that
    question? Because if theres evil, theres good.
    If theres good there has to be a moral law. If
    theres a moral law there has to be a
    transcendent moral lawgiver. But thats what the
    skeptic is trying to disprove and not prove.
    Because if there is no moral law giver, theres
    no moral law. If there no moral law theres no
    good. If theres no good theres no evil. So
    whats the question, really? The strongest
    argument against the existence of God actually
    assumes God in the objection.

20
The Moral Law Argument by Hastings Rashdall
(1858-1924)Beginning with the objectivity of
the moral law, Rashdall reasons to an absolutely
perfect Mind
  • 1.      An absolutely perfect moral ideal exists
    (at least psychologically in our minds).
  • 2.      An absolutely perfect moral law can
    exist only if there is an absolutely perfect
    moral Mind
  • (a) Ideas can exist only if there are minds
    (thoughts depend on thinkers).
  • (b) And absolute ideas depend on an absolute
    Mind (not on individual finite minds like
    ours).
  • 3.      Hence, it is rationally necessary to
    postulate an absolute Mind as the basis for the
    absolutely perfect moral idea.

21
The Moral Law Argument by Hastings
RashdallRashdalls argument for the objectivity
of the absolute moral ideas is argued this way
  • 1.     Morality is generally understood as
    objectively binding.
  • 2.     Mature minds understand morality as being
    objectively binding (i.e., binding on all, not
    just some).
  • 3.     Moral objectivity is a rationally
    necessary postulate (because something cannot be
    judged as better or worse unless there is an
    objective standard of comparison).
  • 4.     Objective moral ideals are practically
    necessary to postulate.

22
The Moral Law Argument by Hastings
RashdallRashdalls argument for the objectivity
of the absolute moral ideas is argued this way
  • If an objective moral law exists independent of
    individual minds, then it must ultimately come
    from a Mind that exists independently of finite
    minds. It is rationally necessary to postulate
    such a Mind in order to account for the objective
    existence of this moral law.

23
The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
  • British idealism is generally distinguished by
    several ideas
  • 1. A belief in an Absolute (a single
    all- encompassing reality that in some sense
    formed a coherent and all-inclusive system)
  • A high view of reason as both the faculty by
    which the Absolute's structure is grasped and
    as that structure itself
  • 3. A rejection of a dichotomy between thought and
    object. Rather, reality consisting of
    thought-and- object together in a strongly
    coherent unity.

24
The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
  • Introduction to Sorleys argument
  • 1. It depends on the objectivity of the moral
    law.
  • 2. Since there exists a moral ideal prior to,
    superior to, and independent of all finite
    minds, there must be a supreme moral Mind
    from which this moral ideal is derived.

25
The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
  • 1.      There is an objective moral law that is
    independent of human consciousness of it and that
    exists in spite of human lack of conformity to
    it
  • (a) Persons are conscious of such a law beyond
    themselves
  • (b) Persons admit its validity is prior to their
    recognition of it (c) Persons acknowledge its
    claim on them, even while not yielding to it
  • (d) no finite mind completely grasps its
    significance
  • (e) all finite minds together have not reached
    complete agreement on its meaning, nor conformity
    with its ideal.

26
The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
  • 2.     But ideas exist only in minds.
  • 3.     Therefore, there must be a supreme Mind
    (beyond all finite minds) in which this objective
    moral law exists.

27
Moral Law Argument according to Dr. David Elton
Trueblood

Popular 20th Century American Quaker,
philosopher, Evangelical theologian.
Chaplain to both Harvard Stanford
University. Senior advisor to President David
Eisenhower close friends with President
Hoover. Founder of the Yokefellow
Movement Author of 33 books including the Humor
of Christ, The Predicament of Modern Man, Abraham
Lincoln Theologian of American Anguish
Trustworthiness of Religious Experience

28
The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
  • 1.     There must be an objective moral law
    otherwise
  • (a) There would not be such great agreement on
    its meaning.
  • (b) No real moral disagreements would ever have
    occurred, each person being right from his own
    moral perspective.
  • (c) No moral judgment would ever have been
    wrong, each being subjectively right.
  • (d) No ethical question could ever be discussed,
    there being no objective meaning to any ethical
    terms.
  • (e) Contradictory views would both be right,
    since opposites could be equally correct.

29
The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
  • 2.     This moral law is beyond individual
    persons and beyond humanity as a whole
  • (a) It is beyond individual persons, since they
    often sense a conflict with it.
  • (b) It is beyond humanity as a whole, for they
    collectively fall short of it and even measure
    the progress of the whole race by it.

30
The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
  • 3.     This moral law must come from a moral
    Legislator because
  • (a) A law has no meaning unless it comes from a
    mind only minds emit meaning.
  • (b) Disloyalty makes no sense unless it is to a
    person, yet people die in loyalty to what is
    morally right.
  • (c) Truth is meaningless unless it is a meeting
    of mind with mind, yet people die for the truth.
  • (d) Hence, discovery of and duty to the moral
    law make sense only if there is a Mind or Person
    behind it.
  • 4.     Therefore, there must be a moral, personal
    Mind behind this moral law.

31
The Moral Law Argument by Linda ZagzebskiAn
argument from moral order.
  • Dr. Zagzebski is Linda is Kingfisher College
    Chair of the Philosophy of Religion and Ethics
    George Lynn Cross Research Professor at
    University of Oklahoma.
  • Author of approx. 8 books including Virtues of
    the Mind Faith.
  • President of the Society of Christian
    Philosophers 2004-7.

32
The Moral Law Argument by Dr. Zagzebski
Zagzebski's version is rooted in the idea that
naturalism entails moral skepticism.
  • 1. Morality is a rational enterprise.
  • 2. Morality would not be a rational if moral
    skepticism were true.
  • 3. There is much too much unresolved moral
    disagreement for us to suppose that moral
    skepticism can be avoided if human sources of
    moral knowledge are all that we have.
  • 4. Therefore we must assume that there is an
    extra-human, divine source of moral wisdom.

33
A Practical Moral Law Argument by Dr. Robert
Adams
  • If there is no source of moral order morality
    will collapse. In other words, morality cease to
    be a sustainable enterprise.
  • 1. It would be demoralizing not to believe there
    is a moral order to the universe.
  • 2. Demoralization is morally undesirable.
  • 3. There is a moral advantage in believing that
    there is a moral order in the universe.
  • 4. Theism provides the best theory of the source
    of moral order.
  • 5. Therefore there is a moral advantage in
    accepting theism. (Adams, Virtues of Faith, 151)
    .

34
A Practical Moral Law Argument by Dr. Douglas
Drabkin Atheism is demoralizing.
  • In essence, Douglas Drabkin argues that the
    moral problems and ills that would afflict
    humanity if there was no God give justification
    to pause and seriously investigate, not for the
    belief that there is a God, but whether one's
    reasons for rejecting belief in God has been
    carefully thought out.

35
The Moral Law Argument by Dr. Douglas Drabkin
Atheism is demoralizing.
  • 1. Morality demands that we ought to aspire to
    become as good as we can be.
  • 2. If there is no source of moral order in the
    world, then the project of becoming as good as we
    can be is fraught with difficulties.
  • 3. These difficulties would be taken away if we
    were assured of the truth of theism.
  • 4. Therefore we have a moral reason for getting
    ourselves in a state whereby we can come to be
    believe in the truth of theism. (Drabkin, A
    moral argument for undertaking theism, 169)

36
BIBLIOGRAPHY
  • Adams, Robert, The Virtue of Faith, New York
    Oxford University Press, 1987) 144-163
  • Budziszewski, J., Written on the Heart The
    Case for Natural Law (Downers Grove
    InterVarsity Press), 1997.
  • Drabkin, Douglas, 1994, A moral argument for
    undertaking theism, American Philosophical
    Quarterly, 31 169-175 .
  • Geisler, Norman L. Baker Encyclopedia of
    Christian Apologetics. Grand Rapids, Mich.
    Baker Books, 1999 (Baker Reference Library),
    498-99.
  • ______ Frank Turek I Dont Have Enough Faith
    to be An Atheist (Wheaton Crossway, 2004),
    169-83.
  • Linda Zagzebski, Does ethics need God?, Faith
    and Philosophy (1987) 4 294-303.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com