Title: Nihilism
1Nihilism
- By Robert G. Edwards II
- Paul R. Shockley
2(No Transcript)
3Nihilism
- The term comes from the Latin nihil, which means
nothing. - It is a theory that claims there is no meaning or
value to life, though this is often amended to
mean that there is no overarching meaning or
value under which all persons are subjected.
4Nihilism
- There is often a distinction made between
ontological nihilism (the metaphysical claim
about the nothingness of reality) and existential
nihilism (makes claims about the lack of meaning
in human existence). - It is guided by the rejection of objective moral
values and the hope of the eternal.
5Nihilism
- It is often associated with philosopher Friedrich
Nietzsche (1844-1900), who claimed that God was
dead. - Others are the French existentialist Jean-Paul
Sartre (1905-1980) and Albert Camus
(1913-1960). - Both Sartre and Camus were affected by the
catastrophic world wars.
6Nihilism
- The two of them proposed
the utter hopelessness of life. - Camus compared life to the Greek myth of Sisyphus
who was eternally condemned by the gods to push a
heavy ball up a slope, only to have them kick
back down. - Sartre suggested that there was no purpose to the
accident of human existence.
7Nihilism
- Nietzsche was the son of devout Lutheran parents.
His father was a Lutheran minister and his
mother was the daughter of a Lutheran
minister. - He studied theology and philology for one year
before giving up his faith. He continued his
studies in philology and was given an associate
professorship at the age of 24.
8Nihilism
- He believed that humanity needed a Socratic
figure that was free from all moral constraints
and universal standards. - He distinguished between master morality and
slave morality. - Master morality is basically affirmative and
defines itself by its own terms good is defined
as that which is noble, powerful and beautiful
belonging to greatness.
9Nihilism
- Slave morality is basically negative and claims
otherworldly values ordained by God. It is
resentful and defines good as humility and
pity. - It uses the vindictive term evil to castigate
those opposed to it. - Nietzsche claimed that Jews and Christians had
poisoned all of Europe with this morality. - He proposed a transvaluation of all values in
order to move us beyond good and evil. - This transvaluation of values is possible when
the ressentiment of the lower classes for the
superior becomes so great that they find
compensation only in imagining or creating a
different moral code.
10Nihilism
- The creative genius must begin by declaring the
death of God. - This allows all values related to slave morality
to collapse and the individual to be free to
create his/her own values. - The individual is freed to become an Übermensche
as humans are to apes, who acknowledges the will
to power. - All human relationships are to be understood in
terms of power.
11For Nietzsche, life is simply the will to power.
-
- True morality is that which conforms to nature
and condemns that which has oppressed the
unfettered spirit of humanity. - He condemns as bad whatever is contrary to the
conformity of nature. - Nature is essentially the will to power it is
brutal, harsh, cruel, frightful, tragic, and
beautiful. - We must say yes to life as it is.
12The moral person lives dangerously by
increasing its mastery.
- Morality is located in nature and its process
it is empirical, what we will it is not
metaphysical. - Struggle, through which individuals achieve a
degree of power commensurate with their abilities
is the basic fact of human existence. -
- Morality is not located in forms it does not
have a starting point it is a nature-process. - It is earthly as opposed to spiritual it is
empirical, not metaphysical. Moral terms are
vacuous.
13Nietzsche
- Nietzsche posits the will to power as the
dominant value that human, like all creatures
caught in the evolutionary struggle for survival,
desire most. - Genuine morality is based on this will to power,
but there is a constant tendency on the part of
the mediocre, the herd, to convert morality and
promulgate a morality that promotes the passive
virtues of self-denial, tolerance, humility, and
resignation. This slave morality is opposed to
the higher life of the excellent and noble, who
will eventually win out in the struggle.
14Criticisms
- While some believe that an advantage of
Nietzsches views is his critique of social
structures, his position is self-defeating it
cant stand up to logical strength. - Perspectivalism is also self-defeating.
- Nietzsches ideas have had destructive
consequences in history. - It promotes hatred, bigotry, and discrimination.
- Radical empiricism is unwarranted.
15Consider the following
16The Moral Law Argument by William Lane Craig in
debate with Paul Kurtz titled, Goodness without
God is good enough which took place at Franklin
Marshall College, Oct. 24, 2001.
- If the Theist is wrong, this doesnt mean the
humanist is right by default. Nihilism must be
considered as well. Nihilism says there is no
basis for morality. - If Theism is true, then we have a sound
foundation for morality. - a. If Theism is true, then we have an
objective basis for moral values. - b. If Theism is true, then we have
objective moral duties. - c. If Theism is true, then we have
objective moral accountability. - If Theism is false, then there is no sound
foundation for morality. - a. If Theism is false, then why think human
values are special? - b. If Theism is false, then where is the basis
for objectivity duty? - c. If Theism is false, then what is the basis
for moral accountability?
17The Standard of Justice
As an atheist my argument against God was that
the universe seemed so cruel and unjust. But how
had I got this idea of just and unjust? A man
does not call a line crooked unless he has some
idea of a straight line. What was I comparing
this universe with when I called it unjust?
Straight Line Standard
C.S. Lewis Mere Christianity, p 45.
18We know it, but we can deny it.
- It seems then we are forced to believe in
a real Right and Wrong. First, human beings all
over the earth have this curious idea that they
ought to behave in a certain way. Second, they do
not in fact behave in that way. The truth is, we
believe in decency so much that we cannot bear to
face the fact that we are breaking it, and
consequently we try to shift the responsibility.
C.S. Lewis Mere Christianity, p 21.
19How to use the Moral Law Argument in Discussion
of Evil
-
- Consider the following argument from Ravi
Zacharias - One of the strongest arguments against the
existence of God is the presence of evil and
suffering in the world. Can you not the see what
is brought in through the back door in that
question? Because if theres evil, theres good.
If theres good there has to be a moral law. If
theres a moral law there has to be a
transcendent moral lawgiver. But thats what the
skeptic is trying to disprove and not prove.
Because if there is no moral law giver, theres
no moral law. If there no moral law theres no
good. If theres no good theres no evil. So
whats the question, really? The strongest
argument against the existence of God actually
assumes God in the objection.
20The Moral Law Argument by Hastings Rashdall
(1858-1924)Beginning with the objectivity of
the moral law, Rashdall reasons to an absolutely
perfect Mind
- 1. An absolutely perfect moral ideal exists
(at least psychologically in our minds). - 2. An absolutely perfect moral law can
exist only if there is an absolutely perfect
moral Mind - (a) Ideas can exist only if there are minds
(thoughts depend on thinkers). - (b) And absolute ideas depend on an absolute
Mind (not on individual finite minds like
ours). - 3. Hence, it is rationally necessary to
postulate an absolute Mind as the basis for the
absolutely perfect moral idea.
21The Moral Law Argument by Hastings
RashdallRashdalls argument for the objectivity
of the absolute moral ideas is argued this way
- 1. Morality is generally understood as
objectively binding. - 2. Mature minds understand morality as being
objectively binding (i.e., binding on all, not
just some). - 3. Moral objectivity is a rationally
necessary postulate (because something cannot be
judged as better or worse unless there is an
objective standard of comparison). - 4. Objective moral ideals are practically
necessary to postulate.
22The Moral Law Argument by Hastings
RashdallRashdalls argument for the objectivity
of the absolute moral ideas is argued this way
- If an objective moral law exists independent of
individual minds, then it must ultimately come
from a Mind that exists independently of finite
minds. It is rationally necessary to postulate
such a Mind in order to account for the objective
existence of this moral law.
23The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
- British idealism is generally distinguished by
several ideas - 1. A belief in an Absolute (a single
all- encompassing reality that in some sense
formed a coherent and all-inclusive system) - A high view of reason as both the faculty by
which the Absolute's structure is grasped and
as that structure itself - 3. A rejection of a dichotomy between thought and
object. Rather, reality consisting of
thought-and- object together in a strongly
coherent unity.
24The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
- Introduction to Sorleys argument
- 1. It depends on the objectivity of the moral
law. - 2. Since there exists a moral ideal prior to,
superior to, and independent of all finite
minds, there must be a supreme moral Mind
from which this moral ideal is derived.
25The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
- 1. There is an objective moral law that is
independent of human consciousness of it and that
exists in spite of human lack of conformity to
it - (a) Persons are conscious of such a law beyond
themselves - (b) Persons admit its validity is prior to their
recognition of it (c) Persons acknowledge its
claim on them, even while not yielding to it - (d) no finite mind completely grasps its
significance - (e) all finite minds together have not reached
complete agreement on its meaning, nor conformity
with its ideal.
26The Moral Law Argument by W. R.Sorley
- 2. But ideas exist only in minds.
- 3. Therefore, there must be a supreme Mind
(beyond all finite minds) in which this objective
moral law exists.
27Moral Law Argument according to Dr. David Elton
Trueblood
Popular 20th Century American Quaker,
philosopher, Evangelical theologian.
Chaplain to both Harvard Stanford
University. Senior advisor to President David
Eisenhower close friends with President
Hoover. Founder of the Yokefellow
Movement Author of 33 books including the Humor
of Christ, The Predicament of Modern Man, Abraham
Lincoln Theologian of American Anguish
Trustworthiness of Religious Experience
28The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
- 1. There must be an objective moral law
otherwise - (a) There would not be such great agreement on
its meaning. - (b) No real moral disagreements would ever have
occurred, each person being right from his own
moral perspective. - (c) No moral judgment would ever have been
wrong, each being subjectively right. - (d) No ethical question could ever be discussed,
there being no objective meaning to any ethical
terms. - (e) Contradictory views would both be right,
since opposites could be equally correct.
29The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
- 2. This moral law is beyond individual
persons and beyond humanity as a whole - (a) It is beyond individual persons, since they
often sense a conflict with it. - (b) It is beyond humanity as a whole, for they
collectively fall short of it and even measure
the progress of the whole race by it.
30The Moral Law Argument by Elton Trueblood
- 3. This moral law must come from a moral
Legislator because - (a) A law has no meaning unless it comes from a
mind only minds emit meaning. - (b) Disloyalty makes no sense unless it is to a
person, yet people die in loyalty to what is
morally right. - (c) Truth is meaningless unless it is a meeting
of mind with mind, yet people die for the truth. - (d) Hence, discovery of and duty to the moral
law make sense only if there is a Mind or Person
behind it. - 4. Therefore, there must be a moral, personal
Mind behind this moral law.
31The Moral Law Argument by Linda ZagzebskiAn
argument from moral order.
- Dr. Zagzebski is Linda is Kingfisher College
Chair of the Philosophy of Religion and Ethics
George Lynn Cross Research Professor at
University of Oklahoma. - Author of approx. 8 books including Virtues of
the Mind Faith. - President of the Society of Christian
Philosophers 2004-7.
32The Moral Law Argument by Dr. Zagzebski
Zagzebski's version is rooted in the idea that
naturalism entails moral skepticism.
- 1. Morality is a rational enterprise.
- 2. Morality would not be a rational if moral
skepticism were true. - 3. There is much too much unresolved moral
disagreement for us to suppose that moral
skepticism can be avoided if human sources of
moral knowledge are all that we have. - 4. Therefore we must assume that there is an
extra-human, divine source of moral wisdom.
33A Practical Moral Law Argument by Dr. Robert
Adams
- If there is no source of moral order morality
will collapse. In other words, morality cease to
be a sustainable enterprise. - 1. It would be demoralizing not to believe there
is a moral order to the universe. - 2. Demoralization is morally undesirable.
- 3. There is a moral advantage in believing that
there is a moral order in the universe. - 4. Theism provides the best theory of the source
of moral order. - 5. Therefore there is a moral advantage in
accepting theism. (Adams, Virtues of Faith, 151)
.
34A Practical Moral Law Argument by Dr. Douglas
Drabkin Atheism is demoralizing.
- In essence, Douglas Drabkin argues that the
moral problems and ills that would afflict
humanity if there was no God give justification
to pause and seriously investigate, not for the
belief that there is a God, but whether one's
reasons for rejecting belief in God has been
carefully thought out.
35The Moral Law Argument by Dr. Douglas Drabkin
Atheism is demoralizing.
- 1. Morality demands that we ought to aspire to
become as good as we can be. - 2. If there is no source of moral order in the
world, then the project of becoming as good as we
can be is fraught with difficulties. - 3. These difficulties would be taken away if we
were assured of the truth of theism. - 4. Therefore we have a moral reason for getting
ourselves in a state whereby we can come to be
believe in the truth of theism. (Drabkin, A
moral argument for undertaking theism, 169)
36BIBLIOGRAPHY
- Adams, Robert, The Virtue of Faith, New York
Oxford University Press, 1987) 144-163 - Budziszewski, J., Written on the Heart The
Case for Natural Law (Downers Grove
InterVarsity Press), 1997. -
- Drabkin, Douglas, 1994, A moral argument for
undertaking theism, American Philosophical
Quarterly, 31 169-175 . - Geisler, Norman L. Baker Encyclopedia of
Christian Apologetics. Grand Rapids, Mich.
Baker Books, 1999 (Baker Reference Library),
498-99. - ______ Frank Turek I Dont Have Enough Faith
to be An Atheist (Wheaton Crossway, 2004),
169-83. -
- Linda Zagzebski, Does ethics need God?, Faith
and Philosophy (1987) 4 294-303.