Title: REVIEW: The Structure of Argument: Conclusions and Premises
1REVIEW The Structure of Argument Conclusions
and Premises
- An argument consists of a conclusion (the claim
that the speaker or writer is arguing for) and
premises (the claims that he or she offers in
support of the conclusion). Here is an example
of an argument - Premise Every officer on the force has been
certified, and premise nobody can be certified
without scoring above 70 percent on the firing
range. Therefore conclusion every officer on
the force must have scored above 70 percent on
the firing range.
2The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
- When we analyze an argument, we need to first
separate the conclusion from the grounds for the
conclusion which are called premises. Stating it
another way, in arguments we need to distinguish
the claim that is being made from the warrants
that are offered for it. The claim is the
position that is maintained, while the warrants
are the reasons given to justify the claim. - It is sometimes difficult to make this
distinction, but it is important to see the
difference between a conclusion and a premise, a
claim and its warrant, differentiating between
what is claimed and the basis for claiming it.
3The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
- We might make a claim in a formal argument. For
example, we might claim that teenage pregnancy
can be reduced through sex education in the
schools. - To justify our claim we might try to show the
number of pregnancies in a school before and
after sex education classes. - In writing an argumentative essay we must decide
on the point we want to make and the reasons we
will offer to prove it, the conclusion and the
premises.
4The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
- The same distinction must be made in reading
argumentative essays, namely, what is the writer
claiming and the warrant is offered for the
claim, what is being asserted and why. Take the
following complete argument - Television presents a continuous display of
violence in graphically explicit and extreme
forms. It also depicts sexuality not as a
physical expression of internal love but in its
most lewd and obscene manifestations. We must
conclude, therefore, that television contributes
to the moral corruption of individuals exposed to
it.
5The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
- Whether we agree with this position or not, we
must first identify the logic of the argument to
test its soundness. In this example the
conclusion is television contributes to the
moral corruption of individuals exposed to it.
The premises appear in the beginning sentences
Television presents a continuous display of
violence in graphic and extreme forms, and
(television) depicts sexualityin its most lewd
and obscene manifestations. Once we have
separated the premises and the claim then we need
to evaluate whether the case has been made for
the conclusion.
6The Structure of Argument Conclusions and
Premises
- Has the writer shown that television does corrupt
society? Has a causal link been shown between
the depiction of lewd and obscene sex and the
moral corruption of society? Does TV reflect
violence in our society or does it promote it?
7Conclusion Indicators
- Since dissection is sometimes difficult because
we cannot always see the skeleton of the
argument. In such cases we can find help by
looking for indicator words. When the words in
the following list are used in arguments, they
usually indicate a premise has just been offered
and that a conclusion is about to be presented.
- Consequently
- Therefore
- Thus
- So
- Hence
- accordingly
- We can conclude that
- It follows that
- We may infer that
- This means that
- It leads us to believe that
- This bears out the point that
8Conclusion Indicators II
- Example
- Sarah drives a Dodge Viper. This means that
either she is rich or her parents are. - The conclusion is
- Either she is rich or her parents are.
- The premise is
- Sarah drives a Dodge Viper.
9Premise Indicators
When the words in the following list are used in
arguments, they generally introduce premises.
They often occur just after a conclusion has been
given.
- Since
- Because
- For
- whereas
- In as much as
- For the reasons that
- In view of the fact
- As evidenced by
10Premise Indicators II
- Example
- Either Sarah is rich or her parents are, since
she drives a Dodge Viper. - The premise is the claim that Sarah drives a
Dodge Viper the conclusion is the claim that
either Sarah is rich or her parents are.
11- Indicator words can tell us when the theses and
the supports appear, even in complex arguments
that are embedded in paragraphs. We can see
whether the person has good reasons for making
the claim, or whether the argument is weak. We
should keep this in mind when presenting our own
case. - An argument that presents a clear structure of
premises and conclusions, without narrative
digressions, metaphorical flights, or other
embellishments, is much easier for people to
follow.
12Categorical Propositions
- To help us make sense of our experience, we
humans constantly group things into classes or
categories. These classifications are reflected
in our everyday language. In formal reasoning
the statements that contain our premises and
conclusions have to be rendered in a strict form
so that we know exactly what is being claimed.
These logical forms were first formulated by
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.). They are four in
number, carrying the designations A, E, I, O, as
follows - All S is P (A).
- No S is P (E).
- Some S is P (I).
- Some S is not P (O).
13Categorical Propositions II
- The letter "S" stands for the class designated by
the subject term of the proposition. The letter
"P" stands for the class designated by the
predicate term. Substituting any class-defining
words for S and P generates actual categorical
propositions. - In classical theory, the four standard-form
categorical propositions were thought to be the
building blocks of all deductive arguments. Each
of the four has a conventional designation A for
universal affirmative propositions E for
universal negative propositions I for particular
affirmative propositions and O for particular
negative propositions.
14Categorical Propositions III
- These various relationships between classes are
affirmed or denied by categorical propositions.
The result is that there can be just four
different standard forms of categorical
propositions. They are illustrated by the four
following propositions - All politicians are liars.
- No politicians are liars.
- Some politicians are liars.
- Some politicians are not liars.
15Universal Affirmative
- The first is a universal affirmative proposition.
It is about two classes, the class of all
politicians and the class of all liars, saying
that the first class is included or contained in
the second class. A universal affirmative
proposition says that every member of the first
class is also a member of the second class. In
the present example, the subject term
politicians designates the class of all
politicians, and the predicate term liars
designates the class of all liars. Any universal
affirmative proposition may be written
schematically as - All S is P.
- where the terms S and P represent the subject
and predicate terms, respectively.
16Universal Affirmative II
- The name universal affirmative is appropriate
because the position affirms that the
relationship of class inclusion holds between the
two classes and says that the inclusion is
complete or universal All members of S are said
to be members of P also.
17Universal Negative Propositions
- The second example
- No politicians are liars.
- Is a universal negative proposition. It denies
of politicians universally that they are liars.
Concerned with two classes, a universal negative
proposition says that the first class is wholly
excluded from the second, which is to say that
there is no member of the first class that is
also a member of the second. Any universal
proposition may be written schematically as - No S is P
- Where, again, the letters S and P represent the
subject and predicate terms.
18Universal Negative Propositions II
- The name universal negative is appropriate
because the proposition denies that the relation
of class inclusion holds between the two classes
and denies it universally No members at all of
S are members of P.
19Particular affirmative propositions
- The third example
- Some Politicians are liars.
- is a particular affirmative proposition.
Clearly, what the present example affirms is that
some members of the class of all politicians are
(also) members of the class of all liars. But it
does not affirm this of politicians universally
Not all politicians universally, but, rather,
some particular politician or politicians, are
said to be liars. This proposition neither
affirms nor denies that all politicians are
liars it makes no pronouncement on the matter.
20Particular affirmative propositions II
- The word some is indefinite. Does it mean at
least one, or at least two, or at least one
hundred? In this type of proposition, it is
customary to regard the word some as meaning
at least one. Thus a particular affirmative
proposition, written schematically as - Some S is P.
- says that at least one member of the class
designated by the subject term S is also a member
of the class designated by the predicate term P.
The name particular affirmative is appropriate
because the proposition affirms that the
relationship of class inclusion holds, but does
not affirm it of the first class universally, but
only partially, of some particular member or
members of the first class.
21Particular negative propositions
- The fourth example
- Some politicians are not liars
- is a particular negative proposition. This
example, like the one preceding it, does not
refer to politicians universally but only to some
member or members of that class it is
particular. But unlike the third example, it
does not affirm that the particular members of
the first class referred to are included in the
second class this is precisely what is denied.
A particular negative proposition, schematically
written as - Some S is not P.
- says that at least one member of the class
designated by the subject term S is excluded from
the whole of the class designated by the
predicate term P. -
22Quality and Quantity
- Every categorical proposition has a quality,
either affirmative or negative. It is affirmative
if the proposition asserts some kind of class
inclusion, either complete or partial. It is
negative if the proposition denies any kind of
class inclusion, either complete or partial. - Every categorical proposition also has a
quantity, either universal or particular. It is
universal if the proposition refers to all
members of the class designated by its subject
term. It is particular if the proposition refers
only to some members of the class designated by
its subject term.
23General Schema of Standard-Form Categorical
Propositions
- Standard-form categorical propositions consist of
four parts, as follows - Quantifer (subject term) copula (predicate term)
- The three standard-form quantifiers are "all,"
"no" (universal), and "some" (particular). The
copula is a form of the verb "to be."
24Sentence Standard Form Attribute
All apples are delicious. A All S is P. Universal affirmative
No apples are delicious. E No S is P. Universal negative
Some apples are delicious. I Some S is P. Particular affirmative
Some apples are not delicious. O Some S is not P. Particular negative
25Distribution
- Distribution is an attribute of the terms
(subject and predicate) of propositions. A term
is said to be distributed if the proposition
makes an assertion about every member of the
class denoted by the term otherwise, it is
undistributed. In other words, a term is
distributed if and only if the statement assigns
(or distributes) an attribute to every member of
the class denoted by the term. Thus, if a
statement asserts something about every member of
the S class, then S is distributed otherwise S
and P are undistributed.
26All S are P
- Here is another way to look at All S are P.
The S circle is contained in the P circle, which
represents the fact that every member of S is a
member of P. Through reference to this diagram,
it is clear that every member of S is in the P
class. But the statement does not make a claim
about every member of the P class, since there
may be some members of the P class that are
outside of S.
27Exercises
- Translate the following sentences into standard
form categorical statements - Each insect is an animal.
- Not every sheep is white.
- A few holidays fall on Saturday.
- There are a few right handed first basemen.
28Venn Diagrams
Liars
Politicians
Anything in area 1 is a politician, but not a
liar. Anything in area 2 is both a politician
and a liar. Anything in area 3 is a liar but not
a politician. And anything in area 4, the area
outside the two circles is neither a politician
or a liar.
29Venn Diagrams II
Liars
Politicians
The shading means that the part of the
politicians circle that does not overlap with the
liars circle is empty that is, it contains no
members. The diagram thus asserts that there are
no politicians who are are not liars. All
politicians are liars.
30Venn Diagrams III
To say that no politicians are liars is to say
that no members of the class of politicians are
members of the class of liars that is, that
there is no overlap between the two classes. To
represent this claim, we shade the portion of the
two circles that overlaps as shown above. No
politicians are liars.
31Venn Diagrams IV
In logic, the statement Some politicians are
lairs means There exists at least one
politician and that politician is a liar. To
diagram this statement, we place an X in that
part of the politicians circle that overlaps with
the liars circle.
32Venn Diagrams IV
A similar strategy is used with statements of the
form Some S are not P. In logic, the statement
Some politicians are not liars means At least
one politician is not a liar. To diagram this
statement we place an X in that part of the
politicians circle that lies outside the liars
circle.
33Claims about single individuals
- Claims about single individuals, such as
Aristotle is a logician, can be tricky to
translate into standard form. Its clear that
this claim specifies a class, logicians, and
places Aristotle as a member of that class. The
problem is that categorical claims are always
about two classes, and Aristotle isnt a class.
(We couldnt talk about some of Aristotle being a
logician.) What we want to do is treat such
claims as if they were about classes with exactly
one member.
34Claims about single individuals II
- One way to do this is to use the term people who
are identical with Aristotle, which of course
has only Aristotle as a member. - Claims about single individuals should be treated
as A-claims or E-claims. - Aristotle is a logician can be translated into
All people identical with Aristotle are
logicians. - Individual claims do not only involve people.
For example, Fort Wayne is in Indiana is All
cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in
Indiana.
35Two important things to remember about Some
Statements
- In categorical logic, some always means at
least one. - Some statements are understood to assert that
something actually exists. Thus, some mammals
are cats is understood to assert that at least
one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat.
By contrast, all or no statements are not
interpreted as asserting the existence of
anything. Instead, they are treated as purely
conditional statements. Thus, All snakes are
reptiles asserts that if anything is a snake,
then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes
and that all of them are reptiles.
36Exercises
- Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements.
In some cases, you may need to rephrase the
statements slightly to put them in one of the
four standard forms. - No apples are fruits.
- Some apples are not fruits.
- All fruits are apples.
- Some apples are fruits.
37Translating into standard categorical form
- Do people really go around saying things like
some fruits are not apples? Not very often.
But although relatively few of our everyday
statements are explicitly in standard categorical
form, a surprisingly large number of those
statements can be translated into standard
categorical form.
38Common Stylistic Variants of All S are P
- Example
- Every S is P. Every dog is an animal.
- Whoever is an S is a P. Whoever is a
bachelor is a male. - Any S is a P. Any triangle is a
geometrical figure. - Each S is a P. Each eagle is a bird.
- Only P are S. Only Catholics are popes.
- Only if something is a Only if something is
a dog - P is it an S. is it a cocker
spaniel. - The only S are P. The only tickets
available are tickets for cheap
seats. -
39ONLY
- Pay special attention to the phrases containing
the word only in that list. (Only is one of
the trickiest words in the English language.)
Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject
and the predicate terms must be reversed if the
statement begins with the words only or only
if. Thus, Only citizens are voters must be
rewritten as All voters are citizens, not All
citizens are voters. And, Only if a thing is
an insect is it a bee must be rewritten as All
bees are insects, not All insects are bees.
40Common Stylistic Variants of No S are P
- Example
- No S are P. No cows are reptiles.
- S are not P. Cows are not reptiles.
- Nothing that is an S Nothing that is a
known - is a P. fact is a mere opinion.
- No one who is an S No one who is a
Republican - is a P. is a Democrat.
- All S are non-P. If anything is a plant,
then it is not a mineral.
41Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are P
- Example
- Some P are S. Some students are men.
- A few S are P. A few mathematicians are
- poets.
- There are S that are P. There are monkeys that
are - carnivores.
- Several S are P. Several planets in the solar
system are gas giants. - Many S are P. Many students are hard
workers. - Most S are P. Most Americans are
carnivores.
42Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are not P
- Example
- Not all S are P. Not all politicians are
liars. - Not everyone who is Not everyone who is a
- an S is a P. politician is a liar.
- Some S are non-P. Some philosophers are non
Aristotelians. - Most S are not P. Most students are not
binge drinkers. - Nearly all S are Nearly all students are not
- not P. cheaters.
43Paraphrasing
- The process of casting sentences that we find in
at ext into one of these four forms is
technically called paraphrasing, and the ability
to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal
with statements logically. - In the processing of paraphrasing we designate
the affirmative or negative quality of a
statement principally by using the words no or
not. We indicate quantity, meaning whether we
are referring to the entire class or only a
portion of it, by using words all or some.
In addition, we must render the subject and the
predicate as classes of objects with the verb
is or are as the copula joining the halves.
44Paraphrasing II
- We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming
the sentences if need be, to determine the parts
of the sentence, the group that is meant, and
even what noun is being modified. - The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is
not always obvious. For example, if you think
for a moment about the claim I always get
nervous when I take logic exams, youll see its
a claim about times. Its about getting nervous
and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but
it pertains directly to times or occasions. The
proper translation of the example is All times I
take logic exams are times that I get nervous.
45- Once our statement is translated into proper
form, we can see it implications to other forms
of the statement. For example, if we claim All
scientists are gifted writers, that certainly
implies that Some scientists are gifted
writers, but we cannot logically transpose the
proposition to All gifted writers are
scientists. In other words, some statements
would follow, others would not. - To help determine when we can infer one statement
from another and when there is disagreement,
logicians have devised tables that we can refer
to if we get confused.
46Distribution
- Thus, by the definition of distributed term, S
is distributed and P is not. In other words for
any (A) proposition, the subject term, whatever
it may be, is distributed and the predicate term
is undistributed.
47(No Transcript)
48No S are P
- No S are P states that the S and P class are
separate, which may be represented as follows
This statement makes a claim about every member
of S and every member of P. It asserts that
every member of S is separate from every member
of P, and also that every member of P is separate
from every member of S. Both the subject and the
predicate terms of universal negative (E)
propositions are distributed.
49Some S are P
- The particular affirmative (I) proposition states
that at least one member of S is a member of P.
If we represent this one member of S that we are
certain about by an asterisk, the resulting
diagram looks like this
Since the asterisk is inside the P class, it
represents something that is simultaneously an S
and a P in other words, it represents a member
of the S class that is also a member of the P
class. Thus, the statement Some S are P makes
a claim about one member (at least) of S and also
one member (at least) of P, but not about all
members of either class. Thus, neither S or P is
distributed.
50Some S are not P
- The particular negative (O) proposition asserts
that at least one member of S is not a member of
P. If we once again represent this one member of
S by an asterisk, the resulting diagram is as
follows
Since the other members of S may or may not be
outside of P, it is clear that the statement
Some S are not P does not make a claim about
every member of S, so S is not distributed. But,
as may be seen from the diagram, the statement
does assert that the entire P class is separated
from this one member of the S that is outside
that is, it does make a claim about every member
of P. Thus, in the particular negative (O)
proposition, P is distributed and S is
undistributed.
51Two mnemonic devices for distribution
- Unprepared Students Never Pass
- Universals distribute Subjects.
- Negatives distribute Predicates.
- Any Student Earning Bs Is Not On Probation
- A distributes Subject.
- E distributes Both.
- I distributes Neither.
- O distributes Predicate.
52The Traditional Square of Opposition
- Quality, quantity, and distribution tell us what
standard-form categorical propositions assert
about their subject and predicate terms, not
whether those assertions are true. Taken
together, however, A, E, I, and O propositions
with the same subject and predicate terms have
relationships of opposition that do permit
conclusions about truth and falsity. In other
words, if we know whether or not a proposition in
one form is true or false, we can draw certain
valid conclusions about the truth or falsity of
propositions with the same terms in other forms.
53Traditional Square of Opposition II
- There are four ways in which propositions may be
opposed-as contradictories, contraries,
subcontraries, and subalterns.
54(No Transcript)
55Contradictories
- Two propositions are contradictories if one is
the denial or negation of the other that is, if
they cannot both be true and cannot both be false
at the same time. If one is true, the other must
be false. If one is false, the other must be
true. - A propositions (All S is P) and O propositions
(Some S is not P), which differ in both quantity
and quality, are contradictories.
56Contradictories II
- All logic books are interesting books.Some logic
books are not interesting books. - Here we have two categorical propositions with
the same subject and predicate terms that differ
in quantity and quality. One is an A proposition
(universal and affirmative). The second is an O
proposition (particular and negative). - Can both of these propositions be true at the
same time? The answer is "no." If all logic books
are interesting, than it can't be true that some
of them are not. Likewise, if some of them are
not interesting, then it can't be true that all
of them are. - Can both propositions be false at the same time?
Again, the answer is "no". If it's false that all
logic books are interesting, then it must be true
that some of them are not interesting. Likewise
if it's false that some of them are not
interesting, then all of them must be
interesting. - Like this pair, all A and O propositions with the
same subject and predicate terms are
contradictories. One is the denial of the other.
They can't both be true or false at the same
time.
57Contradictories III
- E propositions (No S is P) and I propositions
(Some S is P) likewise differ in quantity and
quality and are contradictories. - Example No presidential elections are contested
elections. Some presidential elections are
contested elections. - Here again we have two categorical propositions
with the same subject and predicate terms that
differ in both quantity and quality. In this
case, the first is an E propositionuniversal and
negativeand the second is an I
propositionparticular and positive. - Can both be true at the same time? The answer is
"no." If no presidential elections are contested,
then it can't be true that some are. Likewise is
some are contested, then it can't be true that
none are.
58Contradictories IV
- Can both be false at the same time? Again the
answer is "no." If it's false that no
presidential elections are contested, then it
must be true that some of them are. Likewise if
it's false that some are contested, then it must
be the case that none are. - Like this pair, all E and I propositions with the
same subject and predicate terms are
contradictories. One is the denial of the other.
They can't both be true or false at the same
time.
59Contraries
- Two propositions are contraries if they cannot
both be true that is, if the truth of one
entails the falsity of the other. If one is true,
the other must be false. But if one is false, it
does not follow that the other has to be true.
Both might be false. - A (All S is P) and E (No S is P)
propositions-which are both universal but differ
in quality-are contraries unless one is
necessarily (logically or mathematically) true. - For example
- All books are written by Stephen King.
- No books are written by Stephen King.
- Both are false.
60Subcontraries
- Two propositions are subcontraries if they cannot
both be false, although they both may be true. - I (Some S is P) and O (Some S is not P)
propositions-which are both particular but differ
in quality-are subcontraries unless one is
necessarily false. - For example
- Some dogs are cocker spaniels.
- Some dogs are not cocker spaniels.
61Subalternation
- Subalternation is the relationship between a
universal proposition (the superaltern) and its
corresponding particular proposition (the
subaltern). - According to Aristotelian logic, whenever a
universal proposition is true, its corresponding
particular must be true. Thus if an A proposition
(All S is P) is true, the corresponding I
proposition (Some S is P) is also true. Likewise
if an E proposition (No S is P) is true, so too
is its corresponding particular (Some S is not
P). The reverse, however, does not hold. That is,
if a particular proposition is true, its
corresponding universal might be true or it might
be false.
62Subalternation II
- For example All bananas are fruit. Therefore,
some bananas are fruit. - Or, no humans are reptiles. Therefore, some
humans are not reptiles. - However, we cant go in reverse. We cant say
some animals are not dogs. Therefore, no animals
are dogs. - Or, some guitar players are famous rock
musicians. Therefore, all guitar players are
famous rock musicians.
63Conversion
- The first kind of immediate inference, called
conversion, proceeds by simply interchanging the
subject and predicate terms of the proposition. - Conversion is valid in the case of E and I
propositions. No women are American
Presidents, can be validly converted to No
American Presidents are women. - An example of an I conversion Some politicians
are liars, and Some liars are politicians are
logically equivalent, so by conversion either can
be validly inferred from the other.
64Conversion II
- One standard-form proposition is said to be the
converse of another when it is formed by simply
interchanging the subject and predicate terms of
that other proposition. Thus, No idealists are
politicians is the converse of No politicians
are idealists, and each can validly be inferred
from the other by conversion. The term
convertend is used to refer to the premise of an
immediate inference by conversion, and the
conclusion of the inference is called the
converse.
65Conversion III
- Note that the converse of an A proposition is not
generally valid form that A proposition. - For example All bananas are fruit, does not
imply the converse, All fruit are bananas. - A combination of subalternation and conversion
does, however, yield a valid immediate inference
for A propositions. If we know that "All S is P,"
then by subalternation we can conclude that the
corresponding I proposition, "Some S is P," is
true, and by conversion (valid for I
propositions) that some P is S. This process is
called conversion by limitation.
66Conversion IV
- Convertend A proposition All IBM computers are
things that use electricity. Converse A
proposition All things that use electricity are
IBM computers. - Convertend A proposition All IBM computers are
things that use electricity. Corresponding
particular I proposition Some IBM computers
are things that use electricity. Converse (by
limitation) I proposition Some things that use
electricity are IBM computers. - The first part of this example indicates why
conversion applied directly to A propositions
does not yield valid immediate inferences. It is
certainly true that all IBM computers use
electricity, but it is certainly false that all
things that use electricity are IBM computers. - Conversion by limitation, however, does yield a
valid immediate inference for A propositions
according to Aristotelian logic. From "All IBM
computers are things that use electricity" we
get, by subalternation, the I proposition "Some
IBM computers are things that use electricity."
And because conversion is valid for I
propositions, we can conclude, finally, that
"Some things that use electricity are IBM
computers."
67Conversion V
- The converse ofSome S is not P, does not yield
an valid immediate inference. - Convertend O proposition Some dogs are not
cocker spaniels.Converse O proposition Some
cocker spaniels are not dogs. - This example indicates why conversion of O
prepositions does not yield a valid immediate
inference. The first proposition is true, but its
converse is false.
68Conversion Table
Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men.
Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men.
69Obversion
- Obversion - A valid form of immediate inference
for every standard-form categorical proposition.
To obvert a proposition we change its quality
(from affirmative to negative, or from negative
to affirmative) and replace the predicate term
with its complement. Thus, applied to the
proposition "All cocker spaniels are dogs,"
obversion yields "No cockerspaniels are nondogs,"
which is called its "obverse." The proposition
obverted is called the "obvertend."
70Obversion II
- The obverse is logically equivalent to the
obvertend. Obversion is thus a valid immediate
inference when applied to any standard-form
categorical proposition. - The obverse of the A proposition "All S is P" is
the E proposition "No S is non-P." - The obverse of the E proposition "No S is P" is
the A proposition "All S is non-P."
71Obversion III
- The obverse of the I proposition "Some S is P" is
the O proposition "Some S is not non-P." - The obverse of the O proposition "Some S is not
P" is the I proposition "Some S is non-P." - Obvertend A-proposition All cartoon characters
are fictional characters. Obverse
E-proposition No cartoon characters are
non-fictional characters. - Obvertend E-proposition No current sitcoms are
funny shows. Obverse A-proposition All current
sitcoms are non-funny shows.
72Obversion IV
- Obvertend I-proposition Some rap songs are
lullabies. Obverse O-proposition Some rap
songs are not non-lullabies. - Obvertend O-proposition Some movie stars are
not geniuses. Obverse I-proposition Some movie
stars are non-geniuses.
73Obversion V
- As these examples indicate, obversion always
yields a valid immediate inference. - If every cartoon character is a fictional
character, then it must be true that no cartoon
character is a non-fictional character. - If no current sitcoms are funny, then all of them
must be something other than funny. - If some rap songs are lullabies, then those
particular rap songs at least must not be things
that aren't lullabies. - If some movie stars are not geniuses, than they
must be something other than geniuses.
74Contraposition
- Contraposition is a process that involves
replacing the subject term of a categorical
proposition with the complement of its predicate
term and its predicate term with the complement
of its subject term. - Contraposition yields a valid immediate inference
for A propositions and O propositions. That is,
if the proposition - All S is P is true, then its contrapositive
- All non-P is non-S is also true.
75Contraposition II
- For example
- Premise
- A proposition All logic books are interesting
things to read. - Contrapositive
- A proposition All non interesting things to read
are non logic books.
76Contraposition III
- The contrapositive of an A proposition is a valid
immediate inference from its premise. If the
first proposition is true it places every logic
book in the class of interesting things to read.
The contrapositive claims that any
non-interesting things to read are also non-logic
bookssomething other than a logic bookand
surely this must be correct.
77Contraposition IV
- Premise
- I-proposition Some humans are non-logic
teachers. - Contrapositive
- I-proposition Some logic teachers are not human.
- As this example suggests, contraposition does
not yield valid immediate inferences for I
propositions. The first proposition is true, but
the second is clearly false.
78Contraposition V
- E premise
- No dentists are non-graduates.
- The contrapositive is No graduates are
non-dentists. - Obviously this is not true.
79Contraposition VI
- The contrapositive of an E proposition does not
yield a valid immediate inference. This is
because the propositions "No S is P" and "Some
non-P is non-S" can both be true. But in that
case "No non-P is non-S," the contrapositive of
"No S is P," would have to be false. - A combination of subalternation and
contraposition does, however, yield a valid
immediate inference for E propositions. If we
know that "No S is P" is true, then by
subalternation we can conclude that the
corresponding O proposition, "Some S is not P,"
is true, and by contraposition (valid for O
propositions) that "Some non-P is not non-S" is
also true. This process is called contraposition
by limitation.
80Contraposition VII
- Premise
- E-proposition No Game Show Hosts are Brain
Surgeons. - Contrapositive
- E proposition No non-Brain Surgeons are non-Game
show hosts. - Premise
- E proposition No game show hosts are brain
surgeons. - Corresponding particular O proposition Some game
show hosts are not brain surgeons. - Contrapositive
- O proposition Some non-brain surgeons are not
non-game show hosts.
81Contraposition VIII
- The first part of this example indicates why
contraposition applied directly to E propositions
does not yield valid immediate inferences. Even
if the first proposition is true then the second
can still be false. This may be hard to see at
first, but if we take it apart slowly we can
understand why. The first proposition, if true,
clearly separates the class of game show hosts
from the class of brain surgeons, allowing no
overlap between them. It does not, however, tell
us anything specific about what is outside those
classes. But the second proposition does refer to
the areas outside the classes and what it says
might be false. It claims that there is not even
one thing outside the class of brain surgeons
that is, at the same time, a non-game show host.
But wait a minute. Most of us are neither brain
surgeons nor game show hosts. Clearly the
contrapositive is false.
82Contraposition IX
- Contraposition by limitation, however, does yield
a valid immediate inference for E propositions
according to Aristotelian logic. By
subalternation from the first proposition we get
the O proposition "Some game show hosts are not
brain surgeons." And then by contraposition,
which is valid for O propositions, we get the
valid, if tongue-twisting O proposition, "Some
non-brain surgeons are not non-game show hosts."
83Contraposition X
- O proposition.
- Premise
- Some flowers are not roses.
- Some non-roses are not non-flowers.
- This is valid. Thus we can see that
contraposition is a valid form of inference only
when applied to A and O propositions.
Contraposition is not valid at all for I
propositions and is valid for E propositions only
by limitation.
84Contraposition XI
Table of Contraposition Table of Contraposition
Premise Contrapositive
A All S is P. A All non-P is non-S.
E No S is P. O Some non-P is not non-S. (by limitation)
I Some S is P. Contraposition not valid.
O Some S is not P. Some non-P is not non-S.
85Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions
- Aristotelian logic suffers from a dilemma that
undermines the validity of many relationships in
the traditional Square of Opposition.
Mathematician and logician George Boole proposed
a resolution to this dilemma in the late
nineteenth century. This Boolean interpretation
of categorical propositions has displaced the
Aristotelian interpretation in modern logic.
86Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions II
- The source of the dilemma is the problem of
existential import. A proposition is said to have
existential import if it asserts the existence of
objects of some kind. I and O propositions have
existential import they assert that the classes
designated by their subject terms are not empty.
But in Aristotelian logic, I and O propositions
follow validly from A and E propositions by
subalternation. As a result, Aristotelian logic
requires A and E propositions to have existential
import, because a proposition with existential
import cannot be derived from a proposition
without existential import.
87Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions III
- A and O propositions with the same subject and
predicate terms are contradictories, and so
cannot both be false at the same time. But if A
propositions have existential import, then an A
proposition and its contradictory O proposition
would both be false when their subject class was
empty. - For example
- Unicorns have horns. If there are no unicorns,
then it is false that all unicorns have horns and
it is also false that some unicorns have horns.
88Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions IV
- The Boolean interpretation of categorical
propositions solves this dilemma by denying that
universal propositions have existential import.
This has the following consequences - I propositions and O propositions have
existential import. - A-O and E-I pairs with the same subject and
predicate terms retain their relationship as
contradictories. - Because A and E propositions have no existential
import, subalternation is generally not valid. - Contraries are eliminated because A and E
propositions can now both be true when the
subject class is empty. Similarly, subcontraries
are eliminated because I and O propositions can
now both be false when the subject class is
empty.
89Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions V
- Some immediate inferences are preserved
conversion for E and I propositions,
contraposition for A and O propositions, and
obversion for any proposition. But conversion by
limitation and contraposition by limitation are
no longer generally valid. - Any argument that relies on the mistaken
assumption of existence commits the existential
fallacy.
90Existential Import and the Interpretation of
Categorical Propositions VI
- The result is to undo the relations along the
sides of the traditional Square of Opposition but
to leave the diagonal, contradictory relations in
force.
91Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions
- The relationships among classes in the Boolean
interpretation of categorical propositions can be
represented in symbolic notation. We represent a
class by a circle labeled with the term that
designates the class. Thus the class S is
diagrammed as shown below
92Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions II
- To diagram the proposition that S has no members,
or that there are no Ss, we shade all of the
interior of the circle representing S, indicating
in this way that it contains nothing and is
empty. To diagram the proposition that there are
Ss, which we interpret as saying that there is
at least one member of S, we place an x anywhere
in the interior of the circle representing S,
indicating in this way that there is something
inside it, that it is not empty.
93Symbolism and Diagrams for Categorical
Propositions III
- To diagram a standard-form categorical
proposition, not one but two circles are
required. The framework for diagramming any
standard-form proposition whose subject and
predicate terms are abbreviated by S and P is
constructed by drawing two intersecting circles
94(No Transcript)
95(No Transcript)
96(No Transcript)
97Claims about single individuals
- Claims about single individuals, such as
Aristotle is a logician, can be tricky to
translate into standard form. Its clear that
this claim specifies a class, logicians, and
places Aristotle as a member of that class. The
problem is that categorical claims are always
about two classes, and Aristotle isnt a class.
(We couldnt talk about some of Aristotle being a
logician.) What we want to do is treat such
claims as if they were about classes with exactly
one member.
98Claims about single individuals II
- One way to do this is to use the term people who
are identical with Aristotle, which of course
has only Aristotle as a member. - Claims about single individuals should be treated
as A-claims or E-claims. - Aristotle is a logician can be translated into
All people identical with Aristotle are
logicians. - Individual claims do not only involve people.
For example, Fort Wayne is in Indiana is All
cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in
Indiana.
99Two important things to remember about Some
Statements
- In categorical logic, some always means at
least one. - Some statements are understood to assert that
something actually exists. Thus, some mammals
are cats is understood to assert that at least
one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat.
By contrast, all or no statements are not
interpreted as asserting the existence of
anything. Instead, they are treated as purely
conditional statements. Thus, All snakes are
reptiles asserts that if anything is a snake,
then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes
and that all of them are reptiles.
100Exercises
- Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements.
In some cases, you may need to rephrase the
statements slightly to put them in one of the
four standard forms. - No apples are fruits.
- Some apples are not fruits.
- All fruits are apples.
- Some apples are fruits.
101Translating into standard categorical form
- Do people really go around saying things like
some fruits are not apples? Not very often.
But although relatively few of our everyday
statements are explicitly in standard categorical
form, a surprisingly large number of those
statements can be translated into standard
categorical form.
102Common Stylistic Variants of All S are P
- Example
- Every S is P. Every dog is an animal.
- Whoever is an S is a P. Whoever is a
bachelor is a male. - Any S is a P. Any triangle is a
geometrical figure. - Each S is a P. Each eagle is a bird.
- Only P are S. Only Catholics are popes.
- Only if something is a Only if something is
a dog - P is it an S. is it a cocker
spaniel. - The only S are P. The only tickets
available are tickets for cheap
seats. -
103ONLY
- Pay special attention to the phrases containing
the word only in that list. (Only is one of
the trickiest words in the English language.)
Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject
and the predicate terms must be reversed if the
statement begins with the words only or only
if. Thus, Only citizens are voters must be
rewritten as All voters are citizens, not All
citizens are voters. And, Only if a thing is
an insect is it a bee must be rewritten as All
bees are insects, not All insects are bees.
104Common Stylistic Variants of No S are P
- Example
- No S are P. No cows are reptiles.
- S are not P. Cows are not reptiles.
- Nothing that is an S Nothing that is a
known - is a P. fact is a mere opinion.
- No one who is an S No one who is a
Republican - is a P. is a Democrat.
- All S are non-P. If anything is a plant,
then it is not a mineral.
105Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are P
-
- Some P are S.
- A few S are P.
- There are S that are P.
- Several S are P.
- Many S are P.
- Most S are P.
106Common Stylistic Variants of Some S are not P
-
- Not all S are P.
- Not everyone who is
- an S is a P.
- Some S are non-P.
- Most S are not P.
- Nearly all S are
- not P.
107Paraphrasing
- The process of casting sentences that we find in
at ext into one of these four forms is
technically called paraphrasing, and the ability
to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal
with statements logically. - In the processing of paraphrasing we designate
the affirmative or negative quality of a
statement principally by using the words no or
not. We indicate quantity, meaning whether we
are referring to the entire class or only a
portion of it, by using words all or some.
In addition, we must render the subject and the
predicate as classes of objects with the verb
is or are as the copula joining the halves.
108Paraphrasing II
- We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming
the sentences if need be, to determine the parts
of the sentence, the group that is meant, and
even what noun is being modified. - The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is
not always obvious. For example, if you think
for a moment about the claim I always get
nervous when I take logic exams, youll see its
a claim about times. Its about getting nervous
and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but
it pertains directly to times or occasions. The
proper translation of the example is All times I
take logic exams are times that I get nervous.
109- Once our statement is translated into proper
form, we can see it implications to other forms
of the statement. For example, if we claim All
scientists are gifted writers, that certainly
implies that Some scientists are gifted
writers, but we cannot logically transpose the
proposition to All gifted writers are
scientists. In other words, some statements
would follow, others would not. - To help determine when we can infer one statement
from another and when there is disagreement,
logicians have devised tables that we can refer
to if we get confused.
110Conversion Table
Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men.
Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men.
Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men.
111Syllogisms
- Syllogism a deductive argument in which a
conclusion is inferred from two premises. - In a syllogism we lay out our train of reasoning
in an explicit way, identifying the major premise
of the argument, the minor premise, and the
conclusion. - The major premise consists of the chief reason
for the conclusion, or more technically, it is
the premise that contains the term in the
predicate of the conclusion. - The minor premise supports the conclusion in an
auxiliary way, or more precisely, it contains the
term that appears in the subject of the
conclusion. - The conclusion is the point of the argument, the
outcome, or necessary consequence of the premise.
112Syllogisms II
- Example in an argumentative essay
- In determining who has committed war crimes we
must ask ourselves who has slaughtered unarmed
civilians, whether as reprisal, ethnic
cleansing, terrorism, or outright genocide.
For along with pillaging, rape, and other
atrocities, this is what war crimes consist of .
In the civil war in the former Yugoslavia,
soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army committed
hundreds of murders of this kind. They must
therefore be judged guilty of war crimes along
with the other awful groups in our century, most
notably the Nazis.
113Syllogisms III
- The conclusion to this argument is that soldiers
in the Bosnian Serb army are guilty of war
crimes. The premises supporting the conclusion
are that slaughtering unarmed civilians is a war
crime, and soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army have
slaughtered unarmed civilians. The following
syllogism will diagram this argument. - All soldiers who slaughter unarmed civilians are
guilty of war crimes. - Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are soldiers who
slaughter unarmed civilians
- Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are guilty of war
crimes.
114Enthymeme
- Enthymeme - An argument that is stated
incompletely, the unstated part of it being taken
for granted. An enthymeme may be the first,
second, or third order, depending on whether the
unstated proposition is the major premise, the
minor premise, or the conclusion of the argument.
- Enthymemes traditionally have been divided into
different orders, according to which part of the
syllogism is left unexpressed.
115Enthymeme II
- A first order enthymeme is one in which the
syllogisms major premise is not stated. - For example, suppose someone said, We must
expect to find needles on all pine trees they
are conifers after all. Once we recognize this
as an enthymeme we must provide the unstated
(major) premise, namely, All conifers have
needles. Then we need to paraphrase the
statements and arrange them in a syllogism,
indicating by parentheses which one we added was
not in the text - (All conifers are trees that have needles.)
- All pine trees are conifers.
- All pine trees are trees that have needles.
116Enthymeme III
- A second - order enthymeme is one in which only
the major premise and the conclusion are stated,
the minor premise being suppressed. - For example, Of course tennis players arent
weak, in fact, no athletes are weak. Obviously,
the missing premise is Tennis players are
athletes, so the syllogism would appear this
way. - No athletes are weak.
- (All tennis players are athletes.)
- No tennis players are weak.
117Enthymeme IV
- A third order enthymeme is one in which both
premises are sated, but the conclusion is left
unexpressed. - For example, All true democrats believe in
freedom of speech, but there are some Americans
who would impose censorship on free expression.
The reader is left to draw the conclusion that
some Americans are not true democrats. The
syllogism - All true democrats are people who believe in
freedom of speech. - Some Americans are not people who believe in
freedom of speech. - (Some Americans are not true democrats.)
118Exercises
- No certainty should be rejected. So, no
self-evident propositions should be rejected. - Some beliefs about aliens are not rational, for
all rational beliefs are proportional to the
available evidence. - John is a member of the police force and all
policemen carry guns.
119Validity and Truth
- No matter how diligent we are in constructing our
argument in proper form, our conclusion can still
be mistaken if the conclusion does not strictly
follow from the premises, that is, if the logic
is not sound. - For example,
- All fish are gilled creatures.
- All tuna are fish.
- All tuna are gilled creatures.
- This seems correct.
120Validity and Truth II
- But suppose we want to claim that all tuna are