Aristotle - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Aristotle

Description:

Aristotle s illusion and the enactive embodied situated approach to perception Elena Pasquinelli PhD Student Elena.Pasquinelli_at_ehess.fr Institut Jean Nicod EHESS – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:108
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 34
Provided by: andrea670
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Aristotle


1
Aristotles illusion and the enactive embodied
situated approach to perception
  • Elena Pasquinelli
  • PhD Student
  • Elena.Pasquinelli_at_ehess.fr
  • Institut Jean Nicod EHESS
  • www.institutnicod.org
  • EU Network of Excellence Enactive
  • www.enactivenetwork.org

2
  • New wave in cognitive sciences
  • representationalist, computationalist,
    cognitivist view of mind (mainstream) vs
    enactive, situated, embodied view of mind
    (enactive view)
  • 3 main criticisms of the enactive situated
    embodied view towards the mainstream
  • No representations
  • Embodied, situated, distributed processes
  • Role of action and movement in perception and
    cognition
  • Different claims
  • Different theoretical frameworks
  • Aristotles illusion
  • Relation of the Aristotles illusion to motor
    possibilities
  • Experiments by Benedetti on the role of motor
    skills in the occurrence of the illusion
  • Merleau-Ponty on Aristotles illusion
  • Implicit knowledge about sensorimotor skills
  • ORegan theory of sensorimotor contingencies and
    sensorimotor knowledge
  • Explanation of the Aristotles illusion in terms
    of sensorimotor knowledge

3
Enactive embodied situated approach

4
  • cognitivist/
  • computationalist/
  • representationalist view of the mind
  • Vs
  • enactive/embodied/situated view of the mind

5
representationalist-computationalist mainstream
  • The cognitivist/classicist research program can
    be defined as a rule-based, information-processing
    model of cognition that
  • 1) characterizes problem-solving in terms of
    inputs and outputs,
  • 2) assumes the existence of symbolic, encoded
    representations which enable the system to devise
    a solution by means of computation, and
  • 3) maintains that cognition can be understood by
    focusing primarily on an organisms internal
    cognitive processes (i.e., specifically those
    involving computation and representation).

6
criticisms of the representationalist-computationa
list mainstream
  • Cognition (knowledge and perception) is not
    (limited to) being the mirror of reality
    (representation of a pre-given world)
  • criticism of symbolic processes and internal
    representations. Two possible positions are
    presented
  • internal, symbolic representations are obsolete
    for explaining cognition (i.e. Brooks, 1991
    ORegan, 2001)
  • internal symbolic representations are just not
    the whole story (i.e. Kirsh, 1995)

7
  • Cognitive processes are not (necessarily)
    centralized, i.e. there is no gap between
    cognitive processes and their surrounds
  • cognitive processes are not all in the brain ?
    study of the role of the body in cognition, of
    peripheral processes (such as the physical
    conditions of the body) in perception and action
    (i.e. Thelen, 1994 Brooks, 1991, Varela, 1991)
  • cognitive processes are not all in the (one)
    subject ? study of the role of environment
    (social physical) (i.e. Hutchins, 1995)

8
  • Perception and cognition cannot be considered
    outside the frame of action and movement
  • the motor experience plays a significant position
    in the explanation of perceptual phenomena
  • action and perception are conceived as directly
    linked as in the case of a sensory-motor loop,
    with no mediation of cognitive processes

9
two different claims within the assertion of a
key role played by action in perception
  • The first claim is that action directs
    perception through the exploration of the
    environment and that perception guides action
    Lederman, 1987 Milner, 1995.
  • The second claim is that motor competences and
    motor acts shape the perceptual content.

10
Action is for perception and perception is for
action
  • Milner, 1995 affirms the existence of two
    perceptual systems one directed to the
    construction of representations of the world and
    the other to the guidance of action. The two
    systems would be anatomically and functionally
    separated.
  • Lederman, Klatsky and colleagues (i.e. Lederman,
    1987) sustained that the hand system is an
    intelligent instrument in that it makes use of
    its motor capacities for ameliorating its
    sensitive abilities.
  • Kirsh, 1995 Successful Tetris players make use
    of epistemic actions, that is they manipulate the
    pieces that are falling, changing their
    orientation to assess the fit instead of holding
    up the performance, epistemic actions seem to
    have the effect of saving time and of increasing
    the chances of success in the game. Epistemic
    actions in fact are supposed to improve cognition
    by reducing the memory and the number of steps
    involved in mental computation (space and time
    complexity) and reducing the probability of
    error.

11
perceptual content depends upon action
  • Ecological perception tradition what we directly
    perceive is affordances
  • Affordances are usually described as -ables, as
    a ball which is catch-able possibilities for
    action Turvey, 1981 Gibson, 1979 surfaces for
    walking, chairs for sitting, space for
    navigating, and so on. It is not the absolute
    size or shape of a ledge that determines whether
    the ledge is a stepping down or a falling off
    place it depends on the particular animal that
    is facing the ledge, including its size and style
    of locomotion.
  • Theory of perception as simulated action
    Berthoz, 2002
  • perceptual activity is not confined to the
    interpretation of sensory messages but
    anticipates the consequences of action, so it is
    internal simulation of action.
  • Sensorimotor approach to perception O'Regan,
    2001
  • perceiving is doing and the content of the
    perceptual experience is determined by the
    knowledge of sensorimotor contingencies

12
Sensorimotor contingencies
  • As an exploratory activity, perception is related
    to the actions a perceiver performs and to the
    sensory consequences of his actions.
  • Thus, perception is based on skills that are both
    motor and perceptual and that are called
    sensorimotor contingencies because perception is
    contingent to the exertion of motor explorations.
  • Being a perceiver is an ability that consists in
    being able of keeping track of the
    interdependence of perception and action this
    ability comprises the capacity of keeping track
    of how what one does affects what one perceives.

13
Patterns of sensorimotor contingecies
  • In the case of habitual movements and habitual
    perceptual conditions, the interdependence of
    perception and action takes the stable form of
    patterns of sensorimotor contingencies.
  • Driving a car, for instance, is characterized,
    for the expert driver, by some stable connections
    between the actions that he performs on the wheel
    and the perceptual consequences that normally
    arise.
  • In the same way, but involving patterns of
    sensorimotor contingencies that are more stable
    and general, seeing a circular surface from a
    certain point of view is related to the ability
    of keeping track of the fact that the surface
    will look more or less elliptic when changing the
    point of view.

14
Sensorimotor knowledge
  • the patters of sensorimotor contingencies
    instantiate a form of understanding or knowledge,
    which is named by the authors sensorimotor or
    implicit knowledge, which is responsible for
    expectations and surprises
  • This knowledge has the form of a mastery.

15
Implicit knowledge
  • Implicit knowledge related to the
    motor-perceptual skills allows the subject to
    make (implicit) previsions about the perceptual
    consequences of the movements he accomplishes
  • When an object as a cube is sensed only a part of
    it enters in contact with the organs of
    perception, for instance, only a face can be
    directly viewed.
  • But all the faces of the cube are present in
    perception because of the knowledge about the
    perceptual consequences of the familiar action of
    making the tour of the object.
  • When the body makes the tour of the object, all
    the faces of the cube are viewed one after the
    other.
  • The faces are synchronously present in the
    possibility of seeing them by the same movement
    that makes them successively present and in the
    implicit knowledge of this possibility.

16
Enactive knowledge
  • (Bruner, 1956) proposes the existence of 3 types
    of knowledge
  • Symbolic knowledge, i.e. the one implied in
    language
  • Iconic knowledge (i.e. the one implied in the use
    of iconic representations, as images)
  • Enactive knowledge or knowledge by doing (i.e.
    the knowledge implied in skilled actions, such as
    riding a bycicle)

17
Praktognosie
  • Merleau-Ponty (1945) describes an implicit form
    of knowledge or praktognosie
  • Praktognosie is grounded on the motor and
    perceptual skills of the body
  • The acquisition of new motor skills represents
    the acquisition of new knowledge about the body
    and the parts of the world that are committed
    with the bodily actions
  • Praktognosie is related to concrete gestures and
    movements
  • Indicating a body part, or reproducing a gesture
    without its context, are abstract gestures
    related to abstract knowledge tailoring a dress,
    driving a car, typing a letter are all concrete
    movements, related to motor habits and concrete
    knowledge
  • In concrete movements the body and the objects
    and circustances that are committed with the
    bodily actions cannot be separated

18
Aristotles illusion
  • a case study for investigating the role of
    skilled actions in perception

19
  • The phenomenon described as Aristotles illusion
    presents the following characteristics
  • if one crosses two adjacent fingers one over the
    other and then touches the two crosses fingertips
    to a small ball, one will perceive touching two
    balls.
  • A variant consists in the two crossed fingers
    touching ones nose, thus one perceiving two
    noses

20
  • Aristotles illusion is one of the oldest
    observations about perception
  • the phenomenon was first described in Aristotles
    Metaphysics and On Dreaming
  • Successively, it was analyzed at the end of the
    XIX century and at the beginning of the XXth.
    Aristotles illusion is also taken into account
    by (Merleau-Ponty, 1945)
  • More recently, the phenomenon has been
    investigated by (Benedetti, 1985 Benedetti,
    1986) who has described Aristotles illusion as a
    form of somesthetic or tactile diplopia. The
    doubling of the object perceived with crossed
    fingers reminds in fact the doubling of an image

21
  • The phenomenon not only interests the fingertips,
    but has also been described at the level of lips,
    tongue, face, scrotum and ears
  • when the skin is displaced from its resting
    position, and a small ball is touched with the
    displaced skin, the perception of a double ball
    arises.
  • A different form of the phenomenon is described
    in 1855 by Czermak as inversion of the sensation
    when the fingers are crossed
  • if one touches with crossed fingers an object
    which presents a sharp point on one side and a
    convex surface on the other, then one perceives
    the sharp point in the location where the convex
    surface is and viceversa.

22
  • (Tastevin, 1937) has provided an explanation for
    the occurrence of the Aristotles illusion which
    is based on the activity of the neuromuscular
    apparatus
  • When the fingers are passively crossed in an
    artificial position (beyond the limit of the
    voluntary movement) and stimulated, the sensation
    of the stimulus is referred back to the limiting
    position, that is to the position they would
    achieve with voluntary muscular effort beyond
    that limit, the neuromuscular apparatus does not
    provide any further information
  • Thus, the spatial location of the stimulus is
    perceived in the natural limit position

23
  • (Merleau-Ponty, 1945) Aristotles illusion is a
    trouble of the body schema
  • The body schema is composed of the actual and
    potential motor habits and perceptual
    possibilities of the body
  • Motor habits and perceptual possibilities are
    the actions a subject is able to perform and
    normally performs, and they can be expanded by
    new acquisitions, as when one learns to dance or,
    as a blind person, to use a stick
  • Crossing the fingers is an artificial movement
    which goes beyond the motor possibilities of the
    fingers.
  • For this reason, the body schema is not able to
    comprise the crossed fingers as one organ
    directed to one and the same motor project or
    intention.
  • Thus, the crossed fingers act separately and give
    rise to separate sensations that cannot be
    unified in one percept.

24
  • Benedetti, 1985 has provided an experimental
    setting for the explanation provided by Tastevin.
  • Experiment 1 shows that tactile information with
    crossed fingers is processed as if the fingers
    were not crossed and that the information is
    processed differently when the third finger is
    crossed over or underneath the fourth
  • Experiment 2 is directed to test the second part
    of the hypothesis emitted by Tastevin that
    beyond certain limits the perceived location of
    tactile stimuli does not vary
  • Experiment 3 shows that the Aristotles illusion
    is susceptible of disappearing following
    sensorimotor training

25
Experiment 1
  • Experimental setting
  • Subjects are asked to identify the position of a
    small ball.
  • The position is expressed as the angle between
    the ball and a sharp point which is equally
    contacted.
  • In the uncrossed condition the third finger
    contacts the sharp point the sharp point is
    placed at the center of a circle and the ball is
    placed at 0 at the right of the sharp point.
  • In the crossed condition the fourth finger
    contacts the sharp point and the third finger the
    ball, which is still in the same position, even
    if the subjects are informed that the ball may
    assume different positions.
  • Results
  • In the uncrossed position the ball is judged to
    be at an average angle of 3 with the point with
    the third finger crossed over the fourth, the
    perceived angle increases to 96 with the third
    finger crossed under, the perceived angle
    decreases to -115.
  • Both 96 and -115 values are located on the left
    of the fourth finger touching the point, even if
    in the crossed position the third finger is on
    the right of the fourth one.
  • Comments
  • Thus, when the fingers are crossed, tactile
    spatial information seems to be processed as if
    fingers were uncrossed (third finger on the left
    of the fourth one).

26
Experiment 2
  • Experimental setting
  • The apparatus is analogous to the exp. 1 but
  • the 0 is on the left, while in the first
    experiment it was on the right
  • the range of normal position is between 90 and
    -90
  • the range with the third finger crossed over the
    fourth is between 90 and 180 for the third
    finger crossed under is between -180 and -90),
  • so that the limits are 84 (180 - 96) and 65
    (180 - 115) and saturation of tactile
    information (no variations in the perceived
    position) is expected at these points.
  • The fourth finger of the subjects is immobilized
    and put in contact with a sharp point and the
    third finger is again passively moved over and
    under the fourth one and contacts a small ball.
  • Results
  • The results seem to confirm the expected
    saturation effect tactile sensations with
    crossed fingers are perceived at 80 and -70.
  • Within this functional range of action the
    tactile spatial sensation follows and reproduces
    almost exactly the effective spatial position of
    the fingers beyond the indicated values, the
    experience does not change.
  • Comments
  • beyond certain limits of fingers location and
    movement, the perceived location of tactile
    stimuli does not vary

27
Experiment 3
  • Experimental setting
  • Tests whether the individuated range of action of
    the fingers can be modified by a long-lasting
    crossing.
  • The subjects crossed the third finger over the
    second and conducted a normal life with crossed
    fingers for variable periods, from 60 to 183 days
    (with short periods of rest with uncrossed
    fingers)
  • some of the subjects also underwent special
    training.
  • Spatial perception with crossed and uncrossed
    fingers and the perception of the position of the
    fingers were tested at intervals in the modality
    adopted for the experiments 1 and 2
  • Again, since the actual position of the ball is
    at 0, an error greater than 90 indicates that
    the ball is perceived as if the fingers were
    uncrossed, while an error smaller than 90
    indicates that the ball is perceived on the
    correct side.
  • Results
  • A decrease of the error from 90 is observed for
    all subjects. Hence, all the subjects learned to
    perceive the ball on the correct side with the
    second and third finger. A test performed over
    the non-trained third and fourth finger always
    elicited perception as if the fingers were
    uncrossed.
  • Comments
  • The results indicate that Aristotles illusion
    disappears after a period of training with
    crossed fingers.
  • Even when perception with the crossed fingers
    became correct, perception with uncrossed fingers
    still remained correct too ? no adaptation has
    occurred, but an extension of the range of action
    of the fingers, which now includes the crossed
    position.
  • The observed perceptual modifications (extension
    of the range within which perception varies
    following the variations of the stimuli) are
    accompanied by corresponding motor modifications.
    The percentage of correct movements ( the number
    of times a stimulus is rejoined correctly)
    greatly improve in correspondence with the
    dropping of perceptual errors. Thus motor and
    perceptual performances show a good
    correspondence.

28
  • The experiments by Benedetti show that
  • What mediates the perception of the object with
    crossed fingers is something related to the
    possible movement of the fingers
  • (but not the representation of the position of
    the fingers, which is not altered by the fact of
    crossing the subject of the illusion describes
    his fingers as crossed).
  • The configurations with uncrossed or crossed
    fingers include intertwined motor and perceptual
    components.

29
  • We can consider the two configurations with
    crossed and uncrossed fingers as different
    sensorimotor configurations and the perceptual
    and motor abilities that are connected to the
    configurations as sensorimotor skills.
  • A skilled perceiver with uncrossed fingers
    becomes an unskilled perceiver with crossed
    fingers because he lacks the proper skills
  • The unskilled perceiver lacks the capacity of
    synthesizing the partial percepts in one
    perceptual unit
  • Becoming a skilled perceiver with crossed fingers
    enlarges the capacity of synthesis

30
  • Deviations from the laws of sensorimotor
    contingency extracted by the brain can cause
    modifications in the resulting percept or
    illusions
  • Nevertheless, our brains have extracted such
    laws, and any deviation from the laws will cause
    the percept of the surfaces shape to be
    modified. Thus, for example, our brains register
    the fact that the laws associated with normal
    seeing are not being obeyed when, for example, we
    put on a new pair of glasses with a different
    prescription for a while, distortions are seen
    when the head moves (because eye movements
    provoke displacements of unusual amplitudes) or
    when we look into a fish tank (now moving the
    head produces unusual kinds of distortions), or
    dream or hallucinate (now blinking, for instance,
    has no effect). Our impression in such cases is
    that, then, something unusual is happening.
    O'Regan, 2001, pp. 944-945

31
  • Illusory phenomena as the Aristotles illusion
    might be ascribed to some form of deviation from
    the laws of sensorimotor contingency, that is
    from the habitual sensorimotor skills
  • inconsistency between expectations based on
    sensorimotor knowledge and actually gained
    sensorimotor information.

32
  • Berthoz, A. (2002). The brain's sense of
    movement. Harvard University Press.
  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence Without
    Representation. Artificial Intelligence
    Journal(47), 139-159.
  • Bruner, J., Goodnow, J., Austin, A. (1956). A
    Study of Thinking. New York Wiley.
  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there. Cambridge, MA The
    MIT Press.
  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the Wild.
    Cambridge, MA MIT Press.
  • Kirsh, D., Maglio, P. (1995). On Distinguishing
    Epistemic from Pragmatic
  • Actions. Cognitive Science, 18, 513-549.
  • Lederman, S. J., Klatzky, R. L. (1987). Hand
    movements A window into haptic object
    recognition. Cognitive Psychology, 19(3),
    342-368.
  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénoménologie de la
    perception. Paris Gallimard.
  • Milner, A. D., Goodale, M. A. (1995). The
    Visual Brain in Action. Oxford Oxford Univ.
  • Press.
  • O'Regan, K. J., Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor
    account of vision and visual consciousness.
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939-1011.
  • Thelen, E., Smith, L. B. (1994). A Dynamic
    Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition
    and Action. Cambridge, MA MIT Press.
  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., Rosch, E. (1991). The
    Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA MIT Press.
  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to
    visual perception. Houghton Mifflin Co.
  • Turvey, M. (1981). Ecological Laws of Perceiving
    and Acting In Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn.
    Cognition, 9, 237-304.
  • Viviani, P. (1990). Motor-perceptual
    interactions the evolution of an idea. In M.
    Piattelli Palmarini (Ed.), Cognitive Sciences in
    Europe Issues and trends (pp. 11-39) Golem.

33
  • Bendetti, F. (1991). Perceptual learning
    following a long-lasting tactile reversal.
    Journal of experimental psychology Human
    perception performance, 17(1), 267-277.
  • Benedetti, F. (1985). Processing of tactile
    spatial information with crossed fingers. Journal
    of Experimental Psychology Human Perception and
    Performance, 11(4), 517-525.
  • Benedetti, F. (1985). Tactile diplopia
    (diplesthesia) on the human fingers. Perception
    Psychophysics, 15(83-91).
  • Benedetti, F. (1988). Exploration of a rod with
    crossed fingers. Perception Psychophysics, 44,
    281-284.
  • Benedetti, F. (1988). Localization of tactile
    stimuli and body parts in space two dissociated
    perceptual experiences revealed by a lack of
    constancy in the presence of position sense and
    motor activity. Journal of Experimental
    Psychology Human Perception and Performance,
    14(1), 69-76.
  • Benedetti, F. (1990). Goal directed motor
    behavior and its adaptation following reversed
    tactile perception in man. Experimental brain
    research, 81, 70-76.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com