From science to arts: Beauty and simplicity in science - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

From science to arts: Beauty and simplicity in science

Description:

From science to arts: Beauty and simplicity in science Darko Pol ek dpolsek_at_public.srce.hr IUC Dubrovnik May 2004. – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:107
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 11
Provided by: dp1
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: From science to arts: Beauty and simplicity in science


1
From science to artsBeauty and simplicity in
science
  • Darko PolÅ¡ek
  • dpolsek_at_public.srce.hr
  • IUC Dubrovnik
  • May 2004.

2
Henri Poincare
  • "The scientist does not study nature because it
    is useful to do so. He studies it because he
    takes pleasure in it and he takes pleasure in it
    because it is beautiful. If nature were not
    beautiful, it would not be worth knowing..." Many
    physicists (Dirac, Einstein...) seem to hold a
    similar view, that there is a close connection
    between truth and beauty in natural science.

3
Paul Davies
  • In The Mind of God, Davis says "It is widely
    believed among scientists that beauty is a
    reliable guide to truth, and many advances in
    theoretical physics have been made by the
    theorist demanding mathematical elegance...where
    laboratory tests are difficult, these aesthetic
    criteria are considered even more important than
    experiment."

4
Beauty as a driver of scientific appreciacion
  • the work of science is both driven and sustained
    by an appreciation of beauty and a feeling of awe
    (e.g. Einstein, Dirac, Schrodinger).
  • Analysis, emotion and sensibility are integral
    components of both the scientific and the
    artistic process.
  • three levels of aesthetic experience - sensual,
    emotional/imaginative and analytical - are common
    to the experience and process of science and art.
  • The same applies for such elements as the play of
    tension and relief, realization of expectations,
    and surprise upon the encounter of unexpected
    connections of meanings.
  • These aesthetic elements can be found in a
    scientific discovery, just as they can be found
    in a good novel or a fine symphony.
  • The understanding of an essential and deep
    affinity between (great) science and (great) art
    is supported by the claims of many scientists,
    who submit that an aesthetic drive underlies
    science

5
Graham Fermelo It must be beautiful
  • to get over what Einstein meant by saying that a
    grand mathematical theory and equations must be
    beautiful think of a crossword puzzle when
    youre filling it in bits of it make sense and
    it just doesnt quite work. Then you realise
    youve got one of the things wrong and then
    click, it falls into place and it works. When you
    do a rubic cube as well, youre messing about
    with it and all of a sudden click, it falls into
    place. Thats very much akin to the feeling that
    you get mathematically when an equation really
    works. Its that click feeling and thats the
    feeling Einstein certainly had when he put
    forward his gravity equation, and indeed his
    special theory of relativity too. And yes, that
    is the feeling we get these days when we play
    with his equation, when we try to find new
    beautiful equations.

6
Quantum mechanics and aestethics
  • Paul Dirac, the author of the quantum mechanic
    theory for the electron (which predicted the
    existence of antimatter), said "It is more
    important to have beauty in one's equations than
    to have them fit experiment."
  • Bohr and Heisenbergs quantum theory engaged a
    comparison between physics and art. Bohr's view
    was influenced by the "symbolic turn" in that he
    rejected all mechanical models of the movement of
    electrons in the atom. He pronounced "the failure
    of all spatio-temporal models" and the need for
    recourse to symbolic analogies.
  • After 1924 Bohr used the notion of symbolic
    representation regularly, by which he meant all
    elements of a physical theory with no correlate
    in intuition. A more sophisticated - i.e.
    symbolic - language was required.
  • Heisenberg claimed that physical theories were
    like styles of art. He noted that the conceptual
    systems of physics (for instance, Newtonian and
    quantum) differ not only because their objects
    differ, but also because they create different
    groups of relations. As styles of art emerge
    through a set of formal rules so do symbolic
    idealizations underlying conceptual systems of
    physics. Contemporary science is changing the
    entire view of classical physics and modern
    philosophy, introducing (like a style of art) new
    presuppositions about the nature of reality.

7
J. McAllister Beauty and revolution in science
  • In assessing theories, scientists rely upon
    empirical criteria such as internal consistency,
    predictive accuracy and explanatory power.
  • beside empirical matters, aesthetic concerns are
    also operative, which cannot be defined in terms
    of a fixed set of properties, since what is
    considered attractive or beautiful has been
    different at different times and in different
    disciplines.
  • But in general, beauty in science (as in art) is
    identified via features which convey an
    impression of aptness - they are appropriate,
    fitting or seemly.
  • aesthetic criteria are as central to the
    scientist's acceptance of a theory as are
    empirical considerations.
  • theoretical innovations have aesthetic
    constraints.

8
J. McAllister 2
  • There is a distinction between empirical and
    aesthetic criteria, but the latter are not merely
    "extra-scientific", - they are an integral part
    of scientific development and change. The
    aesthetic canon is constructed by the aesthetic
    features of all past theories
  • - an inductive mechanism which ensures that the
    aesthetic canon is conservative. What compels
    scientists to accept a new paradigm is that it is
    empirically better performing. Allegiance to the
    aesthetic canon must be suspended to accept a new
    theory.
  • for some the rupture is too deep and they hang on
    to the established aesthetic paradigm - to the
    conservative aesthetic criteria. Ptolemaic
    Copernican system of heavenly motions.
  • aesthetic factors are on the side of the
    conservative trend in the choice between
    theories, while empirical factors compel
    scientists toward innovation and radical breaks
    with established views

9
Joseph Margolis Against Kuhn
  • No useful instructions from Kuhn, since aestetic
    criteria vary with time
  • Margolis argues that there is a common "reason"
    art and science share professional taste/reason
    in the sciences, as in the arts, is a function of
    historical practice.
  • What is a "good" explanatory theory (or a
    painting) is what accords with practice. Reason
    is "an artifact of historical life" and the
    aesthetic is a convenient "catchall term for the
    informality with which the most formal criteria
    can be legitimated".
  • Margolis posits consensual practices broadly
    grounding scientific praxis and aesthetic taste
    to some common practical reason governing both.
  • There can be no meaningful distinction between
    "objective" and "subjective", but at the same
    time there is no principled difference between
    what counts as objectivity in the arts and the
    sciences.
  • Margolis discerns that science does not "borrow"
    from the aesthetic, but rather the aesthetic is
    "essential to what we mean by objectivity in the
    sciences".

10
Aestetic tinkering as a scientific process
  • The role of models and metaphors
  • Example Watson and Crick - double helix
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com