Title: Bargaining
1Bargaining
- Whoever offers to another a bargain of any kind,
proposes to do this. Give me that which I want,
and you shall have this which you want and it
is this manner that we obtain from one another
the far greater part of those good offices we
stand in need of. It is not from the benevolence
of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we
expect our dinner, but from their regard to their
own interest. - -- A. Smith, 1776
2Bargaining
- We Play a Game
- Bargaining Games
- Credibility
- Subgame Perfection
- Alternating Offers and Shrinking Pies
3We Play a Game
PROPOSER RESPONDER Player ____ Player
____ Offer _____ Accept Reject
4The Ultimatum Game
REJECTEDACCEPTED
N 20 Mean 1.30 9 Offers gt 0 Rejected 1 Offer
lt 1.00 (20) Accepted (3/6/00)
5The Ultimatum Game
OFFERS 5 4 3 2 1 0
REJECTED ACCEPTED
N 32 Mean 1.75 10 Offers gt 0 Rejected 1
Offer lt 1 (20) Accepted (2/28/01)
6The Ultimatum Game
OFFERS 5 4 3 2 1 0
REJECTED ACCEPTED
N 38 Mean 1.69 10 Offers gt 0 Rejected 3
Offers lt 1 (20) Accepted (2/27/02)
1 subject offered 0
7The Ultimatum Game
REJECTEDACCEPTED
N 12 Mean 2.77 2 Offers gt 0 Rejected 0
Offers lt 1.00 (20) Accepted (7/10/03)
8The Ultimatum Game
What is the lowest acceptable offer?
2.50 1.00
N 38 Mean 1.69 10 Offers gt 0 Rejected 3
Offers lt 1 (20) Accepted (2/27/02)
0 3.31 5 P1
1 subject offered 0
9The Ultimatum Game
- Theory predicts very low offers will be made and
accepted. - Experiments show
- Mean offers are 30-40 of the total
- Mode 50
- Offers lt20 are rare and usually rejected
- Guth Schmittberger, and Schwarze (1982)
- Kahnemann, Knetsch, and Thaler (1986)
- Also, Camerer and Thaler (1995)
10The Ultimatum Game
- How can we explain the divergence between
predicted and observed results? - Stakes are too low
- Fairness
- Relative shares matter
- Endowments matter
- Culture, norms, or manners
- People make mistakes
- Time/Impatience
11Bargaining Games
- Bargaining involves (at least) 2 players who face
the the opportunity of a profitable joint
venture, provided they can agree in advance on a
division between them. - Bargaining involves a combination of common as
well as conflicting interests. - The central issue in all bargaining games is
credibility the strategic use of threats,
bluffs, and promises.
12Bargaining Games
Divide a Dollar
Two players have the opportunity to share 1, if
they can agree on a division beforehand. Each
writes down a number. If they add to 1, each
gets her number if not they each get 0. Every
division s.t. x (1-x) 1 is a NE.
P1 x P2 1-x.
Disagreement point
13Chain Store Game
Credibility
A firm (Player 1) is considering
whether to enter the market of a monopolist
(Player 2). The monopolist can choose to fight
the entrant, or not.
1
Enter Dont Enter Fight
Dont Fight
2
(2,2)
(0,0) (3,1)
14Credibility
Battle of the Sexes
F O F O
Player 1
2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2
Fight Opera F O
F O (2,1) (0,0) (0,0)
(1,2)
Player 2
Is there a credible threat?
15Battle of the Sexes
Credibility
EP1 2/3 1/3
2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2
p 2/3
FIGHT OPERA
4/3
p 1/3
q
NE (1, 1) (0, 0) (2/3, 1/3) Prudent 1/3,
2/3)
16Battle of the Sexes
Credibility
P2
2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2
FIGHT OPERA
BATNA
P1
NE (1, 1) (0, 0) (2/3, 1/3)
Best Alternative to a Negotiated Agreement
17Subgame Perfection
Subgame a part (or subset) of an extensive game,
starting at a singleton node (not the initial
node) and continuing to payoffs. Subgame Perfect
Nash Equilibrium (SPNE) a NE achieved by
strategies that also constitute NE in each
subgame. eliminates NE in which the players
threats are not credible. selects the outcome
that would be arrived at via backwards induction.
18Subgame Perfection
Chain Store Game
A firm (Player 1) is considering
whether to enter the market of a monopolist
(Player 2). Player 2 can then choose to fight
the entrant, or not.
1
Enter Dont Enter Fight
Dont Fight
2
(2,2)
(0,0) (3,1)
Subgame
19Subgame Perfection
Chain Store Game
Fight Dont Enter Dont
0, 0 3, 1 2, 2 2, 2
1
Enter Dont Fight
Dont
2
(2,2)
(0,0) (3,1)
Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium
NE (E,D), (D,F). SPNE (E,D).
20Subgame Perfection
Mini-Ultimatum Game
5,5 0,0 8,2 0,0
- A(ccept)
- 2
- H(igh)
- 1
-
- L(ow)
- R(eject)
Proposer (Player 1) can make High Offer
(50-50) or Low Offer (80-20).
21Subgame Perfection
Mini-Ultimatum Game
5,5 0,0 8,2 0,0
- A(ccept)
- 2
- H(igh)
- 1
-
- L(ow)
- R(eject)
Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium
AA RR AR RA
H 5,5 0,0 5,5 0,0 L
8,2 0,0 0,0 8,2
SPNE (L,AA) (H,AR) and (L,RA) involve
incredible threats.
22Subgame Perfection
5,5 0,0 8,2 1,9
AA RR AR RA
H 5,5 0,0 5,5 0,0 L
8,2 1,9 1,9 8,2
23Subgame Perfection
5,5 0,0
AA RR AR RA
H 5,5 0,0 5,5 0,0 L
8,2 1,9 1,9 8,2
1,9
SPNE (H,AR)
24Alternating Offer Bargaining Game
- Two players are to divide a sum of money (S) is a
finite number (N) of alternating offers. Player
1 (Buyer) goes first Player 2 (Seller) can
either accept or counter offer, and so on. The
game continues until an offer is accepted or N is
reached. If no offer is accepted, the players
each get zero. - A. Rubinstein, 1982
25Alternating Offer Bargaining Game
1 (a,S-a)
2 (b,S-b) 1 (c,S-c)
(0,0)
S 5.00 N 3
26Alternating Offer Bargaining Game
1 (a,S-a)
2 (b,S-b) 1 (4.99, 0.01)
(0,0)
S 5.00 N 3
27Alternating Offer Bargaining Game
- 1
-
- (4.99,0.01) 2
- (b,S-b) 1
- (4.99,0.01) (0,0)
-
S 5.00 N 3 SPNE (4.99,0.01)
The game reduces to an Ultimatum Game
28Shrinking Pie Game
-
- Now consider what happens if the sum to be
divided decreases with each round of the game
(e.g., transaction costs, risk aversion,
impatience). - Let S Sum of money to be divided
- N Number of rounds
- d Discount parameter
-
29Shrinking Pie Game
1 (3.74,1.26) 2
(1.25, 1.25) 1
(1.24,0.01) (0,0) 1
S 5.00 N 3 d 0.5
30Shrinking Pie Game
1 (3.13,1.87) 2
(0.64,1.86) 1
(0.63,0.62) 2 (0.01, 0.61)
(0,0) 1
S 5.00 N 4 d 0.5
31Shrinking Pie Game
for d ½
N 1 (4.99, 0.01) 2 (2.50, 2.50)
3 (3.74, 1.26) 4 (3.13,
1.87) 5 (3.43, 1.57) This series converges
to (S/(1d), S S/(1d)) (3.33,
1.67) This pair S/(1 d),S-S/(1 d) are the
payoffs of the unique SPNE.
P2 5 1.67 0
2
4
5
3
1
0 3.33 5 P1
32Shrinking Pie Game
- Optimal Offer (O) expressed as a share of the
total sum to be divided S-S/(1d)/S -
- O d/(1d)
- SPNE 1- d /(1 d), d /(1 d)
- Thus both d1 and d0 are special cases of
Rubinsteins model - When d1 (no bargaining costs), O 1/2
- When d0, game collapses to the ultimatum version
and O 0 (e)
33Shrinking Pie Game
34Bargaining Games
- Bargaining games are fundamental to understanding
the price determination mechanism in small
markets. - The central issue in all bargaining games is
credibility the strategic use of threats,
bluffs, and promises. - When information is asymmetric, profitable
exchanges may be left on the table. - In such cases, there is an incentive to make
oneself credible (e.g., appraisals audits
reputable agents brand names lemons laws
corporate governance).
35Bargaining Negotiation
- In real-world negotiations, players often have
incomplete, asymmetric, or private information,
e.g., only the seller of a used car knows its
true quality and hence its true value. - Making agreements is made all the more difficult
when trust and good faith are lacking and there
is no legal recourse for breach of contract
(Schelling, 1960 20). - Rubinsteins solution If a bargaining game is
played in a series of alternating offers, and if
a speedy resolution is preferred to one that
takes longer, then there is only one offer that a
rational player should make, and the only
rational thing for the opponent to do is accept
it immediately!