Title: Animal Rights
1Animal Rights
2Direct vs. Indirect duties towards animals
- Direct duties duties owed to the animals
themselves (treating animals welfare as an
intrinsic good) - Indirect duties duties to act in certain ways
towards animals for the sake of ourselves, others
or society (treating animal welfare as an
instrumental good)
3- Examples of indirect duties towards animals
- Duty to respect private property (animals that
belong to someone) - Duty to avoid cruelty because it encourages a
cruel nature in us, which might then be expressed
towards other people - Duty not to hurt the feelings of people who love
animals by abusing animals - Duty to maintain the health of biosystems and
nature in general, for our own good - Duty to preserve beautiful creatures, for the
enjoyment of others and future generations - Duty to preserve species that may be sources of
other instrumental goods, e.g. medicine
4Ethical status for animals
- Animal welfare as an intrinsic good
- Kantian and utilitarian ethics traditionally
extended to all - people, but only people
- Kant all rational beings are ends in themselves
- assumption only humans are rational (or maybe
humans, angels and extraterrestrials) - Utilitarianism the pleasures and pains of all
conscious beings are of equal importance - assumption (?) only humans are conscious/have
pleasure and pain - But note Jeremy Bentham, early utilitarian
(pre-Mill) - The question is not, Can they reason?, nor Can
they talk? - but, Can they suffer? (Bentham 1789)
5Peter Singer
- Contemporary Australian philosopher
-
- Professor of bioethics at Princeton
- Preference utilitarian
- Famous advocate of animal rights
- Animal Liberation (1975)
- All Animals are Equal (1989) (and humans are
animals)
6Animal Liberation
- Singer sees ethics as evolving.
- In the past, slaves, women and people of other
races were often not treated as persons, and
their interests were not given consideration. - Now we recognize all people as persons and extend
equal consideration to all people. - Now we should extend equal ethical consideration
to animals as well.
7Speciesism
- Discrimination against animals is speciesism,
analogous to racism - To discriminate on the basis of species
membership, or even on the basis of intelligence
or rationality, is like discriminating on the
basis of skin color - What matters is sentience. Any animal that is
sentient (can feel pleasure or pain) counts as a
moral subject. - All pleasure or pain, or preferences, should
count equally, whether they are the pleasures of
preferences of humans or animals
8The argument from borderline cases
- Borderline cases babies, the severely mentally
- retarded, psychopaths
- Argument from analogy borderline cases are
similar to (some) animals (in terms of abilities,
sentience, capacity for pleasure and pain), so
animals should be treated similarly - We routinely grant importance to the interests to
human borderline cases not full rights (e.g.
the right to vote), but the right to have their
preferences treated as morally important and the
right not to be mistreated - Animals are not equal to normal adults, and
therefore cannot have truly equal rights, but
their preferences (e.g. the desire to avoid pain)
should be given equal consideration
9Equal consideration, not equal rights
- We dont discriminate between people on the basis
of intelligence or ability. So we should not
discriminate against animals because they are
less intelligent or lack certain abilities. - We treat babies and the severely brain damaged
better than we treat animals, but we shouldnt.
Animals have just as much right to consideration
as babies (or more!) E.g. an adult ape is more
aware, more self-directing and has at least as
much capacity for suffering as a baby.
10Implications
- Pro vegetarian taking away a life for a
insignificant benefit (satisfying a persons
tastes) is unjustified. Although, Singer allows
that it is possible to raise animals ethically
for food, if they are raised to have a pleasant
and enjoyable life. An animal without a life plan
does not suffer from death, and a happy animal
can be replaced by another happy animal without
net loss to the world. - Anti-vivisection the utilitarian arguments we
raise to justify using animals this way would not
be accepted as justification for human
vivisection, and therefore are not accepted for
the case of animals either (except in extreme
cases).
11Implications (cont.)
- Individual animals have moral standing, not
species or biosystems. - Thus, killing two common deer would be a greater
sin than - killing one endangered tiger.
- An animals rights are potentially as important
as a humans. - Where to draw the line? At sentience. Where is
the borderline of sentience? Singers guess
between the clam and the shrimp.
12Tom Regan
- Contemporary American Philosopher
- Deontologist, in the tradition of Kant
- Specialist in animal rights
- The Case for Animal Rights (1983)
- Animal Rights, Human Wrongs (1980)
13Animal Rights
- Utilitarians are wrong to focus only on pleasure
and pain. - What is important is respecting the dignity of
others, and to treat those with moral standing as
ends in themselves, not means (c.f. Kant). - What is wrong with eating veal, for example, is
not that the animal suffers, rather
the fundamental wrong is the system that allows
us to view animals as our resources, here for us,
to be eaten, or surgically manipulated, or put in
our cross hairs for sport or money.
14Moral Standing
- Distinguishes moral agents from moral
patients - Moral agents typified by competent human adults
- Moral patients include everything that has
interests, e.g. babies, the mentally incompetent
and animals. - Both moral agents and moral patients have moral
standing, i.e. are ends of themselves and are
subject to rights - What has interests?
- Subjects-of-a-life.
15Subjects-of-a-life
- To be the subject-of-a-life involves more than
merely being alive and more than merely being
conscious. To be the subject-of-a-life is to
have beliefs and desires perception, memory, and
a sense of the future, including their own
future an emotional life together with feelings
of pleasure and pain preference and
welfare-interests a psychophysical identity
over time and an individual welfare in the sense
that their experiential life fares well or ill
for them, independent of their utility for
others. - Not all animals, but only animals that meet these
criteria.
Typically mentally normal mammals of a year or
more, although potentially other animals with
the relevant cognitive capacity.
16Implications
- The following violate animals rights
- Raising animals for food or fur
- Hunting for sport or money
- Keeping pets
- Keeping animals in circuses or zoos
- Vivisection
- Like Singer, holds that only individuals have
moral standing, not species or biosystems. - More inclusive than Singer as to what causes harm
to animals e.g. pets, raising well-cared-for
animals for food, keeping happy animals in a zoo,
etc. - Not as inclusive as Singer as to which animals
matter mostly only mammals of over a year old
compared to everything that is at least as
sentient as a shrimp
17Against rights for animal
- Carl Cohen
- Contemporary American philosopher
- Theoretical rights are reciprocal, among moral
agents or members of a community of moral agents - Practical
- Medical research
- Animals in the wild
18Medical research
- Animal used for vaccines, treatments, of human
diseases, e.g. polio, malaria - But this research would not be allowed if animals
had rights - Rights entail duties
- Rights trump interests absolutely
19Rights trump duties
- Regan agrees
- The harms others might face as a result of the
dissolution of some practice or institution is
no defense of allowing it to continue. . . . No
one has a right to be protected against being
harmed if the protection in question involves
violating the rights of others. . . . No one has
a right to be protected by the continuation of an
unjust practice, one that violates the rights of
others. . . . Justice must be done, though the .
. . heavens fall. (Regan, The Case for Animal
Rights, 1983) - On the rights view, we cannot justify harming a
single rat merely by aggregating the many human
and humane benefits that flow from doing it. . .
. Not even a single rat is to be treated as if
that animal's value were reducible to
his possible utility relative to the interests of
others. (Regan, The Case for Animal Rights, 1983)
20Animals in the wild
- If animals have rights, we have the duty to
protect those rights, even in the wild. - But this is impossible. And undesirable.
- Should we protect prey from predators? Should we
inoculate wild animals from disease? Should we
shoot some members of overpopulated herds (e.g.
deer) to prevent mass starvation? How can we
judge between competing interests/rights? Would
we want to?
21Other objections to Singer and Regan
- Cohens objection is that rights for animal is
too inclusive only humans should count. - Other argue that Singer and Regan are not
inclusive enough should include all animals,
maybe even plants (Goodpaster anything alive
should have moral standing) - Ironically animal rights is criticized as being
essentially anthropocentric still maintains
that only persons count, but some animals count
as persons - What about species, biosystems, larger ecological
systems?
22Readings
- Thomas Nagel (1974), What is it like to be a
bat?, The Philosophical Review, LXXXIII, 4
(October 1974), 435-50 at http//organizations.ut
ep.edu/Portals/1475/nagel_bat.pdf