Title: EUTHANASIA
1EUTHANASIA
Edvard Munch, Death in the Sickroom,1895
2Doctors Must Not Kill
Edmund D. Pellegrino
3SUFFERING AND EUTHANASIA
- Pellegrino is a physician and writes about
euthanasia from that perspective. - His position is that, while doctors have a duty
to alleviate suffering, they cannot knowingly and
willingly involve themselves in the death of a
patient. - And this is the case even if the patient requests
it. Thus his view is opposed to voluntary active
euthanasia as well as to nonvoluntary and
involuntary euthanasia.
4PELLEGRINOS POINTS
- Although Pellegrino says that No one can
reasonably oppose a good death, he is opposed
to euthanasia even out of compassion for the
following reasons. - 1. Moral arguments for euthanasia are not
convincing. - 2. Euthanasia distorts the healing relationship
between doctor and patient. - 3. Euthanasia is likely to be abused by society,
and so can have terrible social consequences.
5ARGUMENTS FOR EUTHANASIA I
- Those who argue for euthanasia typically say the
following basic things - 1. Euthanasia eliminates suffering, suffering is
evil, and so euthanasia is good because it
eliminates suffering. - 2. People who are suffering from a terminal
illness have the right to choose not to suffer.
And if euthanasia is the only means of ending
suffering, then those suffering have the right to
end their suffering by ending their lives. This
is the principle of autonomy. - 3. Terminally ill patients cannot end their own
lives, but depend on doctors who know best how to
do it. Here a doctor acts as an agent on behalf
of the patient.
6ARGUMENTS FOR EUTHANASIA II
- 4. Because part of a doctors moral duty is to
end suffering, she has a moral duty to assist a
patient in obtaining a good death when that is
the patients desire. - 5. There is no moral difference between a
doctors killing a patient and letting her
die. Rachels. - 6. Abuses of euthanasia can be controlled by
legislation. - 7. No physician who is morally opposed need
participate.
7EUTHANASIA AND RELIGION I
- Two arguments against euthanasia from the
Judeo-Christian tradition are - 1. Humans are given the gift of life and have no
right to interfere with this gift. Plato. - 2. Even human suffering can have meaning, that
is, it can be meaningful in a positive way. - Although Pellegrino thinks that these arguments
are not lightly dismissed, he says that he will
not try to make his argument against euthanasia
by appeal to these things. And this is because
Even without recourse to religious beliefs,
active euthanasia is morally untenable.
8EUTHANASIA AND RELIGION II
- Pellegrino does say, however, that these are
beliefs which are deeply rooted in our culture,
and because they are so deeply rooted, he thinks
that the burden of proof is on the person who
argues against these beliefs in arguing for
euthanasia. - The idea here then is that someone who wants to
argue against tradition and common opinion must
give good reasons for doing so, and he thinks
that the arguments offered in favor of euthanasia
are not proof that it is morally acceptable.
9KILLING AND LETTING DIE I
- Pellegrino will first look at the idea made by
some advocates of euthanasia that there is no
moral difference between killing a patient and
letting him die by deliberate withdrawal or
withholding of life support or lifesaving
treatment. - The moral parity of killing and letting die can
be understood to have two aspects whether it
concerns a moral good or a moral evil. - That you are as guilty of a wrongdoing if you let
someone die whose death you could have prevented
as you are in killing her is to see killing and
letting die as equally morally evil. - On the other hand, if letting someone die -
passive euthanasia - is a moral good because it
ends suffering, then why is not killing someone
to end suffering - active euthanasia - also not a
moral good? Arent these equally morally good?
10KILLING AND LETTING DIE II
- For Pellegrino, the difference is that in active
euthanasia the doctor is the direct cause of the
patients death, whereas in letting the patient
die or passive euthanasia the illness is the
cause of death. - Therefore he does not see them as morally
equivalent because in the first case the doctor
does something and in the second instance he does
nothing.
11KILLING AND LETTING DIE III
- James Rachels response is that it is not true
that in passive euthanasia the doctor does
nothing. - After all, he lets the patient die, and letting
someone die can be subject to moral evaluation -
good or bad - as we have seen. - Rachels says that if passive euthanasia is seen
as medically acceptable, then that is because it
is seen that death is an equal or lesser evil
than suffering. - And if passive euthanasia is acceptable to
eliminate the equal or greater evil of suffering,
then, for Rachels, so is active euthanasia.
12EUTHANASIA AND AUTONOMY I
- Pellegrino next looks at the argument for
euthanasia based on the patients right of
autonomy. - The right of autonomy is the right to
self-determination - to make free choices for
yourself. - This could include a terminally ill patients
right to choose to die to end her pain and
suffering. The idea is whose life is it anyway?
13EUTHANASIA AND AUTONOMY II
- Pellegrinos problem with the right to autonomy
is that, in exercising her right to die, a person
is using her freedom to give up her freedom. - Thus, in the name of autonomy the patient decides
to end the life which makes autonomy possible. - When you give up your life you give up
everything, including your freedom and control
over a whole set of options, all of which cannot
be foreseen and many of which would be of
importance if life - the basis of freedom - had
not been forgone.
14EUTHANASIA AND AUTONOMY III
- However, a proponent of euthanasia might argue
that a dying patients using freedom to eliminate
freedom is not a contradiction but is simply a
use to which freedom is practically put, given
his illness and suffering. - And it might be further argued that, if the
medical condition of the patient is such as to
restrict or eliminate all future meaningful
options, then the most meaningful thing for
freedom to do is to eliminate the life which
supports the suffering.
15EUTHANASIA AND AUTONOMY IV
- Pellegrino also says in regard to autonomy that,
if the patient chooses death because of
unbearable suffering, then the choice of death is
really not free. - But again, a euthanasia advocate might argue
that, even if this is the case, and the patient
is powerless to act otherwise, euthanasia can yet
be seen as the only option to eliminate the evil
of suffering. - And here autonomy could yet be relevant in the
patients having made the free choice to opt for
euthanasia if such a medical condition as he now
experiences were ever to arise. The patient
would have simply exercised his freedom earlier
in his life by planning for such an event through
a will.
16THE BURDEN OF TERMINAL ILLNESS
- Pellegrino says that terminally ill patients
often see themselves as social, economic, and
emotional burdens to others. - And in their debilitated condition they may be
susceptible to subtle suggestion - such a
doctors agreeing that they are a burden. They
could then decide to choose euthanasia. - For Pellegrino, euthanasia is too often an act
of desperation - an act that could be avoided if
pain is properly managed. - But what about the cases where pain cannot be
properly managed? And what about the medical
conditions which are so terrible that modern
medicine can do nothing for them?
17KINDNESS AND COMPASSION I
- Advocates of euthanasia will cite kindness and
compassion as reasons for ending through death
the terrible suffering of a terminally ill
patient. - Pellegrino recognizes that compassion is part of
medicine, since every doctor desires to make his
patients well, and he recognizes that even those
who see meaning in suffering would prefer that
someone not suffer. - Do not compassion and mercy then override all
other considerations?
18KINDNESS AND COMPASSION II
- The answer to this, for Pellegrino, is that
compassion can concern removing the dying
patients pain without resorting to euthanasia. - By removing a patients pain, he can experience a
good death - the one which nature intended. - Pellegrino The aim of medicine should be to
facilitate a death that is as pain-free as
possible but that is also a human experience.
19DYING, EXPERIENCE, AND UNDERSTANDING
- Euthanasia of humans is morally unacceptable for
Pellegrino because they have the capacity to
understand the experience of dying, and possibly
benefit from it, whereas such understanding is
not possible for other lower life forms such as
our pets. - The experience of dying is important for
Pellegrino since humans can grow morally even
with negative experiences. - Notice that dying can be treated as an experience
for a person who is conscious while his life is
ending, whereas death, at least from the
perspective of life on earth, is the end of all
experience. - See the first two full paragraphs on page 176
and compare with the questions for Pellegrino on
the handout.
20THE MOTIVATION FOR EUTHANASIA
- Pellegrino says that The motivation for
euthanasia arises principally from two worries
fear of intolerable pain, suffering, and anguish,
and fear of becoming a victim of overzealous
physicians and dehumanizing medical
technologies. - Although Pellegrino recognizes that both of these
are legitimate worries, he thinks that each can
be handled without resort to euthanasia through
improved measures for relief of pain and
anxiety which physicians have a moral obligation
to use, and through hospice programs and
palliative care.
21MAKING DYING POSITIVE
- With the help of such programs, dying, according
to Pellegrino, can be a communal experience, in
which the dying person contributes something
positive to those around her as well as to her
own growth as a person. - And Pellegrino thinks that the physicians
obligation to act beneficently and to show
respect for the patients dignity is better
served by these measures than by killing the
patient.
22MAJORITY OPINION
- Pellegrino points out, correctly, that that the
majority of people believe something does not
make it morally correct or incorrect. Thus
comment consent does not guarantee the truth of
whatever it is about which the majority agree,
and philosophical argument with relevant evidence
must be established to determine the truth of
something, not popular opinion. - If the majority is in favor of euthanasia that
does not in itself show that euthanasia is
morally correct, and if most people are against,
that majority opinion also does not show that
euthanasia is immoral.
23DISTORTING THE HEALING RELATIONSHIP I
- According to Pellegrino, euthanasia distorts the
healing relationship between doctor and patient. - A doctors aim is to heal her patient if
possible, and if that is not possible, then the
physician has an obligation to treat the
patients pain to the best of her ability. - Notice that he says this in spite of his respect
for the moral value of suffering. Is this a
problem for his view? - Pellegrino notes that medicine is grounded in
trust, and he thinks that euthanasia could
destroy that trust.
24DISTORTING THE HEALING RELATIONSHIP II
- Euthanasia could destroy the patients trust of
his doctor since, if euthanasia were legal, then
some doctors might opt for killing their patients
rather than healing them. - The doctor who thinks his patient is better off
dead might try to convince his patient to end his
life rather than waiting to die naturally. - This is the slippery slope idea that if we
legalize euthanasia then abuses of the system
would inevitably occur, human nature being what
it is.
25A SLIPPERY SLOPE I
- As Mary Warnock puts it The slippery slope is
the name of an argument based on a certain view
of human nature, not on logic, and commonly used
in nonphilosophical discussions of moral issues.
- Warnock The reasoning is that, though a
practice may be unobjectionable in one type of
case, if it is once permitted, its use will
inevitably be extended to other more morally
dubious cases. - Warnock The inevitability here supposed is not
logical inevitability, but is thought to result
from peoples always wanting more than they
have. - Warnock In fact, legislation or other forms of
regulation can usually control an undesirable
slide down the slippery slope.
26A SLIPPERY SLOPE II
- According to the slippery slope argument then,
although a certain kind of practice may be
acceptable in one kind of case, once it is
permitted, it will be extended to cases where it
ought not to be used. - The idea is that we slide down the slope from a
good thing to a bad thing. - In this instance, if euthanasia were okay for one
kind of terminally suffering patient, it would be
used in cases where it should not - where it is
not really the wish of the patient to be put to
death.
27A SLIPPERY SLOPE III
- A slippery slope argument such as this depends on
seeing human beings as basically morally
irresponsible, unable to make reasonable
judgements, susceptible to external influence, or
all of these. - The common rebuttal to such slippery slope
arguments is that potential bad cases can be
prevented through proper legislation. - Advocates of euthanasia, such as James Rachels,
recognize the possibility of system abuses, but
are willing to rely on legislation and the good
judgement of the medical community to correct
them.
28A SLIPPERY SLOPE IV
- The idea then is that the remedy for abuses is
either to enforce legislation so that they dont
occur, and if the violations become too excessive
you simply repeal the law which legalized
euthanasia. - But Pellegrino might respond that this is not a
risk worth taking. In fact he says that laws
will not prevent abuses, and thinks that abuse
is inevitable. - On the other hand, James Rachels is a philosopher
who thinks that the benefits of euthanasia will
outweigh any abuses that may occur.
29A SLIPPERY SLOPE V
- Whatever the case about likely abuses of
euthanasia though, Pellegrinos view is that the
doctor has an obligation to alleviate or
eliminate suffering so that the patient could
experience a good death, and she must reject
euthanasia since that eliminates the prospect of
a good death and distorts the healing
relationship between doctor and patient.
30VOLUNTARY ACTIVE EUTHANASIA
Dan W. Brock
31V.A.E. AND P.A.S. I
- Brock thinks that both euthanasia and physician
assisted suicide are morally permissible. - Remember that voluntary active euthanasia
(v.a.e.) is when the doctor intentionally kills a
terminally ill patient with the patients
consent. - In physician assisted suicide (p.a.s.) the
patient kills herself with the assistance of the
doctor, the doctor does not act directly to kill
the patient.
32V.A.E. AND P.A.S. II
- In physician assisted suicide, the patient is the
one who directly ends her own life. - An example of physician assisted suicide is when
a patient ends her life with a drug that the
doctor prescribes. - In voluntary active euthanasia, the doctor
directly kills the patient at the request of the
patient. - In voluntary active euthanasia the doctor or a
medical assistant acting on the doctors orders
administers the drug to the patient.
33V.A.E. AND P.A.S. III
- In both euthanasia and assisted suicide the
choice of death rests fully with the patient.
In each case the patient acts last in the sense
of retaining the right to change his or her
mind. - And in each case the doctor is directly involved,
and plays an active and necessary causal role. - In fact, for Brock, the only difference that
need exist between the two v.a.e. and p.a.s. is
the person who actually administers the dose -
the physician or the patient. - Brock wants to know then how there could be a
substantial moral difference between the two
v.a.e. and p.a.s. based only on this small
difference in the part played by the physician in
the causal process resulting in death?
34V.A.E. AND P.A.S. IV
- Thus Brock wonders why some people think that
there is a major moral difference here between
euthanasia and assisted suicide since the doctor
is necessarily and actively involved in both
cases. - Some might respond that the moral difference is
clear since in euthanasia the doctor kills the
patient, while in p.a.s the patient kills the
patient, with, of course, the doctors
assistance. - But Brock says that this is misleading at best.
- Its misleading because in p.a.s the doctor and
patient together kill the patient. And they do
it together since the patient cannot kill himself
without the doctors help.
35V.A.E. AND P.A.S. V
- Brock points out that, if a doctor gave a patient
a lethal dose of medication with full knowledge
that the patient will use it to kill someone
else, we would hold the doctor responsible for a
wrongful death. - So if the doctor gives his patient a lethal drug
with the full knowledge that he will use it to
kill himself then he is also responsible for the
death of the patient. - And Brock says that if it is really the case that
there is no significant difference between
euthanasia and p.a.s, then why should people be
in favor of one and not the other? - Accordingly, a law which permitted p.a.s. on
moral grounds ought also to permit euthanasia on
moral grounds.
36THE CENTRAL ARGUMENT FOR EUTHANASIA
- Brock will focus on voluntary active euthanasia
only, which I will call euthanasia for short. - The argument for euthanasia comes typically from
two fundamental moral points regarding persons - 1. The right to self-determination the right of
autonomy. - 2. The right to well-being.
- A persons right to self-determination is his or
her right to make free choices about his or her
life to the extent that such choices do not
interfere with someone elses right to
self-determination. - And a persons right to well-being includes the
right not to suffer, physically, psychologically,
or both.
37SELF-DETERMINATION I
- Self-determination in regard to euthanasia means
that a terminally ill patient whose suffering
only death will end has the right to decide about
her own life. - Thus a person suffering from a terminal illness
should be free to make up her own mind about her
future in relation to that illness. - We take self-determination to be a good thing,
and we take suffering to be a bad thing.
38SELF-DETERMINATION II
- Brock says that By self-determination as it
bears on euthanasia, I mean peoples interest in
making important decisions about their lives for
themselves according to their values or
conceptions of a good life, and in being left
free to act on those decisions. - For Brock, self-determination is both valuable
and a central aspect of human dignity. - Basing euthanasia on the right of
self-determination means that people must have
the ability to decide for themselves.
39SELF-DETERMINATION III
- Basing euthanasia on the right of
self-determination also presupposes some minimum
of decision-making capacities or competence . . .
and cannot justifiably be administered, for
example, in cases of serious dementia or
treatable clinical depression. - Those in favor of euthanasia would say the right
to self-determination extends to a persons right
to decide about her own death. - For them, we ought to have the right to
discontinue our lives when faced with terminal
suffering.
40SELF-DETERMINATION IV
- People have a natural fear of suffering and a
fear of losing dignity due to illness, and
euthanasia would give them an option then to
avoid both. - However, Brock says that everyone has to decide
for himself, and that people and life are
complicated enough that there is no single
objectively correct answer for everyone about
how much suffering you can take, and about when
loss of dignity will occur. - Accordingly, where euthanasia may be proper for
some it may not be for others, and this is why
the emphasis is on euthanasia being voluntary. - Because people are so different, and the right of
self-determination is so important, it is
especially important that terminally ill people
are able to control the manner, circumstances,
and timing of their dying and death.
41WELL-BEING
- We think that life is good and death is evil,
but, more particularly, we think that a healthy
life is good and that suffering is an evil. And
we think that everyone has a right to well-being
- that no one should suffer who does not have to. - Proponents of euthanasia say that, since everyone
has a right to well-being, and a right to
self-determination, when someone loses her
feeling of well-being when life becomes an
unbearable burden and when a life of suffering
is worse than no further life at all, then a
person has the right to end her suffering through
death. - Again, Brock says that there is no objective
standard about what constitutes an unbearable
life, but only the competent patients judgement
of whether continued life is no longer a
benefit.
42PHYSICIANS AND EUTHANASIA
- Brock says that a persons right to
self-determination cannot be used to compel
doctors to practice euthanasia or p.a.s. - If a doctor objects to either on moral grounds,
then she cannot be forced to participate in
bringing about the death of the patient. - That is, the doctors right of self-determination
also has to be respected. - Even if euthanasia becomes legal, a doctor who
objects to it need not be involved, and his role
can be taken by another willing physician.
43ARGUMENTS AGAINST EUTHANASIA
- Two main arguments against euthanasia cited by
Brock are - 1. The deliberate killing of an innocent person
is always ethically wrong. - 2. Perhaps euthanasia is morally acceptable in
certain cases, but it ought not to be legally
permitted since it will be abused, and so the bad
consequences will outweigh the good. Slippery
slope.
44DELIBERATE KILLING OF AN INNOCENT PERSON I
- Opponents of euthanasia say that euthanasia is
the deliberate killing of an innocent person, and
they object to euthanasia because they think that
this deliberate killing is always immoral. - Brock says that they are right that euthanasia is
the deliberate killing of an innocent person. - The killing is done deliberately at the patients
request to end her suffering, and the person is
not guilty of any crime or wrongdoing in virtue
of being terminally ill and suffering.
45DELIBERATE KILLING OF AN INNOCENT PERSON II
- The question of the morality of euthanasia then
concerns whether or not the deliberate killing of
an innocent person is always wrong. - If it is then euthanasia is immoral.
- If it is not then euthanasia may be permissible,
at least in some cases.
46KILLING AND ALLOWING TO DIE I
- While some think that voluntary active euthanasia
is wrong, they do not think that deliberately
allowing a person to die, or passive euthanasia
is wrong. - Thus, allowing someone to die by deliberately
withholding life sustaining treatment is thought
to be morally acceptable and different from
euthanasia, because in allowing to die you are
allowing the disease to kill the patient and so
the doctor is not killing the patient. - But Brock says that this view is confused and
mistaken. - See Brocks example on pp. 188-189.
47KILLING AND ALLOWING TO DIE II
- The idea here is that the same physical actions
are performed by the greedy son as by the
compassionate physician. If the sons action is
killing why is not the doctors? - Brock understands that there is a difference of
intention here, and that both the intention and
other considerations make us think that there is
a moral difference here. - For instance, the doctor acts with the patients
consent, has a good motive - ending suffering -
and is performing a social role for which he is
legally authorized. - On the other hand, the son acts without the
patients consent, with a bad motive - greed -
and is not performing a social role for which he
is legally authorized.
48KILLING AND ALLOWING TO DIE III
- Brocks point is that these things show that what
the doctor did to the patient and what the son
did are morally different - one is moral and the
other is immoral - but what the example does not
show is that the son killed the patient while
the doctor allowed her to die. - For Brock, even if we suppose that killing is
worse than allowing to die, and that withdrawing
life support is allowing to die, while euthanasia
is killing, it need not follow that euthanasia is
morally wrong.
49WHY IS KILLING WRONG I?
- Brock asks just what is it that makes the
deliberate killing of an innocent person wrong? - He thinks that a good answer is that killing
deprives a person of the possibility of having a
valuable future. Don Marquis uses this as an
argument against abortion. - Every innocent person has a right to the
possibility of a valuable future, and as killing
deprives a person of this right, killing is
wrong. Another way to put this is people have a
moral right not to be killed.
50WHY IS KILLING WRONG II?
- People are a kind of being which can have a sense
of the future, can plan for the future, and can
see life in the future as something which they
value and can anticipate taking pleasure in. - But making plans for and valuing the future
presupposes the continued existence of the life
whose plans and valuing they are. - If that life is ended so is the possibility of
realizing those plans, and so ends the
possibility of value to be realized in the
future.
51WHY IS KILLING WRONG III?
- Killing frustrates a persons plans and ends her
dreams of a good future. - Death is an evil because in death you give up
everything. - Thus an act which deliberately causes a persons
death is seen as an evil because it is the cause
of an evil. - And so people have a moral right not to be
killed, not to have the possibility of a good
future interfered with.
52WRONGFUL KILLING AND EUTHANASIA I
- Whereas deliberate killing of an innocent person
may seem to rule out euthanasia as immoral, it
does not necessarily. This is because what makes
deliberate killing wrong is its depriving a
person of a valuable future. - If the person has no prospect of a good future,
then killing her at her request need not be
morally wrong. - A terminally ill patients future may be worse
than no future at all because of the promise of
suffering which will characterize that future.
53WRONGFUL KILLING AND EUTHANASIA II
- As much as we think that people have a right to a
good future, we also think that everyone has a
right to well-being and hence a right not to
suffer. - For Brock, a persons right not to be killed can
be waived by that person. Thus a person can give
up her right not to be killed in favor of her
right not to suffer. - Euthanasia then can be seen as morally acceptable
since the terminally ill patient chooses to give
up her right not to be killed. She deliberately
chooses euthanasia since she sees death as the
only means of ending her suffering.
54RELIGION AND EUTHANASIA
- Brock says that many people who feel squeamish
about euthanasia, even when they agree about the
evil of suffering, are uncomfortable about
euthanasia due to religious reasons. - However, for Brock, the question of euthanasia
concerns the moral correctness or incorrectness
of adopting euthanasia as public policy - of
making it legal or not - and he thinks that such
public policy cannot be grounded on religion in a
free society. - We live in a pluralistic society which consists
of many people who accept and others who reject
religion, and we have to recognize the strong
commitment we have to freedom of belief.
55EUTHANASIA AND PUBLIC POLICY
- Brock recognizes that it is one thing to talk of
the morality of euthanasia in individual cases
where it is requested by a dying patient, and it
is another to talk of legalizing euthanasia. - And here it is pertinent to recognize that, in
addition to saying that the deliberate killing of
an innocent person is always wrong, the second
main argument against euthanasia is that the bad
consequences of making it legal would outweigh
the good consequences. - Brock notes that there are two kinds of
disagreement about this second argument
empirical or factual disagreement about what the
consequences would be and moral disagreements
about the relative importance of different
effects of legalizing euthanasia.
56POTENTIAL GOOD CONSEQUENCES OF PERMITTING
EUTHANASIA
57THE RIGHT TO SELF DETERMINATION
- A first good consequence of permitting euthanasia
would enable us to respect the right to
self-determination of competent patients who ask
for it. - But Brock notes that the opponent of euthanasia
could ask here whether we need to respect the
right to self-determination in every case, or
might some other ethical principles override it? - If the opponent says that the deliberate killing
of another person is always wrong, then this
moral law could override the right to
self-determination. - On the other hand, if a competent person can
waive his right to be killed in favor of his
right not to suffer, then the right not to suffer
coupled with the right of self-determination
could override morally the principle which says
that the deliberate killing of an innocent person
is always wrong.
58DESIRE FOR EUTHANASIA AS AN OPTION
- When we ask about instituting euthanasia as
public policy we would have to ask how many
people are likely to want it, and the answer to
this will depend to the extent to which the
illness is treatable, or the extent to which the
suffering is manageable. That is, the question
will concern is euthanasia the only option? - Brock thinks that the number of people in the U.
S. who would want euthanasia is probably
relatively small, but thinks that it should be
available for those who would choose it.
59SATISFYING THE MAJORITY
- A second good consequence of permitting
euthanasia would be giving the majority what they
want. This is because polls show that most
Americans want the option of euthanasia even if
they would not choose it for themselves when the
time came. - Most people think that a person has the right to
choose euthanasia, and making euthanasia legal
would reinforce the perception of this moral
right. - Thus it would be reassuring to people to know
that euthanasia is an option, should they need
it. - Brock says that this would make euthanasia a
kind of insurance policy against the threat of
interminable suffering.
60RELEASE FROM SUFFERING AND AGONY I
- The third good consequence of legalizing
euthanasia, according to Brock, is its
elimination of horrible suffering when nothing
else will take it away, and he suggests that the
sad fact is that many patients suffer needlessly
for physicians fear of hastening the patients
death. This would not be a fear if euthanasia
were legal. - The argument for euthanasia as the only means of
eliminating pain or other kind of terrible
suffering is the argument from compassion or
mercy.
61RELEASE FROM SUFFERING AND AGONY II
- Brock says that in talk of pain we must
distinguish between pain that is treatable by
medication and pain that is not, or pain which
only death will remove. - Brock recognizes that the argument for euthanasia
based on the elimination of pain loses much of
its force if the pain can be managed without
death - even at the cost of making the patient
comatose. (Presumably the patient could not die
Pellegrinos good death if comatose) - Thus the argument from compassion can be met if
the suffering can be ended without killing the
patient. Here then the argument in favor of
euthanasia from suffering would depend on there
being kinds of suffering which only death can
eliminate.
62RELEASE FROM SUFFERING AND AGONY III
- Brock mentions psychological pain or suffering in
addition to physical pain, and notes that the
knowledge of how to treat this is much more
limited. - Thus an argument from compassion for the
suffering patient can be made for euthanasia
where the psychological suffering is unbearable,
and death is the only means of eradicating this
suffering. - And if this kind of suffering is less treatable,
then patients suffering psychological pain might
be more in need of euthanasia than others.
63HUMANITY
- A final good consequence of euthanasia is that
ending life quickly and painlessly is more humane
than a prolonged death which involves pain and
suffering. - Brock asks, dont we think that people who die
quickly or in their sleep are lucky? - A psychological factor here is that we care how
people remember us, and we dont want to be
remembered as sick and suffering. Thus a
debilitating disease can rob us of our dignity. - For the patient who wants it, euthanasia can be a
quick and peaceful end to life which will give
some dignity and allow her loved ones to remember
her as she was in better times.
64POTENTIAL BAD CONSEQUENCES OF PERMITTING
EUTHANASIA
65DOCTORS MUST NOT KILL
- A first potential bad consequence of legalizing
euthanasia is that permitting doctors to perform
euthanasia is incompatible with their
professional and moral commitment to heal and
care for patients rather than to kill them.
(Pellegrino.) - Permitting doctors to practice euthanasia would
remove the trust between doctor and patient and
distort the trust which the patient has in the
doctor. (Pellegrino.) - Patients then could no longer be sure that their
doctor was not giving them a drug which will kill
them rather than reduce pain, and the patients
trust of his doctor would be eroded.
66BROCKS RESPONSE I
- Brock wonders how legitimate this concern is.
How can a patient have a fear about the nature of
a certain drug when she has asked for the doctor
to perform euthanasia? - If euthanasia is restricted to cases which are
strictly voluntary, then how can a patient who
has not requested euthanasia fear anything? - In fact, Brock thinks that a patients trust of
her physician could actually be increased. - Trust would be increased if euthanasia were legal
since then a suffering patient would know that
she could request it if needed, and could trust
that her doctor would honor her request.
67BROCKS RESPONSE II
- Brock says recall what the two main arguments for
euthanasia are - 1. The patients right of self-determination.
- 2. The patients right to well-being.
- Brock says that doctors who respected these two
basic rights would not be changing the moral
character of medicine. Rather, respect for these
two values will support doctors who practice
euthanasia when requested by competent patients. - For Brock, what is morally suspect is practice of
medicine without regard for these two basic
patient rights.
68THE VALUE OF HEALTH CARE
- A second bad consequence of euthanasia is that it
could weaken societys commitment to provide the
best care for patients that is possible. - Because health care is expensive, some might see
euthanasia as a cheaper alternative to costly
care, and we might use abuse euthanasia when
other more costly care is available.
69BROCKS RESPONSE
- There is little evidence that patients right to
refuse treatment - passive euthanasia - has
caused patients to receive worse care. And if
the possibility of passive euthanasia has not
caused the quality of health care to go down,
then why should active euthanasia? - In addition, Brock thinks that very few people
would choose euthanasia even if it were
available. - Thus permitting euthanasia should not interfere
with the high quality of health care that we have
without euthanasia.
70PRESSURE TO CHOOSE EUTHANASIA
- A third bad consequence of euthanasia mentioned
by Brock is due to David Velleman, who says that
making a new option or choice available to
people can sometimes make them worse off. - The choice of euthanasia could mean that some
people who do not really want to choose
euthanasia will be led to choose it by others who
see it as the best option for them. - If euthanasia were not legal, then this option
would not exist and the dying patient would not
have to consider it. However, if euthanasia is
an option, then the choice of it can make the
person who does not want it worse off if she
thinks that she ought to choose it because others
want her to choose it. - Velleman does not see this as an argument to
outlaw euthanasia, but only to restrict it to
those who genuinely want it for unmistakable and
overpowering reasons.
71BROCKS RESPONSE I
- Brock wonders whether it is true that people
would be made worse off by having the choice of
euthanasia. He says that polls show that most
people want the option and so think that they
would be made better off and not worse off by
having the choice. - He also maintains that, if giving people the
option of euthanasia is a possibly harmful choice
for them, then so could be the option of passive
euthanasia - refusing life-sustaining treatment. - However, there is no evidence that this has been
a bad option for people.
72BROCKS RESPONSE II
- Also, because the conditions for wanting or not
wanting euthanasia are so wide and varied, it is
not advisable to restrict it in the way that
Velleman suggests. - It is not advisable since then euthanasia could
be denied to people who really want it. - Brock To permit it only in cases where
virtually everyone would want it would be to deny
it to most who would want it.
73THE PROHIBITION OF HOMICIDE
- The American College Dictionary defines homicide
as the killing of one human being by another,
and Brock says that This prohibition is so
fundamental to civilized society, it is argued,
that we should do nothing that erodes it. - Because legalizing euthanasia could be seen to
erode the general prohibition of homicide, it
could be taken to be a fourth possible bad
consequence of euthanasia.
74BROCKS RESPONSE I
- Because, according to Brock, stopping life
support is killing the patient in most cases,
then permitting this kind of killing could
already be seen to have weakened the prohibition
of homicide. - However, Brock recognizes that most people, as
well as the courts, have not seen passive
euthanasia as killing, and so it would not really
figure in here as a weakening of the prohibition
of homicide. - Passive euthanasia has been thought acceptable on
grounds of the rights to privacy and
self-determination and has not been looked at as
an exception to homicide laws, but Brock says
that the same fundamental right of
self-determination applies to euthanasia. - After all, in euthanasia the patient consents to
his killing, whereas in other cases of homicide
he does not.
75BROCKS RESPONSE II
- Both murder and euthanasia are kinds of homicide,
kinds of deliberate killing of one innocent human
by another. However, they differ in that, in
euthanasia but not in murder, the person who is
killed gives his consent to be killed. Thus
there is self-determination in euthanasia but not
in murder. - And Brock says that If procedures can be
designed that clearly establish the voluntariness
of the persons request of euthanasia, it would
under those procedures represent a carefully
circumscribed qualification on the legal
prohibition of homicide.
76ABUSE OF A GOOD THING
- The final potential bad consequence of permitting
euthanasia even for those cases in which it is
unequivocally voluntary and the patient finds his
or her condition unbearable, is that euthanasia
would inevitably lead to abuse in being performed
in cases where patient consent is not given and
may not be desired. - This is the slippery slope argument which says
that people will abuse a good thing, and because
active voluntary euthanasia will lead to
nonvoluntary and even involuntary euthanasia, it
should not be permitted in any case.
77BROCKS RESPONSE I
- Although Brock thinks that this objection is the
most serious objection to euthanasia, he also
thinks that the strength of such slippery slope
arguments can be doubted and are hard to
evaluate. - When all else fails, the conservative objector to
euthanasia simply says that it will end up being
applied to people who have not asked for it, and
because it will end up being so applied it should
not be legalized in the first place.
78BROCKS RESPONSE II
- For Brock, whereas one must admit that abuses of
euthanasia are possible, that is not enough to
prohibit it if it is otherwise morally justified.
- What has to be assessed is how likely the abuses
are. - Euthanasia would be abused if the conditions for
granting euthanasia to a patient are not
satisfied. - Most specifically, if the patients consent has
not been given, or if her consent has been forced
through persuasion.
79BROCKS RESPONSE III
- However, unless opponents of euthanasia can
provide good data to support their view of likely
abuses there is little reason to consider them. - The extent to which abuses are likely depend on
the rules and procedures which are put in place
to prevent such abuses from occurring. - See Brocks four guidelines to avoid abuses on
p. 196. - The idea of the safeguards is to ensure that it
is the patient who makes the choice, and the
choice is informed by accurate medical
information.
80BROCKS RESPONSE IV
- At the same time that we want rules which will
help to avoid abuses, we do not want to make them
so strict that voluntary active euthanasia will
be impossible to get for someone who wants it. - Life is such that some abuses are likely to
occur, but abuses can be minimized by ongoing
reviews of cases of euthanasia which have
occurred.
81NONVOLUNTARY ACTIVE EUTHANASIA I
- Brock thinks that a system can be constructed
where it will make involuntary active euthanasia
rare or unlikely, but he says that legalization
of voluntary active euthanasia could very well
make nonvoluntary euthanasia likely. - Thus, where we cannot get a patients consent,
due to coma for instance, we may be tempted to
legalize nonvoluntary euthanasia. - Here the right to choose euthanasia would be
given to a person who can act on behalf of the
patient - such as a family member. And the
person who chooses for the incompetent patient is
supposed to choose as the patient would have
chosen if able to do so.
82NONVOLUNTARY ACTIVE EUTHANASIA II
- The reasoning behind allowing nonvoluntary
euthanasia is that it seems unreasonable to
continue life-sustaining treatment that the
patient would not have wanted just because the
patient now lacks the capacity to tell us that. - As it is now, patient surrogates will often
refuse life-sustaining treatment when they know
that is what the patient would have wanted, and
such a wish could extend from voluntary to
nonvoluntary euthanasia. - As Brock says, why continue to force unwanted
life on patients just because they have now lost
the capacity to request euthanasia from us?
83NONVOLUNTARY ACTIVE EUTHANASIA III
- Of course, the courts can still restrict
euthanasia to voluntary only, as they have in
Holland. - Nonvoluntary euthanasia can be fairly clear cut
where a patient has made her wishes known ahead
of time, but, for those who have not, Brock says
that the potential for abuse is clearly there if
nonvoluntary euthanasia is legalized. - Thus for nonvoluntary euthanasia the important
thing for avoiding abuse is to make sure that
rules are in place for surrogates acting on
behalf of incapacitated patients.
84NONVOLUNTARY ACTIVE EUTHANASIA IV
- Rules which are in place which authorize others
to act on the patients behalf when the patient
herself has given such authorization can protect
us from sliding down the slippery slope from
voluntary to nonvoluntary euthanasia. - Brock ends by saying that the issues concerning
euthanasia are complex, but he thinks that the
arguments in favor of permitting it are stronger
than the arguments against it.