Title: Theories of knowledge organization
1Theories of knowledge organization theories of
knowledgeKeynote speech given March 19. 2013,
at the 13th Meeting of the German ISKO
(International Society for Knowledge
Organization), Potsdam, 19th to 20th March
2013Birger Hjørland
2Outline
- 1. Ontological commitment
- 2. Scientific versus bibliographic
classifications - 3. The epistemological basis of classifications
- 4. Approaches to knowledge organization
- 4.1 Automatic versus human classification
- 4.2 User-based and cognitive approaches
- 4.3 Facet classifications
- 4.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- 4.5 Bibliometric approaches
- 4.6 Domain-analytic classification
- 5. Conclusion
3- 1. Ontological commitment
41. Ontological commitment
- The core issues in knowledge organization are to
determine semantic relations between concepts and
to ascribe subjects to documents. - For example
- To say that a cat is a mammal
- To say that a given document is about cats
- These issues also involve determining the meaning
of the words cat, mammal, aboutness (and
further concepts such as species, concepts,
generic relation etc.)
51. Ontological commitment
- Normally non-experts would just say that we know
what a cat is and that we know that it is a
mammal. If challenged we might look it up in an
authoritative source, either a general
encyclopedia or an authoritative biological
handbook or ask some experts. - In the case of cats and mammals, this might be
safe, but in many other cases there are no
consensus among experts. In main-stream
biological systematics major groups of animals
(such as fishes and reptiles) are no longer
regarded as valid systematic units.
61. Ontological commitment
- Cladistics is a novel classificatory method and
philosophy adopted by zoologists in the last few
decades, which has provided a rather turbulent
state of zoological classification (see Blake,
2011). - In brief the new cladistic approach prefers to
group animals based exclusively on shared
ancestry rather than on shared features such as
in the traditional Linnaean system.
71. Ontological commitment
- How to classify animals (and even to say what
a species is both in an abstract and concrete
sense as in cats) is not something that is simply
given but it is something which depends on
background theories (paradigms), and in
biological systematics we have today different
competing paradigms. - This may be hard to understand and to accept,
because in the traditional epistemology we start
seeing and from there construe our theories based
on the given. Here things are turned up-side
down Our theories determine what we see
something as!
81. Ontological commitment
- The notion of ontological commitment has come to
prominence in the second half of the twentieth
century, mainly through the work of Willard Quine
1908-2000 . - On Quines view the right guide to what exists
is science, so that our best guide to what exists
is our best current scientific theory what
exists is what acceptance of that theory commits
us to. (Craig, 1998)
91. Ontological commitment
- Of course things may be classified in many ways.
Animals may, for example, be classified according
to weight and size, color, sweetness, and
usefulness for human beings. - This is often done, for example, in books for
children, or by authorities pests etc. There is
no one correct way of classifying things, and
classifications should always be considered in
relation to their purposes, and everything is
always classified in many ways. - Where does this leave KO as a scholarly field?
101. Ontological commitment
- At present, many, perhaps most, current
bibliographic classifications for mammals reflect
quite outdated science. The latest edition of
DDC, for example, arranges mammals in essentially
the same way as the second edition of 1885
(Blake, 2011, p. 469) - Such outdated classifications may still do
their job well. The library of the Zoological
Society of London uses its own scheme, devised in
the 1960s and largely based on the Bliss
Bibliographic Classification, to classify the
monographs it holds. The librarian reports that,
in most cases, her patrons are able to retrieve
items and browse the collection effectively
(Blake, 2011, p. 469-470)
111. Ontological commitment
- Can it really be true that such outdated
classifications may still do their job well? - Might the reason be that library
classifications do not serve advanced retrieval
purposes (e.g. within front-end research)? Or
that libraries and databases do not support the
dissemination of new knowledge to the general
public? - If we have such low level of ambition concerning
classification systems, is there then a need for
KO as a scholarly research discipline? (Can the
kind of work done in revising DDC be said to be
scholarly?)
121. Ontological commitment
- Even if there is no one true classification,
it does not mean that any classification is as
good as anyone else. - If KO is to be taken seriously as a scholarly
field, it must be based on knowledge about the
implications of alternative ways of classifying. - We should not say we know that X is a kind of
Y. We should say that according to a given view
X is considered a kind of Y (but according to
other views and interests X is a kind of Z). - The scholarly basis for classification is to
consider the underlying paradigms and make an
informed choice.
13- 2. Scientific / scholarly versus
- bibliographic classifications
142. Scientific versus bibliographic
classifications
- Mai (2004, p. 41) argued that scientific
classification of natural objects, and the
bibliographic classification of the content of a
document, are distinct . - I find this understanding harmful because it
undermines the important relation between subject
knowledge and bibliographical classification
(e.g. between knowledge about zoological taxonomy
and the design of classification systems on
animals for bibliographic databases).
152. Scientific versus bibliographic
classifications
- The way biologists classify living organisms is,
for example, reflected in bibliographical
classification schemes such as the UDC (with some
delay). - Blake (2011) writes that cladistics is a novel
classificatory method and philosophy adopted by
zoologists in the last few decades, which has
provided a rather turbulent state of zoological
classification. - Both scientific classification and bibliographic
classification are subject to the same kinds of
theory-dependence, interpretation and
difficulties (i.e. the paradigm shift from
Linnaean to cladistic classification).
162. Scientific versus bibliographic
classifications
- The same was shown by Ørom in the field of art
The way works of art are presented in museums,
the way histories of art are organized and the
way bibliographical classifications are organized
are all dependent on the view of art (theory or
philosophy of art) which has dominated the people
making the organization.
172. Scientific versus bibliographic
classifications
Figure 1 Social values worldviews scholarly
paradigms (After Ørom, 2003, p. 132)
18 - 3. The epistemological basis of classifications
193. The epistemological basis of classifications
- Some classifications are based on logic (e.g.,
that even numbers are numbers). The philosophical
school of conceptual analysis is an attempt to
generalize the use of a priory analysis for
classification (see Hanna, 1998). - Some classifications are based on empirical
studies. A drug is classified as, e.g.
tranquilizer, based on medical experiments. - Some classifications are based on human
conventions (e.g. the borders of a country, who
is a royal person).
203. The epistemological basis of classifications
- Some classifications are based on heritage
(e.g., who belongs to a certain family). The
cladistics school in biological systematics which
today is the dominant school is based on this
principle. - Some classifications are based on purpose (e.g.
tools for cooking). - Some classifications are based on a mixture of
criteria (e.g., combined logical, empirical,
historicist and pragmatic criteria)
213. The epistemological basis of classifications
- Logical, empirical, historicist and pragmatic
methods may each have applications for which they
are especially relevant but each may also be
generalized and used more widely because of
traditions and ideologies. - How do we determine whether one or another
classification is best? To evaluate a
classification is to consider the methods by
which it has been produced and to evaluate the
logic, empirical studies, knowledge of human
conventions, the genealogy, and the goals the
classification is meant to serve.
223. The epistemological basis of classifications
- In other words To evaluate a classification is
to engage in the research which lies behind the
classification in order to check its validity and
relevance. - All research is influenced by epistemological
norms or commitments. There is no simply correct
way of doing research or one correct and
all-encompassing scientific method and also in
the theory of knowledge consensus is rare. In my
view versions of pragmatism/activity theory are
the best candidate for fruitful philosophy of
enquiry, but this issue is still open and is in a
somewhat confused condition today.
233. The epistemological basis of classifications
- The classical theories of empiricism and
rationalism are still very much alive and
influential in contemporary research (although
mostly unrecognized). These theories have been
characterized as a trap, and the point here is
that if we understand their shortcomings, we may
avoid the trap and do better research leading to
better classifications. Empiricism and
rationalism used to be considered the fundamental
epistemological positions (and their combination
was tried by the logical positivists in the
beginning of the 20th century without success).
243. The epistemological basis of classifications
- Because of their shortcomings, we need to include
some alternatives. I consider four theories the
basic epistemological theories Empiricism,
rationalism, historicism and pragmatism/activity
theory. - But there are many labels in use today, including
actor-network theory, cognitivism, critical
rationalism, critical realism, critical theory,
dialectical materialism/Marxism, feminist
epistemology, hermeneutics , paradigm theory,
phenomenology, postmodernism (late modernism),
semiotics, social epistemology and social
constructivism.
253. The epistemological basis of classifications
- I do not think that all these epistemologies have
important different implications for KO. As
pragmatic philosophers say If a theory is of no
practical consequence it is indifferent and
trivial. - The most important thing in the criticism of
empiricism, rationalism and positivism is - Knowledge is a social and historical product made
to serve certain purposes and interests. It is
important to reconsider knowledge claims in the
light of new purposes, conditions and interests.
263. The epistemological basis of classifications
- Example Textbooks like Harter (1986), Lancaster
(2003), Large, Tedd Hartley (2001), and
Svenonius (2000) can be characterized as texts
that solidify the use of technical and managerial
language in LIS in the sense that they are
basically how-to books, constantly referring to
techniques, standards, principles, methods and
rules. If one's professional knowledge base has
such texts at its foundation, no critical
attitude is developed nor demanded because these
textbooks do not question at all the role of
information seeking or of knowledge organization
systems in culture and society.
273. The epistemological basis of classifications
- They do not provide students with a language, an
understanding, a knowledge that make them capable
of participating in public discourse debating the
functionality and legitimacy of these systems
(Andersen, 2005) - I believe Jack Andersens quote can be
interpreted as a critical epistemological view of
KO. (And, by the way, JA is inspired by activity
theory). - However, a critical view cannot be separated from
knowledge about technical aspects.
28- 4. Approaches to knowledge organization
- 4.1 Automatic versus human classification
- 4.2 User-based and cognitive approaches
- 4.3 Facet classifications
- 4.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- 4.5 Bibliometric approaches
- 4.6 Domain-analytic classification
29- 4.1 Automatic versus human classification
304.1 Automatic versus human classification
- In overviews of KO a fundamental difference
between computer based versus human based
classification and indexing is often made. In
Hjørland (2011) I argue, however, that this
distinction is theoretically unfruitful. - Both human indexers and programmers are guided by
their knowledge (theories) which at the deepest
is connected to their (implicit) theories of
knowledge (of which the most important are
(empiricism, rationalism, positivism) on the one
hand and (historicism, hermeneutics, pragmatism,
AT) on the other (to be demonstrated below))
31- 4.2 User-based and cognitive classifications
324.2 User-based and cognitive classifications
- User-based and cognitive views have been
influential in KO since the 1970s. Hjørland
(2013b) is a critical analysis of this approach. - If KO addresses questions such as Should document
A be classified in class X? Is term A synonymous
with term B? It is difficult to understand how
the study of users (qua users) can provide the
knowledge needed to answer such questions. - It is therefore difficult to understand why
user-studies have been so popular an approach in
KO.
334.2 User-based and cognitive classifications
- One hypothesis is that this is caused by the
influence of empiricist/positivist ideals of
science - It seems better science to make empirical studies
of users than to engage in say literary genre
studies, theories of art or the philosophy of
biological taxonomy. (It is also much easier to
avoid difficult theoretical problems by basing KO
on the study of user-preferences). - User-based approaches is thus seen as an ideology
with a problematic basis with roots in
empiricism.
34- 4.3 Facet classifications
354.3 Facet classifications
- In Hjørland (2013a) I found that the facet
analytic approach is based on the epistemology of
rationalism. - The strength of this approach is its logical
principles and the way it provides structures in
knowledge organization systems (KOS).
364.3 Facet classifications
- The main weaknesses are
- its lack of empirical basis and
- its speculative ordering of knowledge without
basis in the development or influence of theories
and socio-historical studies. - It seems to be based on the problematic
assumption that relations between concepts are a
priori and not established by the development of
models, theories and laws. - This tradition thus demonstrates how rationalism
as a theory of knowledge has influenced KO.
37- 4.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
384.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- Statistical methods such as cluster analysis,
factor analysis etc. are used in many different
sciences and on many different kinds of data
(e.g. for classification of diseases or
biological organisms). - They are also used for classifying documents
(vector space models, latent semantic indexing,
etc.) and may therefore also be considered an
approach to KO. - (Normally Information Retrieval (IR) and KO are
considered different fields, but I argue that
they should be considered different approaches).
394.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- IR is an extremely wide and complex field, and it
may seem hasty and problematic to go into this
field in such an overall way as is attempted
here. However, these techniques are competing
with other approaches to KO (and seemingly have
much more success and authority in academia
today). I therefore feel that we in KO have to
take numeric taxonomic/IR-approaches very
seriously, and if we want to make room for other
approaches, we have to provide convincing
argumentation about the limits of mainstream IR.
404.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- In this presentation I shall limit myself to
approaches based on statistical measures of
similarity between documents (including between
queries and documents). - Such statistical measures look like objective
science. However, things may be similar in many
different ways, and the seemingly objective
nature of these approaches may be illusionary
414.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- Even in the field of numerical taxonomy, where
the use of similarity coefficients has been even
more widespread than in information retrieval,
Jackson, Somers and Harvey (1989) were moved to
conclude that the choice of a similarity
coefficient is largely subjective and often based
on tradition or on a posteriori criteria such as
the interpretability of the results, and went
on to quote Gordon (1987) Human ingenuity is
quite capable of providing a post hoc
justification of dubious classifications.
(Ellis, Furner-Hines Willett, 1993, p. 144)
424.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- Presented in these terms, the history of
research into the use of similarity coefficients
in text retrieval appears to betray a lack of
progress (Ellis, Furner-Hines Willett, 1993,
p. 141). - My claims are 1) that all numeric taxonomic
approaches need to have criteria on how to choose
among alternative algorithms 2) that such
criteria must be based on subject theories (e.g.
cladistic research) on what should be considered
similar.
434.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- It should also be considered that IR is applied
to collections of descriptions of objects (e.g.
animals). We therefore have different levels of
epistemology - The way the objects are described in the
literature influenced by various paradigms. - The way a given collection is made influences
which paradigms are dominating - The way a given similarity measure is chosen
supports given paradigms at the expense of
others.
444.4 Numeric taxonomic approaches
- Without information from substantial theories,
IR-approaches are based on problematic empiricist
ideals and must fail. - (If they are successful after all, it might be
that subject knowledge has been used indirectly,
e.g. by relevance-assessments).
45- 4.5 Bibliometric classifications
464.5 Bibliometric classifications
- Methods based on citation analysis (e.g.
co-citation analysis and bibliometric coupling)
represent a unique set of approaches, which can
be used to construe atlases of sciences, provide
candidate terms for thesauri and many other kinds
of knowledge organizing systems (KOS). - What are the principal strengths and limits of
such methods?
474.5 Bibliometric classifications
- In general, it cannot be expected that methods
based on citation analysis are able to produce
intellectual maps such as geographical maps,
biological taxonomies or periodical systems. A
geographical structure, for example, places
different regions in a structure that is
autonomous in relation to the documents that are
written about those regions. You cannot produce a
geographical map of Spain by making, for example,
bibliometric maps of the literature about Spain
Yet such autonomous structures as maps of Spain
are often very useful for information retrieval
about Spain (Hjørland, 2002, p. 452).
484.5 Bibliometric classifications
- In Hjørland (submitted) I make the distinction
between KOS reflecting intellectual KO versus KOS
reflecting social KO - The intellectual aspect of KO is knowledge
organized in concepts, propositions, models,
theories, and laws. Such intellectual
organizations are primarily structured via
relations of explanatory coherence (Thagard,
1992, p. 9), which are again primarily related to
questions concerning truth.
494.5 Bibliometric classifications
- The social aspect of KO is knowledge organized
into academic departments, disciplines,
cooperative networks, administrative bodies etc.
Such social organizations are primarily
structured by the social division of labor in
societies which are again primarily related to
questions concerning social relevance, authority
and power. - I argue that citation-based approaches are by
nature social organizations, and by implication
the principal limits of these approaches are tied
to the relation between intellectual and social
KO.
504.5 Bibliometric classifications
- Bibliographic methods therefore cannot render
subject knowledge superfluous (but are themselves
like numeric taxonomy dependent on subject
knowledge). - Although bibliometrics is often associated with
domain-analysis, I here argue for considering
these approaches separately.
51- 4.6 Domain-analytic classification
524.6 Domain-analytic classification
- The domain-analytic (DA) view first of all
recognizes the need for subject knowledge in
classification and indexing. - A fine domain-analytic study is Blake (2011) who
demonstrates solid knowledge about zoological
taxonomy and the competing approaches in the
field (cladistics, evolutionary taxonomy and the
Linnaean system). - He also carefully discusses the relations between
scientific theory, quasi-taxonomic groupings, the
specific demands that information retrieval puts
on classifications (including the principles of
literary warrant).
534.6 Domain-analytic classification
- Finally Blake describes the classifications used
by biologists in their writings (monographs) and
reveals the tendency to use conflicting or
inconsistent classifications (corresponding to
Øroms (2003) concept bricolage). - The domain-analytic view is the only view which
is fully committed to exploring knowledge
organization in the light of subject knowledge
and substantial scholarly theories (and their
epistemological basis).
544.6 Domain-analytic classification
- The criticism raised against other approaches to
KO is made from the theoretical position of
domain-analysis. In all cases it was found that
the subject-knowledge perspective of DA cannot be
dismissed. - That is not to say that other approaches (e.g.
IR-approaches) are not the most efficient
approaches we have today. I am just claiming that
their theoretical bases are problematic and that
such approaches might be improved by considering
domain-analytic perspectives.
554.6 Domain-analytic classification
- Have arguments been put forward against
domain-analysis? - Not really. Even leading scholars of other
approaches seem to avoid direct discussions. The
resistance towards DA seems mostly to be unvoiced
or unspoken. - Although DA is gaining influence, there still
seems to be a silent resistance. Why?
564.6 Domain-analytic classification
- Some possible reasons may be
- the need to design concrete systems rather than
to develop theoretical principles - the problematic tendency to use techniques, not
theory to direct scientific practice (the
so-called law of the instrument) - The displeasure to be involved in subject
knowledge (and the fear of loosing ones own
disciplinary identity)
57 58Conclusion
- The necessity of subject knowledge in KO (as in
the broader field of information science/ library
and information science) is certainly not a new
idea. This kind of knowledge has always been
assumed in high standard libraries and
bibliographical databases such as the National
Library of Medicine and the MEDLINE database. - (In parallel to teaching qualifications the
higher the level of teaching, the bigger are the
demands on subject knowledge, at the university
level research qualifications are demanded).
59Conclusion
- In spite of this subject knowledge has been and
still is extremely neglected in KO. My claim is
that the neglect of the importance of subject
knowledge has brought forward a crisis in KO, and
that no real progress can be observed in the
field. - There is real progress in digital technologies,
and these are used to improve KO and IR, but this
is mainly progress caused by developments outside
our field. -
60Conclusion
- Where does this place the theory of knowledge in
KO? The first thing to say is that you cannot
classify domains on the basis of theories of
knowledge (or other metadisciplines, including
genre studies, the sociology of knowledge etc.).
Our studies have to be based on concrete domains. - Epistemology is, however, the best general
background it is possible to educate people
within in information science. It is the best
general preparation we can provide people with in
order to study any domain.
61Conclusion
- The general lesson I draw from epistemology is
that knowledge is created by humans for some
specific purposes and serve some interests better
than others. Concepts and semantic relations are
not a priori or neutral, but should be examined
in relation to their implications for the users
they are meant to serve. - I hope that my discussion of existent approaches
to KO has been able to make this claim probable.
62- Thank you for your attention!
63References
- Ammon, Ulrich (1977). Probleme der
Soziolinguistik. 2. Aufl. Tübingen Niemeyer. - Andersen, Jack (2005). Information Criticism
Where is it? Progressive Librarian, no. 25, pp.
12-22. http//web.archive.org/web/20110611100746/h
ttp//www.libr.org/pl/PL25_summer2005.pdf - Anderson, J.D. Pérez-Carballo, J. (2001a). The
nature of indexing how humans and machines
analyze messages and texts for retrieval. Part I
research, and the nature of human indexing.
Information Processing Management, 37 (2),
231-254. - Anderson, J.D. Pérez-Carballo, J. (2001b). The
nature of indexing how humans and machines
analyze messages and texts for retrieval. Part
II machine indexing, and the allocation of human
versus machine effort. Information Processing
Management, 37 (2), 255-277
64References
- Blake, James (2011). Some Issues in the
Classification of Zoology. Knowledge
Organization, 38(6), 463-472. - Broadfield, A. (1946). The philosophy of
classification. London Grafton. - Civallero, Edgardo (2011). UDC Biology Revision
Project First Stage Class 59 Vertebrates
http//eprints.rclis.org/16450/1/Civallero20-20U
DC20Biology20Revision20Project20-202011.pdf - Cooper, R. (2005). Classifying madness A
philosophical examination of the diagnostic and
statistical manual of mental disorders. Berlin
Springer. - Craig, E. (1998). Ontology. Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version 1.0, London
Routledge. -
65References
- Ellis, David Furner-Hines, Jonathan Willett,
Peter (1993).Measuring the degree of similarity
between objects in text retrieval systems.
Perspectives in Information Management, 3(2),
128-149 - Feinberg, Melanie (2008). Classification as
Communication Properties and Design. A
dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of
the requirements for the degree of Doctor of
Philosophy. Washington University of Washington.
http//www.ischool.utexas.edu/feinberg/Feinberg2
0dissertation.pdf - Feinberg, Melanie (2011). Classification as
Communication Properties and Design. Ann Arbor,
MI ProQuest, UMI Dissertation Publishing. - Fox, Melodie J. (2012). Book review of two books
by Rick Szostak. Knowledge Organization, 39(4),
300-303.
66References
- Gordon, A.D. (1987). A review of hierarchical
classification. Journal of the Royal Statistical
Society, Series A (General), 150(2), 119-137. - Hanna, Robert (1998). Conceptual analysis. In
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version
1.0, London Routledge. - Hansson, Joacim. (2006). Knowledge organization
from an institutional point of view Implications
for theoretical practical development.
Progressive Librarian A Journal for Critical
Studies Progressive Politics in Librarianship,
27 3143. - Hetherington, John (2000). Role of theory and
experimental design in multivariate analysis and
mathematical modeling. In H.E.A.Tinsley S. D.
Brown (eds). Handbook of applied multivariate
statistics and mathematical modeling (pp. 37-63).
San Diego Academic press.
67References
- Hjørland, B. (1998a). Information retrieval, text
composition, and semantics. Knowledge
Organization, 25(1/2), 16-31. - Hjørland, B. (1998b). The classification of
psychology. Knowledge Organization, 25(4),
162-201 - Hjørland, B. (2002) The Methodology of
Constructing Classification Schemes. A Discussion
of the State-of-the-Art. Advances in Knowledge
Organization, 8, 450-456. - Hjørland, B. (2008a). Book review of Ereshefsky
(2007) The Poverty of the Linnaean Hierarchy A
Philosophical Study of Biological Taxonomy.
Knowledge Organization, 35(4), 255-259. - Hjørland, B. (2008b). Core classification theory
A reply to Szostak. Journal of Documentation,
64(3), 333-342.
68References
- Hjørland, B. (2010). The foundation of the
concept of relevance. Journal of the American
Society for Information Science and Technology,
61(2), 217-237. - Hjørland, B. (2011). The Importance of Theories
of Knowledge Indexing and Information retrieval
as an example. Journal of the American Society
for Information Science and Technology, 62(1),
72-77. - Hjørland, B. (2013a). Facet analysis The logical
approach to knowledge organization. Information
Processing Management, 545-557. - Hjørland, B. (2013b). User-based and cognitive
approaches to knowledge organization A
theoretical analysis of the research literature.
Knowledge Organization, 40(1), 11-27. - Hjørland, B (submitted). Bibliometrics a dynamic
approach to knowledge organization
69References
- ISO 2788 (1986). Documentation Guidelines for
the establishment and development of monolingual
thesauri. International Organization for
Standardization. - Jackson, D.A., Somers, K.M., Harvey, H.H.,
(1989). Similarity Coefficients Measures of
Co-Occurrence and Association or Simply Measures
of Occurrence? The American Naturalist, 133(3),
436-453. - Kaplan, Abraham (1964). The conduct of inquiry
Methodology for Behavioral Science. New York
Chandler Publishing. - Mai, Jens-Erik. 2004. Classification in context
relativity, reality, and representation.
Knowledge organization 31(1), 3948.
70References
- Mai, J.-E. (2012). Den Gode Klassifikation (The
Good Classification). Royal School of Library and
Information Science, Copenhagen, Denmark, Sept.
13, 2012. Inaugural lecture for the
professorship in information studies .
http//www.youtube.com/watch?vnXLpK0JqRyM - Mammen, J. (2008). What is a concept? Journal of
Anthropological Psychology, 19, 2527. - Moser, Paul K. (1998). A priori. In Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version 1.0, London
Routledge. - Ørom, A. (2003). Knowledge organization in the
domain of art studies - history, transition and
conceptual changes. Knowledge organization,
30(3/4), 128-143.
71References
- Rescher, Nicholas (1998). Fallibilism. In
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version
1.0, London Routledge - Small, H. G. (1973). Co-citation in the
relationship between two documents. Journal of
the American Society for Information Science,
24(4), 256269. - Svenonius, E. (2000). The intellectual foundation
of information organization. Cambridge, MA MIT
Press. - Tennis, Joseph T. (2003). Two Axes of Domains for
Domain Analysis. Knowledge Organization, 30(3/4),
191-195. - Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions.
Princeton Princeton University Press.
72References
- Toulmin, Stephen (1999). Knowledge as shared
procedures. In Engeström, Yrjö Miettinen,
Reijo Punamäki, Raija-Leena (eds.) Perspectives
on Activity Theory (pp. 70-86). Cambridge, UK
Cambridge University Press. - Will, Leonard (2009). Glossary of terms relating
to thesauri and other forms of structured
vocabulary for information retrieval. Retrieved
February 16, 2013 from http//www.willpowerinfo.c
o.uk/glossary.htm - Wilson, D. E. Reeder, D. M. eds. (2005).
Mammal species of the world a taxonomic and
geographic reference. 3rd ed. Baltimore Johns
Hopkins University Press. - Wilson, Patrick (1968). Two kinds of power An
essay on bibliographic control. Berkeley, CA
University of California Press.
73References
- Wilson, Patrick (1983). Second-hand knowledge. An
inquiry into cognitive authority. Westport, Conn.
Greenwood Press.