Title: Chapter 8: Organ Transplants and Medical Resources
1Chapter 8 Organ Transplants and Medical Resources
2Major ethical issues
- As with many other bioethical issues raised in
this book, the existence of those issues has
resulted because of the development of new
medical technologies. - In some cases, one of the ethical questions that
might be raised is whether the technology should
be used at all. - This has been true in the cases of genetic
testing, in vitro fertilization, and human
cloning, for example. With each of these
technologies some have challenged the very idea
of using them.
3Major ethical issues
- But this is not the case with organ transplants.
The practice is widespread and widely accepted.
Nonetheless, it too raises ethical concerns,
three of which are emphasized in this chapter - (a) Who should receive transplanted organs and on
what basis should the decision be made? - (b) Under what conditions should organ donations
be allowed and accepted? - (c) How should organ transplants be allocated?
4Some facts about organ transplants
- The first organs to be transplanted were kidneys
beginning in the 1950s - Worldwide, more than 200,000 kidney transplants
have been performed, and about 94 percent of the
organs are still functioning one year later. - Â
- Over the last twenty years the list of organs
that are transplanted has grown to include
corneas, bone marrow, bone and skin, livers,
lungs, pancreases, intestines, and hearts. - A kidney transplant may cost about 40,000, a
heart transplant about 150,000, and a liver
transplant in the range from 200,000 to
300,000.
5Some facts about organ transplants
- Kidney donors face odds of 1 in 20,000 of dying
from surgical complications, but the risk of
dying as a result of having only one kidney is
extremely small. - People with one kidney are slightly more likely
to develop high blood pressure than those with
two. No long-term studies of kidney donors have
been done. - The immunosuppressive drugs needed to prevent
rejection of a transplanted organ cost from
10,000 to 20,000 a year, and they must be taken
for the remainder of the patients life. - Medicare, Medicaid, and most, but not all,
insurance companies pay for organ transplants and
at least part of the continuing drug and
treatment costs.
6Some facts about organ transplants
- The End- Stage Renal Disease Program covers
kidney transplants for everyone, yet people
needing any other sort of transplant who dont
qualify for public programs and lack appropriate
insurance must find some way of raising the
money. - About 25,000 people a year receive transplants at
the nations 278 transplant centers, but about
10,000 more die while waiting for organs. - At any given time, about 100,000 people are on
the transplant waiting list.
7Some facts about organ transplants
- Each year, 35,00040,000 additional people
register to get organs. For each organ
transplanted, three more people sign up, and
those on the waiting list die at a rate of ten a
day. - According to one estimate, between 6900 and
10,700 potential organ donors are available, but
for various reasons only about 37 to 57 percent
of potential donors become actual donors. - At a time when the need for donors is increasing,
their actual number is decreasing. The number of
live donors began to decline in 2004. - Organ donations are regulated by the federal
Uniform Anatomical Gift Act of 1984 which has
also served as a model for state laws virtually
all states have enacted laws to promote the
increase of organ donation.
8Some facts about organ transplants
- Despite such laws, transplant centers have been
reluctant to intrude on a familys grief by
asking that a deceased patients organs be
donated. Even if a patient has signed an organ
donation card, the permission of the immediate
family is required, in most cases, before the
organs can be removed. - The 1984, National Organ Transplantation Act made
the sale of organs for transplant illegal in the
United States. At least twenty other countries,
including Canada, Britain, and most of Europe,
have similar laws. - Sixty-nine procurement organizations, operating
in federally defined geographical regions,
collect organs from donors and transport them to
the 278 hospitals with transplant facilities. A
procurement agency may be paid about 25,000 for
its services.
9Some facts about organ transplants
- Hospitals pay for the organs they receive, but
they pass on their costs. Hospitals charge, on
average, 16,000 to 18,000 for a kidney or a
heart and 20,000 to 22,000 for a liver. - According to one study, hospitals may mark up the
cost of an organ by as much as 200 percent to
cover costs that patients are unable to pay or
that exceed the amount the government will
reimburse. - Organs are distributed in the US through the
federally funded United Network for Organ Sharing
also apply (UNOS).
10Section 1 Who Deserves Transplant Organs?
- Section 3 focuses on how the scarcity of organ
transplants raises questions about their fair
distribution. - This section looks at another aspect of that
scarcity. Because of the life-giving function
transplanted organs can potentially provide,
together with their scarcity, such organs acquire
extraordinary value. - The strength of this value leads to the companion
idea that any organ recipient should be deserving
of it.
11Section 1 Who Deserves Transplant Organs?
- For example, should a confessed serial killer on
death row be entitled to a transplant? - Or, if there is choice between a death row serial
killer and a crimeless mother of three children,
is the killer as deserving as the mother? - For many people the answer is an obvious no to
both questions but decisions about who deserves a
transplant are more complicated than the examples
suggest, as the readings in this section make
clear.
12Reading Wanted, Dead or Alive? Kidney
Transplantation in Inmates Awaiting
ExecutionJacob M. Appel
- Jacob Appel argues that death-row inmates should
be allowed to be candidates for kidney
transplants. - Although the state has determined that the inmate
does not deserve to live, it would be wrong for a
medical decision to lower his quality of life
while he is waiting for execution. - Also, if the inmate was wrongly convicted,
denying him a transplant would result in the
irreversible suffering of an innocent person.
13Reading Wanted, Dead or Alive? Kidney
Transplantation in Inmates Awaiting
ExecutionJacob M. Appel
- Appel also argues that the life expectancy of a
death-row inmate is different in kind from the
natural one used in kidney allocation, so the
inmates life expectancy should not be considered
relevant to a transplant decision. - Finally, Appel points out, a kidney transplant
costs less than dialysis, so the money saved
could be used to meet other health care needs.
14Reading The Prisoners Dilemma Should Convicted
Felons Have the Same Access to Heart
Transplantation as Ordinary Citizens?Robert M.
SadeÂ
- Robert Sade claims that the answer to whether an
inmate should receive a heart transplant depends
on who is asked. - Physicians and organ procurement and distribution
agencies are obligated to consider prisoners
eligible for a transplant, just because they are
human beings. - For a transplant center, however, the question of
payment arises it needs to be paid by the prison
system. - But for most prison systems, heart transplants
are almost certainly too expensive to provide
without cutting back on other needs. - Thus, in Sades view, prisoners should be denied
transplants so that other prison expenses can be
covered.
15Reading Alcoholics and Liver TransplantationCarl
Cohen, Martin Benjamin, and the Ethics and
Social Impact Committee of the Transplant and
Health Policy Center, Ann Arbor, Michigan
- The authors examine the moral and medical
arguments for excluding alcoholics as candidates
for liver transplants and conclude that neither
kind of argument justifies a categorical
exclusion. - The moral argument holds that alcoholics are
morally blameworthy for their condition. Thus,
when resources are scarce, it is preferable to
favor an equally sick non-blameworthy person over
a blameworthy one. - The authors maintain that if this argument were
sound, it would require physicians to examine the
moral character of all patients before allocating
scarce resources. But this is not feasible, and
such a policy could not be administered fairly by
the medical profession.
16Reading Alcoholics and Liver TransplantationCarl
Cohen, Martin Benjamin, and the Ethics and
Social Impact Committee of the Transplant and
Health Policy Center, Ann Arbor, Michigan
- The medical argument holds that because of their
bad habits, alcoholics have a lower success rate
with transplants. - Hence, scarce organs should go to others more
likely to benefit. The authors agree that the
likelihood of someones following a treatment
regimen should be considered, but they maintain
that the consideration must be given case by
case. - We permit transplants in cases where the
prognosis is the same or worse, and the
categorical exclusion of alcoholics is unfair. We
cannot justify discrimination on the grounds of
alleged self-abuse, unless we are prepared to
develop a detailed calculus of just deserts for
health care based on good conduct.
17Section 2 Acquiring Transplant Organs
- While, in the future, vital human organs might be
grown in a non-human organism or in vitro, at
the present time all organs must be procured from
other humans, either alive or recently dead. - This fact raises the question under what
circumstances is it ethically acceptable to
harvest a persons organs? - Where the donor has recently died the answer may
seem simple if the deceased or an authorized
family member has consented, the harvesting is
unobjectionable. - But, as discussed in the chapter on euthanasia,
the definition of death has become more
problematic because of advances in life-support
technology. Â
18Section 2 Acquiring Transplant Organs
- For example, suppose a patient is still breathing
but is also brain dead. Is the patient dead
enough to make harvesting, say, his heart
morally acceptable? - In addition, where there is no question that a
patient is dead, not to harvest healthy organs
can be viewed as a morally objectionable waste. - Should we not, then, as suggested in the article
Conscription of Cadaveric Organs for
Transplantation Lets at Least Talk About It,
make use of cadaveric organs even if it is
contrary to the deceased, or his relatives,
wishes? - In the case where the organ donor is alive,
different ethical issues arise.
19Section 2 Acquiring Transplant Organs
- Because the donor is alive and intends to remain
alive, we are not considering the extraordinary
case where the person is willing to see himself
killed in order to make his organs available.
(This would be homicide.) - Â
- This means that the kinds of organs that may be
harvested are ones either that can regenerate
(for example, liver lobes) or where the patient
has more than one of the organ and can live with
only one (most frequently, the kidneys). - It is widely accepted that a donor must consent
to harvesting any of his organs otherwise we are
violating his autonomy.
20Section 2 Acquiring Transplant Organs
- The major ethical question concerns whether the
fact that a person wants to have an organ
harvested is sufficient justification for
granting his wish. - On the one hand, some argue that not allowing the
person to do so is a violation of his autonomy
(provided he has consented and understands the
risks involved). The organ does, after all,
belong to the person. - On the other hand, there are those who believe
that, at best, the permissible circumstances
should be severely circumscribed.
21Section 2 Acquiring Transplant Organs
- The primary worry here is that, although the sale
of organs is prohibited in all countries,
promoting the idea that the decision to donate is
primarily up to the donor encourages the view
that transplant organs are simply commodities
which can be bought and sold on the open market. - This can lead to the exploitation of the poor and
degrades human dignity. Â
22Reading The Donors Right to Take a RiskRonald
Munson
- Ronald Munson asks whether, given the risk to
themselves, we should permit people to donate a
liver lobe and whether, by operating on a donor
for the benefit of a recipient, surgeons are
violating the dictum Do no harm. - He claims that, while autonomy warrants consent,
we must take measures to guarantee that consent
is both informed and freely given. - So far as benefit is concerned, Munson maintains,
when consent is valid, living donors can be
viewed as benefiting themselves, as well as the
recipients of their gift.
23Reading The Case for Allowing Kidney SalesJanet
Radcliffe-Richards, A. S. Daar, R. D. Guttmann,
R. Hoffenberg, I. Kennedy, M. Lock, R. A. Sells,
N. Tilney, and the International Forum for
Transplant Ethics
- The authors argue that although some may feel
disgust at the idea of selling kidneys, this is
not a sufficient reason to deny people a
necessary treatment. - Â
- The authors critically examine the objections
that kidney sales would exploit the poor, benefit
the rich unfairly, undermine confidence in
physicians, threaten the welfare of women and
children in societies that treat them as chattel,
and lead to the sale of hearts and other vital
organs. - Â
- The authors hold that until stronger objections
are offered, the presumption should be in favor
of kidney sales as a way of resolving the current
shortage.
24Reading Refuse to Support the Illegal Organ
TradeKishore D. Phadke and Urmila Anandh
- The authors observe that, although organ sales
are prohibited in all countries, society in
general has shifted toward regarding transplant
organs as commodities that can be bought. - In developing countries like India, laws against
organ sales are not enforced and the practice has
popular support. - The authors call for the medical profession to
refuse to be a part of this unscrupulous trade,
which exploits the poor, discourages altruistic
giving, commercializes the body, and undercuts
human dignity.
25Conscription of Cadaveric Organs for
Transplantation Lets at Least Talk About
ItAaron Spital and Charles A. Erin
- The authors observe that the scarcity of
transplant organs results in the death of many
people who could be saved and that a major
barrier to acquiring organs is the refusal of
families of the recently dead to donate their
organs. - The authors argue for the adoption of a new
policythe conscription of organs. All usable
organs should be taken, without consent, and used
for transplantation. - Â
- Spital and Erin address objections and defend the
view that consent is not ethically required and
that conscription, which can save lives, is
ethically preferable to all current and proposed
practices.
26Section 3 Allocation Principles
- Transplanted organs are, today, a scarce
resource. That is, there is a greater demand for
the organs than there is a supply of them. - This is not peculiar to transplanted organs it
is true of many things we want and is certainly
true of other medical resources such as stays in
hospitals, surgical operations, MRIs, diagnostic
laboratory tests, in vitro fertilization,
bone-marrow transplants blood transfusions,
genetic screening, respirators, etc. - Scarcity means that choices have to be made as to
who will and will not receive those organs that
are available. Those organs (or any scarce
resource) must therefore be rationed.
27Section 3 Allocation Principles
- There are four major ways this may be done
(discussed in greater detail in the reading The
Prostitute, the Playboy, and the Poet Rationing
Schemes for Organ Transplantation in this
section). - Â
- The Market allow organs to be sold and bought in
the marketplace at a price. - Â
- The market decides who receives the organs and
what the persons qualification must be. Quite
simply, the organs go to who can afford them. - A Committee a hospital committee made up medical
professionals and other stakeholders decides on
who qualifies. - Either explicit criteria or committee member
judgment is the basis for selection. - Â
28Section 3 Allocation Principles
- A Lottery organ recipients are selected
blindly on a random basis. - Selection of recipients depends totally on
chance. - By customary practice selection of candidates is
made on the basis of understood practice among
medical professionals. - Either explicit criteria or medical professional
judgment is the basis for selection. - Allocation may, of course, be based on some
combination of these approaches. - Framing an acceptable method of selection raises
the fundamental question Is the method fair and
what criteria of fairness should be employed? The
articles in this chapter explore this issue.
29Reading The Prostitute, the Playboy, and the
Poet Rationing Schemes for Organ
TransplantationGeorge J. Annas
- The author takes a position on transplant
selection that introduces a modification of the
first-come, first-served principle. - He reviews four approaches to rationing scarce
medical resourcesmarket, selection committee,
lottery, and customaryand finds that each has
disadvantages so serious as to make them all
unacceptable. - An acceptable approach, he suggests, is one that
combines efficiency, fairness, and a respect for
the value of life. - Because candidates should both want a transplant
and be able to derive significant benefits from
one, the first phase of selection should involve
a screening process that is based exclusively on
medical criteria that are objective and as free
as possible of judgments about social worth.
30Reading The Prostitute, the Playboy, and the
Poet Rationing Schemes for Organ
TransplantationGeorge J. Annas
- Since selection might still have to be made from
this pool of candidates, it might be done by
social-worth criteria or by lottery. - However, social-worth criteria seem arbitrary,
and a lottery would be unfair to those who are in
more immediate need of a transplantones who
might die quickly without it. - After reviewing the relevant considerations, a
committee operating at this stage might allow
those in immediate need of a transplant to be
moved to the head of a waiting list. To those not
in immediate need, organs would be distributed in
a first-come, first-served fashion. - Although absolute equality is not embodied in
this process, the procedure is sufficiently
flexible to recognize that some may have needs
that are greater (more immediate) than others.