Title: Proof a historical perspective
1Proof a historical perspective
2References
- Harel, G., Sowder, L (in press). Toward a
comprehensive perspective on proof, In F. Lester
(Ed.), Second Handbook of Research on Mathematics
Teaching and Learning, National Council of
Teachers of Mathematics. http//www.math.ucsd.edu/
harel/downloadablepapers/TCPOLTOP.pdf - Kleiner, I. Movshovitz-Hadar, N. (1997). Proof
A many-splendoured thing, The Mathematical
Intelligencer, 19 (3), 16-26. - Kleiner, I. (1991). Rigor and Proof in
Mathematics A Historical Perspective,
Mathematics Magazine, 64 (5), pp. 291-314. - History topics
- http//www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/history/Index
es/HistoryTopics.html
3Some phases in development of the concept of proof
- Pre-Greek math
- Egyptian mathematics 4000-3500 BC
- Babylonian mathematics 2000-1600 BC
- (computational procedures, no symbols)
- Greek math 600 BC 200 BC (deductive
reasoning) - Thales (-600), Pythagoras (-500), Euclid (-300),
Aristotle (-300), Apollonius (-200) - Syria, Iran, India (200-1100 AC) (preservation
and development of the Greek tradition of proof) - Omar Khayyam (1100), Adelard and Fibonacci
(1100) brought math knowledge from Islamic
countries and Greeks back to Europe - Renaissance (16-17th centuries)
- Vieta, Descartes, Leibnitz (symbolic algebra)
- The calculus of Caushi and Weierstrass (19th
century) (rigorization of calculus, genetic
definitions) - Formalism, logicism, intuisionism (20th century)
- Hilbert, Zermelo, Fraenkel, Guedel,
- Computer-based proofs, probabilistic proofs
(1970-)
4Pre-Greek vs. Greek math
- Pre-Greek mathematics concerned actual physical
entities and measurements (method empirical or
perceptual reasoning) - Geeks the entities under investigation are
idealizations of experiential spatial realities
(method logical deductions, terms without
definitions - primary propositions propositions
that should be proved)
5Motives of Greek mathematics
- The crisis caused by Pythagoreans proof of
incommensurability of the diagonal and side of
the square - The desire to decide among contradictory results
from past civilizations (e.g., debate about Pi,
paradox of Zeno) - The nature of Greek society
- The need to teach
6Debates on Greek math(16th century)
- Proposition I.32 in Euclids Elements
- In any triangle, if one of the sides is
produces, then the exterior angle equals the sum
of the two interior and opposite angles, and the
sum of the three interior angles of the triangles
equals two right angles. -
- Aristotles definition of science We suppose
ourselves to possess unqualified scientific
knowledge of a thing,, unless we think that we
know the cause on which the fact depends as the
cause of the fact and of no other. THE IDEA OF
CAUSE AND EFFECT - Implications 1) mathematics is not a science
in Aristotles meaning - 2) Proof by contradiction is meaningless and
should be removed from mathematics - 3) Proofs by exhaustion by Archimedes is
unsatisfactory as it is not causal (Rivaltus,
1615) -
7Additional motives for re-conceptualization of
Greek mathematics in 16th century
- Greeks paid no attention to the operations
underlying spatial configurations, there were
many problems without solutions (e.g., trisection
of an angle) - Vieta and Leibniz creation of algebraic
notation proof is a sequence of sentences
beginning with identities and proceeding by a
finite number of steps of logic and rules of
definitional substitution - It is hardly an exaggeration to say that the
calculus of Leibniz brings within the range of an
ordinary student problems that once required the
ingenuity of an Archimedes or a Newton (Edwards,
1979)
8An example Leibniz proof of the product rule
for differentiation
- d(xy)(xdx)(ydy)-xyxyxdyydxdxdy-xyxdyydx
- since the quantity dxdyis infinitely small in
comparison with the rest, and hence can be
discarded (Leibniz, cited in Edwards, 1979)
9An additional example Euler
Now let n be an infinitely large integer and z an
infinitely small number
The above equation becomes
Let nzx, which is a finite since n is infinitely
large and z infinitely small. Finally,
10Errors were made!
- Example Euler proved that
- (counterexample was given by Schwarz)
- Russel vs. Cantor
11Motives for re-conceptualization of mathematics
in 19th century
- Attempts to establish a consistent foundation for
mathematics one that is free from paradoxes - In both situations Greeks vs. 16th century and
16th vs. 19th century, crises had developed
which threatened the security of mathematics and
in both cases resorts was taken to explicit
axiomatic statement of the foundations upon which
one hoped to build without fear of further
charges of inconsistency - Like the Greek mathematicians, the modern
mathematicians had only one model in mind, albeit
a different model (Wilder, 1967)
12Greek vs. modern mathematics
13Logicism, formalism and intuitionism (Early 20th
century)
- Logicism The notion of proof its scope and
limits a subject of study by mathematicians.
Mathematics is a part of logic (Peano). - Formalism Mathematics is a study of axiomatic
systems. Mathematics is about symbols to which no
meaning is to be attached! (Hilbert) - Intuitionism No formal analysis of axiomatic
systems is necessary. Mathematics should not be
founded on the system of axioms, the
mathematicians intuition will guide him in
avoiding contradictions. Proofs must be
constructive (Brouwer).
14Israel Kleiner
- 1) Most research mathematicians do not take any
course in formal logic! The logicism is not
widespread among mathematicians. - 2) The debate among formalists and intuitionists
is still unresolved, but most mathematicians
are untroubled, at least, in their daily work,
about the debates concerning the various
philosophies of mathematics
15Computer-based and probabilistic proofs
- Appel and Haken (1976) computer-aided proof of
the four-color theorem verification of 1482
confiducations. Thousands of pages of computer
programs that were not published - Michael Rabin 2400-593 is a prime number, the
statement has a small probability of error - Some have argued that there is no essential
difference between probabilistic and
deterministic proofs. Both are convincing
arguments. Both are to be believed with some
probability of error (Kleiner, 1991)