REVIEW: The Structure of Argument: Conclusions and Premises - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 123
About This Presentation
Title:

REVIEW: The Structure of Argument: Conclusions and Premises

Description:

An argument consists of a conclusion (the claim that the speaker or writer is arguing for) and premises (the claims that he or she offers in support of the conclusion). – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:181
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 124
Provided by: jenn277
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: REVIEW: The Structure of Argument: Conclusions and Premises


1
REVIEW The Structure of Argument Conclusions
and Premises
  • An argument consists of a conclusion (the claim
    that the speaker or writer is arguing for) and
    premises (the claims that he or she offers in
    support of the conclusion). Here is an example
    of an argument
  • Premise Every officer on the force has been
    certified, and premise nobody can be certified
    without scoring above 70 percent on the firing
    range. Therefore conclusion every officer on
    the force must have scored above 70 percent on
    the firing range.

2
The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
  • When we analyze an argument, we need to first
    separate the conclusion from the grounds for the
    conclusion which are called premises. Stating it
    another way, in arguments we need to distinguish
    the claim that is being made from the warrants
    that are offered for it. The claim is the
    position that is maintained, while the warrants
    are the reasons given to justify the claim.
  • It is sometimes difficult to make this
    distinction, but it is important to see the
    difference between a conclusion and a premise, a
    claim and its warrant, differentiating between
    what is claimed and the basis for claiming it.

3
The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
  • We might make a claim in a formal argument. For
    example, we might claim that teenage pregnancy
    can be reduced through sex education in the
    schools.
  • To justify our claim we might try to show the
    number of pregnancies in a school before and
    after sex education classes.
  • In writing an argumentative essay we must decide
    on the point we want to make and the reasons we
    will offer to prove it, the conclusion and the
    premises.

4
The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
  • The same distinction must be made in reading
    argumentative essays, namely, what is the writer
    claiming and the warrant is offered for the
    claim, what is being asserted and why. Take the
    following complete argument
  • Television presents a continuous display of
    violence in graphically explicit and extreme
    forms. It also depicts sexuality not as a
    physical expression of internal love but in its
    most lewd and obscene manifestations. We must
    conclude, therefore, that television contributes
    to the moral corruption of individuals exposed to
    it.

5
The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
  • Whether we agree with this position or not, we
    must first identify the logic of the argument to
    test its soundness. In this example the
    conclusion is television contributes to the
    moral corruption of individuals exposed to it.
    The premises appear in the beginning sentences
    Television presents a continuous display of
    violence in graphic and extreme forms, and
    (television) depicts sexualityin its most lewd
    and obscene manifestations. Once we have
    separated the premises and the claim then we need
    to evaluate whether the case has been made for
    the conclusion.

6
The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
  • Has the writer shown that television does corrupt
    society? Has a causal link been shown between
    the depiction of lewd and obscene sex and the
    moral corruption of society? Does TV reflect
    violence in our society or does it promote it?

7
Conclusion Indicators
  • Since dissection is sometimes difficult because
    we cannot always see the skeleton of the
    argument. In such cases we can find help by
    looking for indicator words. When the words in
    the following list are used in arguments, they
    usually indicate a premise has just been offered
    and that a conclusion is about to be presented.
  • Consequently
  • Therefore
  • Thus
  • So
  • Hence
  • accordingly
  • We can conclude that
  • It follows that
  • We may infer that
  • This means that
  • It leads us to believe that
  • This bears out the point that

8
Conclusion Indicators II
  • Example
  • Sarah drives a Dodge Viper. This means that
    either she is rich or her parents are.
  • The conclusion is
  • Either she is rich or her parents are.
  • The premise is
  • Sarah drives a Dodge Viper.

9
Premise Indicators
When the words in the following list are used in
arguments, they generally introduce premises.
They often occur just after a conclusion has been
given.
  • Since
  • Because
  • For
  • whereas
  • In as much as
  • For the reasons that
  • In view of the fact
  • As evidenced by

10
Premise Indicators II
  • Example
  • Either Sarah is rich or her parents are, since
    she drives a Dodge Viper.
  • The premise is the claim that Sarah drives a
    Dodge Viper the conclusion is the claim that
    either Sarah is rich or her parents are.

11
  • Indicator words can tell us when the theses and
    the supports appear, even in complex arguments
    that are embedded in paragraphs. We can see
    whether the person has good reasons for making
    the claim, or whether the argument is weak. We
    should keep this in mind when presenting our own
    case.
  • An argument that presents a clear structure of
    premises and conclusions, without narrative
    digressions, metaphorical flights, or other
    embellishments, is much easier for people to
    follow.

12
Categorical Propositions
  • To help us make sense of our experience, we
    humans constantly group things into classes or
    categories. These classifications are reflected
    in our everyday language. In formal reasoning
    the statements that contain our premises and
    conclusions have to be rendered in a strict form
    so that we know exactly what is being claimed.
    These logical forms were first formulated by
    Aristotle (384-322 B.C.). They are four in
    number, carrying the designations A, E, I, O, as
    follows
  • All S is P (A).
  • No S is P (E).
  • Some S is P (I).
  • Some S is not P (O).

13
Categorical Propositions II
  • The letter "S" stands for the class designated by
    the subject term of the proposition. The letter
    "P" stands for the class designated by the
    predicate term. Substituting any class-defining
    words for S and P generates actual categorical
    propositions.
  • In classical theory, the four standard-form
    categorical propositions were thought to be the
    building blocks of all deductive arguments. Each
    of the four has a conventional designation A for
    universal affirmative propositions E for
    universal negative propositions I for particular
    affirmative propositions and O for particular
    negative propositions.

14
Categorical Propositions III
  • These various relationships between classes are
    affirmed or denied by categorical propositions.
    The result is that there can be just four
    different standard forms of categorical
    propositions. They are illustrated by the four
    following propositions
  • All politicians are liars.
  • No politicians are liars.
  • Some politicians are liars.
  • Some politicians are not liars.

15
Universal Affirmative
  • The first is a universal affirmative proposition.
    It is about two classes, the class of all
    politicians and the class of all liars, saying
    that the first class is included or contained in
    the second class. A universal affirmative
    proposition says that every member of the first
    class is also a member of the second class. In
    the present example, the subject term
    politicians designates the class of all
    politicians, and the predicate term liars
    designates the class of all liars. Any universal
    affirmative proposition may be written
    schematically as
  • All S is P.
  • where the terms S and P represent the subject
    and predicate terms, respectively.

16
Universal Affirmative II
  • The name universal affirmative is appropriate
    because the position affirms that the
    relationship of class inclusion holds between the
    two classes and says that the inclusion is
    complete or universal All members of S are said
    to be members of P also.

17
Universal Negative Propositions
  • The second example
  • No politicians are liars.
  • Is a universal negative proposition. It denies
    of politicians universally that they are liars.
    Concerned with two classes, a universal negative
    proposition says that the first class is wholly
    excluded from the second, which is to say that
    there is no member of the first class that is
    also a member of the second. Any universal
    proposition may be written schematically as
  • No S is P
  • Where, again, the letters S and P represent the
    subject and predicate terms.

18
Universal Negative Propositions II
  • The name universal negative is appropriate
    because the proposition denies that the relation
    of class inclusion holds between the two classes
    and denies it universally No members at all of
    S are members of P.

19
Particular affirmative propositions
  • The third example
  • Some Politicians are liars.
  • is a particular affirmative proposition.
    Clearly, what the present example affirms is that
    some members of the class of all politicians are
    (also) members of the class of all liars. But it
    does not affirm this of politicians universally
    Not all politicians universally, but, rather,
    some particular politician or politicians, are
    said to be liars. This proposition neither
    affirms nor denies that all politicians are
    liars it makes no pronouncement on the matter.

20
Particular affirmative propositions II
  • The word some is indefinite. Does it mean at
    least one, or at least two, or at least one
    hundred? In this type of proposition, it is
    customary to regard the word some as meaning
    at least one. Thus a particular affirmative
    proposition, written schematically as
  • Some S is P.
  • says that at least one member of the class
    designated by the subject term S is also a member
    of the class designated by the predicate term P.
    The name particular affirmative is appropriate
    because the proposition affirms that the
    relationship of class inclusion holds, but does
    not affirm it of the first class universally, but
    only partially, of some particular member or
    members of the first class.

21
Particular negative propositions
  • The fourth example
  • Some politicians are not liars
  • is a particular negative proposition. This
    example, like the one preceding it, does not
    refer to politicians universally but only to some
    member or members of that class it is
    particular. But unlike the third example, it
    does not affirm that the particular members of
    the first class referred to are included in the
    second class this is precisely what is denied.
    A particular negative proposition, schematically
    written as
  • Some S is not P.
  • says that at least one member of the class
    designated by the subject term S is excluded from
    the whole of the class designated by the
    predicate term P.

22
Quality and Quantity
  • Every categorical proposition has a quality,
    either affirmative or negative. It is affirmative
    if the proposition asserts some kind of class
    inclusion, either complete or partial. It is
    negative if the proposition denies any kind of
    class inclusion, either complete or partial.
  • Every categorical proposition also has a
    quantity, either universal or particular. It is
    universal if the proposition refers to all
    members of the class designated by its subject
    term. It is particular if the proposition refers
    only to some members of the class designated by
    its subject term.

23
General Schema of Standard-Form Categorical
Propositions
  • Standard-form categorical propositions consist of
    four parts, as follows
  • Quantifer (subject term) copula (predicate term)
  • The three standard-form quantifiers are "all,"
    "no" (universal), and "some" (particular). The
    copula is a form of the verb "to be."

24
Sentence Standard Form Attribute
All apples are delicious. A All S is P. Universal affirmative
No apples are delicious. E No S is P. Universal negative
Some apples are delicious. I Some S is P. Particular affirmative
Some apples are not delicious. O Some S is not P. Particular negative
25
Distribution
  • Distribution is an attribute of the terms
    (subject and predicate) of propositions. A term
    is said to be distributed if the proposition
    makes an assertion about every member of the
    class denoted by the term otherwise, it is
    undistributed. In other words, a term is
    distributed if and only if the statement assigns
    (or distributes) an attribute to every member of
    the class denoted by the term. Thus, if a
    statement asserts something about every member of
    the S class, then S is distributed otherwise S
    and P are undistributed.

26
All S are P
  • Here is another way to look at All S are P.

The S circle is contained in the P circle, which
represents the fact that every member of S is a
member of P. Through reference to this diagram,
it is clear that every member of S is in the P
class. But the statement does not make a claim
about every member of the P class, since there
may be some members of the P class that are
outside of S.
27
Exercises
  • Translate the following sentences into standard
    form categorical statements
  • Each insect is an animal.
  • Not every sheep is white.
  • A few holidays fall on Saturday.
  • There are a few right handed first basemen.

28
Venn Diagrams

Liars
Politicians
Anything in area 1 is a politician, but not a
liar. Anything in area 2 is both a politician
and a liar. Anything in area 3 is a liar but not
a politician. And anything in area 4, the area
outside the two circles is neither a politician
or a liar.
29
Venn Diagrams II


Liars
Politicians
The shading means that the part of the
politicians circle that does not overlap with the
liars circle is empty that is, it contains no
members. The diagram thus asserts that there are
no politicians who are are not liars. All
politicians are liars.
30
Venn Diagrams III

To say that no politicians are liars is to say
that no members of the class of politicians are
members of the class of liars that is, that
there is no overlap between the two classes. To
represent this claim, we shade the portion of the
two circles that overlaps as shown above. No
politicians are liars.
31
Venn Diagrams IV

In logic, the statement Some politicians are
lairs means There exists at least one
politician and that politician is a liar. To
diagram this statement, we place an X in that
part of the politicians circle that overlaps with
the liars circle.
32
Venn Diagrams IV

A similar strategy is used with statements of the
form Some S are not P. In logic, the statement
Some politicians are not liars means At least
one politician is not a liar. To diagram this
statement we place an X in that part of the
politicians circle that lies outside the liars
circle.
33
Claims about single individuals
  • Claims about single individuals, such as
    Aristotle is a logician, can be tricky to
    translate into standard form. Its clear that
    this claim specifies a class, logicians, and
    places Aristotle as a member of that class. The
    problem is that categorical claims are always
    about two classes, and Aristotle isnt a class.
    (We couldnt talk about some of Aristotle being a
    logician.) What we want to do is treat such
    claims as if they were about classes with exactly
    one member.

34
Claims about single individuals II
  • One way to do this is to use the term people who
    are identical with Aristotle, which of course
    has only Aristotle as a member.
  • Claims about single individuals should be treated
    as A-claims or E-claims.
  • Aristotle is a logician can be translated into
    All people identical with Aristotle are
    logicians.
  • Individual claims do not only involve people.
    For example, Fort Wayne is in Indiana is All
    cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in
    Indiana.

35
Two important things to remember about Some
Statements
  1. In categorical logic, some always means at
    least one.
  2. Some statements are understood to assert that
    something actually exists. Thus, some mammals
    are cats is understood to assert that at least
    one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat.
    By contrast, all or no statements are not
    interpreted as asserting the existence of
    anything. Instead, they are treated as purely
    conditional statements. Thus, All snakes are
    reptiles asserts that if anything is a snake,
    then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes
    and that all of them are reptiles.

36
Exercises
  • Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements.
    In some cases, you may need to rephrase the
    statements slightly to put them in one of the
    four standard forms.
  • No apples are fruits.
  • Some apples are not fruits.
  • All fruits are apples.
  • Some apples are fruits.

37
Translating into standard categorical form
  • Do people really go around saying things like
    some fruits are not apples? Not very often.
    But although relatively few of our everyday
    statements are explicitly in standard categorical
    form, a surprisingly large number of those
    statements can be translated into standard
    categorical form.

38
Common Stylistic Variants of All S are P
  • Example
  • Every S is P. Every dog is an animal.
  • Whoever is an S is a P. Whoever is a
    bachelor is a male.
  • Any S is a P. Any triangle is a
    geometrical figure.
  • Each S is a P. Each eagle is a bird.
  • Only P are S. Only Catholics are popes.
  • Only if something is a Only if something is
    a dog
  • P is it an S. is it a cocker
    spaniel.
  • The only S are P. The only tickets
    available are tickets for cheap
    seats.

39
ONLY
  • Pay special attention to the phrases containing
    the word only in that list. (Only is one of
    the trickiest words in the English language.)
    Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject
    and the predicate terms must be reversed if the
    statement begins with the words only or only
    if. Thus, Only citizens are voters must be
    rewritten as All voters are citizens, not All
    citizens are voters. And, Only if a thing is
    an insect is it a bee must be rewritten as All
    bees are insects, not All insects are bees.

40
Common Stylistic Variants of No S are P
  • Example
  • No S are P. No cows are reptiles.
  • S are not P. Cows are not reptiles.
  • Nothing that is an S Nothing that is a
    known
  • is a P. fact is a mere opinion.
  • No one who is an S No one who is a
    Republican
  • is a P. is a Democrat.
  • All S are non-P. If anything is a plant,
    then it is not a mineral.

41
Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are P
  • Example
  • Some P are S. Some students are men.
  • A few S are P. A few mathematicians are
  • poets.
  • There are S that are P. There are monkeys that
    are
  • carnivores.
  • Several S are P. Several planets in the solar
    system are gas giants.
  • Many S are P. Many students are hard
    workers.
  • Most S are P. Most Americans are
    carnivores.

42
Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are not P
  • Example
  • Not all S are P. Not all politicians are
    liars.
  • Not everyone who is Not everyone who is a
  • an S is a P. politician is a liar.
  • Some S are non-P. Some philosophers are non
    Aristotelians.
  • Most S are not P. Most students are not
    binge drinkers.
  • Nearly all S are Nearly all students are not
  • not P. cheaters.

43
Paraphrasing
  • The process of casting sentences that we find in
    at ext into one of these four forms is
    technically called paraphrasing, and the ability
    to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal
    with statements logically.
  • In the processing of paraphrasing we designate
    the affirmative or negative quality of a
    statement principally by using the words no or
    not. We indicate quantity, meaning whether we
    are referring to the entire class or only a
    portion of it, by using words all or some.
    In addition, we must render the subject and the
    predicate as classes of objects with the verb
    is or are as the copula joining the halves.

44
Paraphrasing II
  • We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming
    the sentences if need be, to determine the parts
    of the sentence, the group that is meant, and
    even what noun is being modified.
  • The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is
    not always obvious. For example, if you think
    for a moment about the claim I always get
    nervous when I take logic exams, youll see its
    a claim about times. Its about getting nervous
    and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but
    it pertains directly to times or occasions. The
    proper translation of the example is All times I
    take logic exams are times that I get nervous.

45
  • Once our statement is translated into proper
    form, we can see it implications to other forms
    of the statement. For example, if we claim All
    scientists are gifted writers, that certainly
    implies that Some scientists are gifted
    writers, but we cannot logically transpose the
    proposition to All gifted writers are
    scientists. In other words, some statements
    would follow, others would not.
  • To help determine when we can infer one statement
    from another and when there is disagreement,
    logicians have devised tables that we can refer
    to if we get confused.

46
Distribution
  • Thus, by the definition of distributed term, S
    is distributed and P is not. In other words for
    any (A) proposition, the subject term, whatever
    it may be, is distributed and the predicate term
    is undistributed.

47
(No Transcript)
48
No S are P
  • No S are P states that the S and P class are
    separate, which may be represented as follows

This statement makes a claim about every member
of S and every member of P. It asserts that
every member of S is separate from every member
of P, and also that every member of P is separate
from every member of S. Both the subject and the
predicate terms of universal negative (E)
propositions are distributed.
49
Some S are P
  • The particular affirmative (I) proposition states
    that at least one member of S is a member of P.
    If we represent this one member of S that we are
    certain about by an asterisk, the resulting
    diagram looks like this

Since the asterisk is inside the P class, it
represents something that is simultaneously an S
and a P in other words, it represents a member
of the S class that is also a member of the P
class. Thus, the statement Some S are P makes
a claim about one member (at least) of S and also
one member (at least) of P, but not about all
members of either class. Thus, neither S or P is
distributed.
50
Some S are not P
  • The particular negative (O) proposition asserts
    that at least one member of S is not a member of
    P. If we once again represent this one member of
    S by an asterisk, the resulting diagram is as
    follows

Since the other members of S may or may not be
outside of P, it is clear that the statement
Some S are not P does not make a claim about
every member of S, so S is not distributed. But,
as may be seen from the diagram, the statement
does assert that the entire P class is separated
from this one member of the S that is outside
that is, it does make a claim about every member
of P. Thus, in the particular negative (O)
proposition, P is distributed and S is
undistributed.
51
Two mnemonic devices for distribution
  • Unprepared Students Never Pass
  • Universals distribute Subjects.
  • Negatives distribute Predicates.
  • Any Student Earning Bs Is Not On Probation
  • A distributes Subject.
  • E distributes Both.
  • I distributes Neither.
  • O distributes Predicate.

52
The Traditional Square of Opposition
  • Quality, quantity, and distribution tell us what
    standard-form categorical propositions assert
    about their subject and predicate terms, not
    whether those assertions are true. Taken
    together, however, A, E, I, and O propositions
    with the same subject and predicate terms have
    relationships of opposition that do permit
    conclusions about truth and falsity. In other
    words, if we know whether or not a proposition in
    one form is true or false, we can draw certain
    valid conclusions about the truth or falsity of
    propositions with the same terms in other forms.

53
Traditional Square of Opposition II
  • There are four ways in which propositions may be
    opposed-as contradictories, contraries,
    subcontraries, and subalterns.

54
(No Transcript)
55
Contradictories
  • Two propositions are contradictories if one is
    the denial or negation of the other that is, if
    they cannot both be true and cannot both be false
    at the same time. If one is true, the other must
    be false. If one is false, the other must be
    true.
  • A propositions (All S is P) and O propositions
    (Some S is not P), which differ in both quantity
    and quality, are contradictories.

56
Contradictories II
  • All logic books are interesting books.Some logic
    books are not interesting books.
  • Here we have two categorical propositions with
    the same subject and predicate terms that differ
    in quantity and quality. One is an A proposition
    (universal and affirmative). The second is an O
    proposition (particular and negative).
  • Can both of these propositions be true at the
    same time? The answer is "no." If all logic books
    are interesting, than it can't be true that some
    of them are not. Likewise, if some of them are
    not interesting, then it can't be true that all
    of them are.
  • Can both propositions be false at the same time?
    Again, the answer is "no". If it's false that all
    logic books are interesting, then it must be true
    that some of them are not interesting. Likewise
    if it's false that some of them are not
    interesting, then all of them must be
    interesting.
  • Like this pair, all A and O propositions with the
    same subject and predicate terms are
    contradictories. One is the denial of the other.
    They can't both be true or false at the same
    time.

57
Contradictories III
  • E propositions (No S is P) and I propositions
    (Some S is P) likewise differ in quantity and
    quality and are contradictories.
  • Example No presidential elections are contested
    elections. Some presidential elections are
    contested elections.
  • Here again we have two categorical propositions
    with the same subject and predicate terms that
    differ in both quantity and quality. In this
    case, the first is an E propositionuniversal and
    negativeand the second is an I
    propositionparticular and positive.
  • Can both be true at the same time? The answer is
    "no." If no presidential elections are contested,
    then it can't be true that some are. Likewise is
    some are contested, then it can't be true that
    none are.

58
Contradictories IV
  • Can both be false at the same time? Again the
    answer is "no." If it's false that no
    presidential elections are contested, then it
    must be true that some of them are. Likewise if
    it's false that some are contested, then it must
    be the case that none are.
  • Like this pair, all E and I propositions with the
    same subject and predicate terms are
    contradictories. One is the denial of the other.
    They can't both be true or false at the same
    time.

59
Contraries
  • Two propositions are contraries if they cannot
    both be true that is, if the truth of one
    entails the falsity of the other. If one is true,
    the other must be false. But if one is false, it
    does not follow that the other has to be true.
    Both might be false.
  • A (All S is P) and E (No S is P)
    propositions-which are both universal but differ
    in quality-are contraries unless one is
    necessarily (logically or mathematically) true.
  • For example
  • All books are written by Stephen King.
  • No books are written by Stephen King.
  • Both are false.

60
Subcontraries
  • Two propositions are subcontraries if they cannot
    both be false, although they both may be true.
  • I (Some S is P) and O (Some S is not P)
    propositions-which are both particular but differ
    in quality-are subcontraries unless one is
    necessarily false.
  • For example
  • Some dogs are cocker spaniels.
  • Some dogs are not cocker spaniels.

61
Subalternation
  • Subalternation is the relationship between a
    universal proposition (the superaltern) and its
    corresponding particular proposition (the
    subaltern).
  • According to Aristotelian logic, whenever a
    universal proposition is true, its corresponding
    particular must be true. Thus if an A proposition
    (All S is P) is true, the corresponding I
    proposition (Some S is P) is also true. Likewise
    if an E proposition (No S is P) is true, so too
    is its corresponding particular (Some S is not
    P). The reverse, however, does not hold. That is,
    if a particular proposition is true, its
    corresponding universal might be true or it might
    be false.

62
Subalternation II
  • For example All bananas are fruit. Therefore,
    some bananas are fruit.
  • Or, no humans are reptiles. Therefore, some
    humans are not reptiles.
  • However, we cant go in reverse. We cant say
    some animals are not dogs. Therefore, no animals
    are dogs.
  • Or, some guitar players are famous rock
    musicians. Therefore, all guitar players are
    famous rock musicians.

63
Conversion
  • The first kind of immediate inference, called
    conversion, proceeds by simply interchanging the
    subject and predicate terms of the proposition.
  • Conversion is valid in the case of E and I
    propositions. No women are American
    Presidents, can be validly converted to No
    American Presidents are women.
  • An example of an I conversion Some politicians
    are liars, and Some liars are politicians are
    logically equivalent, so by conversion either can
    be validly inferred from the other.

64
Conversion II
  • One standard-form proposition is said to be the
    converse of another when it is formed by simply
    interchanging the subject and predicate terms of
    that other proposition. Thus, No idealists are
    politicians is the converse of No politicians
    are idealists, and each can validly be inferred
    from the other by conversion. The term
    convertend is used to refer to the premise of an
    immediate inference by conversion, and the
    conclusion of the inference is called the
    converse.

65
Conversion III
  • Note that the converse of an A proposition is not
    generally valid form that A proposition.
  • For example All bananas are fruit, does not
    imply the converse, All fruit are bananas.
  • A combination of subalternation and conversion
    does, however, yield a valid immediate inference
    for A propositions. If we know that "All S is P,"
    then by subalternation we can conclude that the
    corresponding I proposition, "Some S is P," is
    true, and by conversion (valid for I
    propositions) that some P is S. This process is
    called conversion by limitation.

66
Conversion IV
  • Convertend A proposition All IBM computers are
    things that use electricity. Converse A
    proposition All things that use electricity are
    IBM computers.
  • Convertend A proposition All IBM computers are
    things that use electricity. Corresponding
    particular I proposition Some IBM computers
    are things that use electricity. Converse (by
    limitation) I proposition Some things that use
    electricity are IBM computers.
  • The first part of this example indicates why
    conversion applied directly to A propositions
    does not yield valid immediate inferences. It is
    certainly true that all IBM computers use
    electricity, but it is certainly false that all
    things that use electricity are IBM computers.
  • Conversion by limitation, however, does yield a
    valid immediate inference for A propositions
    according to Aristotelian logic. From "All IBM
    computers are things that use electricity" we
    get, by subalternation, the I proposition "Some
    IBM computers are things that use electricity."
    And because conversion is valid for I
    propositions, we can conclude, finally, that
    "Some things that use electricity are IBM
    computers."

67
Conversion V
  • The converse ofSome S is not P, does not yield
    an valid immediate inference.
  • Convertend O proposition Some dogs are not
    cocker spaniels.Converse O proposition Some
    cocker spaniels are not dogs.
  • This example indicates why conversion of O
    prepositions does not yield a valid immediate
    inference. The first proposition is true, but its
    converse is false.

68
Conversion Table
Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men.
Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men.
69
Obversion
  • Obversion - A valid form of immediate inference
    for every standard-form categorical proposition.
    To obvert a proposition we change its quality
    (from affirmative to negative, or from negative
    to affirmative) and replace the predicate term
    with its complement. Thus, applied to the
    proposition "All cocker spaniels are dogs,"
    obversion yields "No cockerspaniels are nondogs,"
    which is called its "obverse." The proposition
    obverted is called the "obvertend."

70
Obversion II
  • The obverse is logically equivalent to the
    obvertend. Obversion is thus a valid immediate
    inference when applied to any standard-form
    categorical proposition.
  • The obverse of the A proposition "All S is P" is
    the E proposition "No S is non-P."
  • The obverse of the E proposition "No S is P" is
    the A proposition "All S is non-P."

71
Obversion III
  • The obverse of the I proposition "Some S is P" is
    the O proposition "Some S is not non-P."
  • The obverse of the O proposition "Some S is not
    P" is the I proposition "Some S is non-P."
  • Obvertend A-proposition All cartoon characters
    are fictional characters. Obverse
    E-proposition No cartoon characters are
    non-fictional characters.
  • Obvertend E-proposition No current sitcoms are
    funny shows. Obverse A-proposition All current
    sitcoms are non-funny shows.

72
Obversion IV
  • Obvertend I-proposition Some rap songs are
    lullabies. Obverse O-proposition Some rap
    songs are not non-lullabies.
  • Obvertend O-proposition Some movie stars are
    not geniuses. Obverse I-proposition Some movie
    stars are non-geniuses.

73
Obversion V
  • As these examples indicate, obversion always
    yields a valid immediate inference.
  • If every cartoon character is a fictional
    character, then it must be true that no cartoon
    character is a non-fictional character.
  • If no current sitcoms are funny, then all of them
    must be something other than funny.
  • If some rap songs are lullabies, then those
    particular rap songs at least must not be things
    that aren't lullabies.
  • If some movie stars are not geniuses, than they
    must be something other than geniuses.

74
Contraposition
  • Contraposition is a process that involves
    replacing the subject term of a categorical
    proposition with the complement of its predicate
    term and its predicate term with the complement
    of its subject term.
  • Contraposition yields a valid immediate inference
    for A propositions and O propositions. That is,
    if the proposition
  • All S is P is true, then its contrapositive
  • All non-P is non-S is also true.

75
Contraposition II
  • For example
  • Premise
  • A proposition All logic books are interesting
    things to read.
  • Contrapositive
  • A proposition All non interesting things to read
    are non logic books.

76
Contraposition III
  • The contrapositive of an A proposition is a valid
    immediate inference from its premise. If the
    first proposition is true it places every logic
    book in the class of interesting things to read.
    The contrapositive claims that any
    non-interesting things to read are also non-logic
    bookssomething other than a logic bookand
    surely this must be correct.

77
Contraposition IV
  • Premise
  • I-proposition Some humans are non-logic
    teachers.
  • Contrapositive
  • I-proposition Some logic teachers are not human.
  • As this example suggests, contraposition does
    not yield valid immediate inferences for I
    propositions. The first proposition is true, but
    the second is clearly false.

78
Contraposition V
  • E premise
  • No dentists are non-graduates.
  • The contrapositive is No graduates are
    non-dentists.
  • Obviously this is not true.

79
Contraposition VI
  • The contrapositive of an E proposition does not
    yield a valid immediate inference. This is
    because the propositions "No S is P" and "Some
    non-P is non-S" can both be true. But in that
    case "No non-P is non-S," the contrapositive of
    "No S is P," would have to be false.
  • A combination of subalternation and
    contraposition does, however, yield a valid
    immediate inference for E propositions. If we
    know that "No S is P" is true, then by
    subalternation we can conclude that the
    corresponding O proposition, "Some S is not P,"
    is true, and by contraposition (valid for O
    propositions) that "Some non-P is not non-S" is
    also true. This process is called contraposition
    by limitation.

80
Contraposition VII
  • Premise
  • E-proposition No Game Show Hosts are Brain
    Surgeons.
  • Contrapositive
  • E proposition No non-Brain Surgeons are non-Game
    show hosts.
  • Premise
  • E proposition No game show hosts are brain
    surgeons.
  • Corresponding particular O proposition Some game
    show hosts are not brain surgeons.
  • Contrapositive
  • O proposition Some non-brain surgeons are not
    non-game show hosts.

81
Contraposition VIII
  • The first part of this example indicates why
    contraposition applied directly to E propositions
    does not yield valid immediate inferences. Even
    if the first proposition is true then the second
    can still be false. This may be hard to see at
    first, but if we take it apart slowly we can
    understand why. The first proposition, if true,
    clearly separates the class of game show hosts
    from the class of brain surgeons, allowing no
    overlap between them. It does not, however, tell
    us anything specific about what is outside those
    classes. But the second proposition does refer to
    the areas outside the classes and what it says
    might be false. It claims that there is not even
    one thing outside the class of brain surgeons
    that is, at the same time, a non-game show host.
    But wait a minute. Most of us are neither brain
    surgeons nor game show hosts. Clearly the
    contrapositive is false.

82
Contraposition IX
  • Contraposition by limitation, however, does yield
    a valid immediate inference for E propositions
    according to Aristotelian logic. By
    subalternation from the first proposition we get
    the O proposition "Some game show hosts are not
    brain surgeons." And then by contraposition,
    which is valid for O propositions, we get the
    valid, if tongue-twisting O proposition, "Some
    non-brain surgeons are not non-game show hosts."

83
Contraposition X
  • O proposition.
  • Premise
  • Some flowers are not roses.
  • Some non-roses are not non-flowers.
  • This is valid. Thus we can see that
    contraposition is a valid form of inference only
    when applied to A and O propositions.
    Contraposition is not valid at all for I
    propositions and is valid for E propositions only
    by limitation.

84
Contraposition XI
Table of Contraposition Table of Contraposition
Premise Contrapositive
A All S is P. A All non-P is non-S.
E No S is P. O Some non-P is not non-S. (by limitation)
I Some S is P. Contraposition not valid.
O Some S is not P. Some non-P is not non-S.
85
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions
  • Aristotelian logic suffers from a dilemma that
    undermines the validity of many relationships in
    the traditional Square of Opposition.
    Mathematician and logician George Boole proposed
    a resolution to this dilemma in the late
    nineteenth century. This Boolean interpretation
    of categorical propositions has displaced the
    Aristotelian interpretation in modern logic.

86
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions II
  • The source of the dilemma is the problem of
    existential import. A proposition is said to have
    existential import if it asserts the existence of
    objects of some kind. I and O propositions have
    existential import they assert that the classes
    designated by their subject terms are not empty.
    But in Aristotelian logic, I and O propositions
    follow validly from A and E propositions by
    subalternation. As a result, Aristotelian logic
    requires A and E propositions to have existential
    import, because a proposition with existential
    import cannot be derived from a proposition
    without existential import.

87
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions III
  • A and O propositions with the same subject and
    predicate terms are contradictories, and so
    cannot both be false at the same time. But if A
    propositions have existential import, then an A
    proposition and its contradictory O proposition
    would both be false when their subject class was
    empty.
  • For example
  • Unicorns have horns. If there are no unicorns,
    then it is false that all unicorns have horns and
    it is also false that some unicorns have horns.

88
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions IV
  • The Boolean interpretation of categorical
    propositions solves this dilemma by denying that
    universal propositions have existential import.
    This has the following consequences
  • I propositions and O propositions have
    existential import.
  • A-O and E-I pairs with the same subject and
    predicate terms retain their relationship as
    contradictories.
  • Because A and E propositions have no existential
    import, subalternation is generally not valid.
  • Contraries are eliminated because A and E
    propositions can now both be true when the
    subject class is empty. Similarly, subcontraries
    are eliminated because I and O propositions can
    now both be false when the subject class is
    empty.

89
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions V
  • Some immediate inferences are preserved
    conversion for E and I propositions,
    contraposition for A and O propositions, and
    obversion for any proposition. But conversion by
    limitation and contraposition by limitation are
    no longer generally valid.
  • Any argument that relies on the mistaken
    assumption of existence commits the existential
    fallacy.

90
Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions VI
  • The result is to undo the relations along the
    sides of the traditional Square of Opposition but
    to leave the diagonal, contradictory relations in
    force.

91
Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions
  • The relationships among classes in the Boolean
    interpretation of categorical propositions can be
    represented in symbolic notation. We represent a
    class by a circle labeled with the term that
    designates the class. Thus the class S is
    diagrammed as shown below

92
Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions II
  • To diagram the proposition that S has no members,
    or that there are no Ss, we shade all of the
    interior of the circle representing S, indicating
    in this way that it contains nothing and is
    empty. To diagram the proposition that there are
    Ss, which we interpret as saying that there is
    at least one member of S, we place an x anywhere
    in the interior of the circle representing S,
    indicating in this way that there is something
    inside it, that it is not empty.

93
Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions III
  • To diagram a standard-form categorical
    proposition, not one but two circles are
    required. The framework for diagramming any
    standard-form proposition whose subject and
    predicate terms are abbreviated by S and P is
    constructed by drawing two intersecting circles

94
(No Transcript)
95
(No Transcript)
96
(No Transcript)
97
Claims about single individuals
  • Claims about single individuals, such as
    Aristotle is a logician, can be tricky to
    translate into standard form. Its clear that
    this claim specifies a class, logicians, and
    places Aristotle as a member of that class. The
    problem is that categorical claims are always
    about two classes, and Aristotle isnt a class.
    (We couldnt talk about some of Aristotle being a
    logician.) What we want to do is treat such
    claims as if they were about classes with exactly
    one member.

98
Claims about single individuals II
  • One way to do this is to use the term people who
    are identical with Aristotle, which of course
    has only Aristotle as a member.
  • Claims about single individuals should be treated
    as A-claims or E-claims.
  • Aristotle is a logician can be translated into
    All people identical with Aristotle are
    logicians.
  • Individual claims do not only involve people.
    For example, Fort Wayne is in Indiana is All
    cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in
    Indiana.

99
Two important things to remember about Some
Statements
  1. In categorical logic, some always means at
    least one.
  2. Some statements are understood to assert that
    something actually exists. Thus, some mammals
    are cats is understood to assert that at least
    one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat.
    By contrast, all or no statements are not
    interpreted as asserting the existence of
    anything. Instead, they are treated as purely
    conditional statements. Thus, All snakes are
    reptiles asserts that if anything is a snake,
    then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes
    and that all of them are reptiles.

100
Exercises
  • Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements.
    In some cases, you may need to rephrase the
    statements slightly to put them in one of the
    four standard forms.
  • No apples are fruits.
  • Some apples are not fruits.
  • All fruits are apples.
  • Some apples are fruits.

101
Translating into standard categorical form
  • Do people really go around saying things like
    some fruits are not apples? Not very often.
    But although relatively few of our everyday
    statements are explicitly in standard categorical
    form, a surprisingly large number of those
    statements can be translated into standard
    categorical form.

102
Common Stylistic Variants of All S are P
  • Example
  • Every S is P. Every dog is an animal.
  • Whoever is an S is a P. Whoever is a
    bachelor is a male.
  • Any S is a P. Any triangle is a
    geometrical figure.
  • Each S is a P. Each eagle is a bird.
  • Only P are S. Only Catholics are popes.
  • Only if something is a Only if something is
    a dog
  • P is it an S. is it a cocker
    spaniel.
  • The only S are P. The only tickets
    available are tickets for cheap
    seats.

103
ONLY
  • Pay special attention to the phrases containing
    the word only in that list. (Only is one of
    the trickiest words in the English language.)
    Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject
    and the predicate terms must be reversed if the
    statement begins with the words only or only
    if. Thus, Only citizens are voters must be
    rewritten as All voters are citizens, not All
    citizens are voters. And, Only if a thing is
    an insect is it a bee must be rewritten as All
    bees are insects, not All insects are bees.

104
Common Stylistic Variants of No S are P
  • Example
  • No S are P. No cows are reptiles.
  • S are not P. Cows are not reptiles.
  • Nothing that is an S Nothing that is a
    known
  • is a P. fact is a mere opinion.
  • No one who is an S No one who is a
    Republican
  • is a P. is a Democrat.
  • All S are non-P. If anything is a plant,
    then it is not a mineral.

105
Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are P
  • Some P are S.
  • A few S are P.
  • There are S that are P.
  • Several S are P.
  • Many S are P.
  • Most S are P.

106
Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are not P
  • Not all S are P.
  • Not everyone who is
  • an S is a P.
  • Some S are non-P.
  • Most S are not P.
  • Nearly all S are
  • not P.

107
Paraphrasing
  • The process of casting sentences that we find in
    at ext into one of these four forms is
    technically called paraphrasing, and the ability
    to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal
    with statements logically.
  • In the processing of paraphrasing we designate
    the affirmative or negative quality of a
    statement principally by using the words no or
    not. We indicate quantity, meaning whether we
    are referring to the entire class or only a
    portion of it, by using words all or some.
    In addition, we must render the subject and the
    predicate as classes of objects with the verb
    is or are as the copula joining the halves.

108
Paraphrasing II
  • We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming
    the sentences if need be, to determine the parts
    of the sentence, the group that is meant, and
    even what noun is being modified.
  • The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is
    not always obvious. For example, if you think
    for a moment about the claim I always get
    nervous when I take logic exams, youll see its
    a claim about times. Its about getting nervous
    and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but
    it pertains directly to times or occasions. The
    proper translation of the example is All times I
    take logic exams are times that I get nervous.

109
  • Once our statement is translated into proper
    form, we can see it implications to other forms
    of the statement. For example, if we claim All
    scientists are gifted writers, that certainly
    implies that Some scientists are gifted
    writers, but we cannot logically transpose the
    proposition to All gifted writers are
    scientists. In other words, some statements
    would follow, others would not.
  • To help determine when we can infer one statement
    from another and when there is disagreement,
    logicians have devised tables that we can refer
    to if we get confused.

110
Conversion Table
Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men.
Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men.
111
Syllogisms
  • Syllogism a deductive argument in which a
    conclusion is inferred from two premises.
  • In a syllogism we lay out our train of reasoning
    in an explicit way, identifying the major premise
    of the argument, the minor premise, and the
    conclusion.
  • The major premise consists of the chief reason
    for the conclusion, or more technically, it is
    the premise that contains the term in the
    predicate of the conclusion.
  • The minor premise supports the conclusion in an
    auxiliary way, or more precisely, it contains the
    term that appears in the subject of the
    conclusion.
  • The conclusion is the point of the argument, the
    outcome, or necessary consequence of the premise.

112
Syllogisms II
  • Example in an argumentative essay
  • In determining who has committed war crimes we
    must ask ourselves who has slaughtered unarmed
    civilians, whether as reprisal, ethnic
    cleansing, terrorism, or outright genocide.
    For along with pillaging, rape, and other
    atrocities, this is what war crimes consist of .
    In the civil war in the former Yugoslavia,
    soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army committed
    hundreds of murders of this kind. They must
    therefore be judged guilty of war crimes along
    with the other awful groups in our century, most
    notably the Nazis.

113
Syllogisms III
  • The conclusion to this argument is that soldiers
    in the Bosnian Serb army are guilty of war
    crimes. The premises supporting the conclusion
    are that slaughtering unarmed civilians is a war
    crime, and soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army have
    slaughtered unarmed civilians. The following
    syllogism will diagram this argument.
  • All soldiers who slaughter unarmed civilians are
    guilty of war crimes.
  • Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are soldiers who
    slaughter unarmed civilians

  • Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are guilty of war
    crimes.

114
Enthymeme
  • Enthymeme - An argument that is stated
    incompletely, the unstated part of it being taken
    for granted. An enthymeme may be the first,
    second, or third order, depending on whether the
    unstated proposition is the major premise, the
    minor premise, or the conclusion of the argument.
  • Enthymemes traditionally have been divided into
    different orders, according to which part of the
    syllogism is left unexpressed.

115
Enthymeme II
  • A first order enthymeme is one in which the
    syllogisms major premise is not stated.
  • For example, suppose someone said, We must
    expect to find needles on all pine trees they
    are conifers after all. Once we recognize this
    as an enthymeme we must provide the unstated
    (major) premise, namely, All conifers have
    needles. Then we need to paraphrase the
    statements and arrange them in a syllogism,
    indicating by parentheses which one we added was
    not in the text
  • (All conifers are trees that have needles.)
  • All pine trees are conifers.
  • All pine trees are trees that have needles.

116
Enthymeme III
  • A second - order enthymeme is one in which only
    the major premise and the conclusion are stated,
    the minor premise being suppressed.
  • For example, Of course tennis players arent
    weak, in fact, no athletes are weak. Obviously,
    the missing premise is Tennis players are
    athletes, so the syllogism would appear this
    way.
  • No athletes are weak.
  • (All tennis players are athletes.)
  • No tennis players are weak.

117
Enthymeme IV
  • A third order enthymeme is one in which both
    premises are sated, but the conclusion is left
    unexpressed.
  • For example, All true democrats believe in
    freedom of speech, but there are some Americans
    who would impose censorship on free expression.
    The reader is left to draw the conclusion that
    some Americans are not true democrats. The
    syllogism
  • All true democrats are people who believe in
    freedom of speech.
  • Some Americans are not people who believe in
    freedom of speech.
  • (Some Americans are not true democrats.)

118
Exercises
  • No certainty should be rejected. So, no
    self-evident propositions should be rejected.
  • Some beliefs about aliens are not rational, for
    all rational beliefs are proportional to the
    available evidence.
  • John is a member of the police force and all
    policemen carry guns.

119
Validity and Truth
  • No matter how diligent we are in constructing our
    argument in proper form, our conclusion can still
    be mistaken if the conclusion does not strictly
    follow from the premises, that is, if the logic
    is not sound.
  • For example,
  • All fish are gilled creatures.
  • All tuna are fish.
  • All tuna are gilled creatures.
  • This seems correct.

120
Validity and Truth II
  • But suppose we want to claim that all tuna are
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com