Title: Grammar as Choice
1Grammar as Choice?
- Conflict, concord, optimality
2Choice
- Grammar involves Multi-criterion Decision Making
- Similar problems arise in cognitive psychology
(Gigerenzer, Kahneman, Tversky), economics
(Arrow), neural networks (Smolensky), politics,
operations research, and so on. - Many factors interact to determine the form of
words, phrases, sentences, - They need not be remotely in agreement about the
best outcome or course of action.
3The Three Pillars of Decision
- What are the alternatives?
- from which one must choose.
- What are the criteria?
- which evaluate the alternatives.
- How do the many criteria combine into a single
decision? - given pervasive conflict among them.
4Alternatives
- The generative stance the alternatives are
actions - They modify, structure, re-structure, or preserve
an input - As a result, an output is defined.
- The choice is among different (In,Out) pairings.
5An Example
- The Regular Past Tense of English
- Spelled Pronounced Observed Suffix
- massed mæst -t
- nabbed næbd -d
- patted pæt?d -?d
6An Example
- The Regular Past Tense of English
- Spelled Pronounced Observed Suffix
- massed mæst -t
- nabbed næbd -d
- patted pæt?d -?d
7An Example
- The Regular Past Tense of English
- Spelled Pronounced Observed Suffix
- massed mæst -t
- nabbed næbd -d
- patted pæt?d -?d
- ? No overlap in distribution of suffix variants
8An Example
- The Regular Past Tense of English
- Spelled Pronounced Observed Suffix
- massed mæst -t
- nabbed næbd -d
- patted pæt?d -?d
- ? No overlap in distribution of suffix variants
- ? Suffix variants highly similar phonetically
9An Example
- The Regular Past Tense of English
- Spelled Pronounced Observed Suffix
- massed mæst -t
- nabbed næbd -d
- patted pæt?d -?d
- ? No overlap in distribution of suffix variants
- ? Suffix variants highly similar phonetically
- ? Choice of variant entirely predictable on
general grounds
10Regular Past Tense Suffix
11Regular Past Tense Suffix
d
12Regular Past Tense Suffix
d
Similarity ? Identity There is just
one suffix /d/
13Lexical Representation
- Lexical Representation
- massed mæsd
- nabbed næbd
- patted pætd
- Relations Elementary Actions
- d ? d nil
- d ? t devoice
- d ? -?d insert
14Dilemmas of Action
- Reluctance
- ? voi ? voi doesnt remove all b,d,gs from
the language - Ø ? ? doesnt spray schwas into every
crevice - Compliance
- Faithful reproduction of input not possible
- mæsd, pætd
- ? Action is taken only to deal with such problems
- Choices, choices
- Insertion solves all problems. Yet we dont
always do it. - mæs?d is entirely possible (cf. placid)
15The Two Classes of Criteria
- Markedness. Judging the outcome. e.g.
- Diff(voi). (Final) Obstruent clusters may not
differ in voicing. - pd, bt, td, ds, zt, etc.
- Gem. Adjacent consonants may not be identical.
- tt, dd, bb, in pronunciation
- ?This analysis follows Bakovic 2004.
- Faithfulness. Judging the action.
- InputOutput in a certain property
- Every elementary action is individually
proscribed e.g. - NoDevoicing.
- NoInsertion.
- NoDeletion.
16The Two Classes of Criteria
- Markedness. Judging the outcome. e.g.
- Diff(voi). (Final) Obstruent clusters may not
differ in voicing. - pd, bt, td, ds, zt, etc.
- Gem. Adjacent consonants may not be identical.
- tt, dd, bb, in pronunciation
- ?This analysis follows Bakovic 2004.
- Faithfulness. Judging the action.
- InputOutput in a certain property
- Every elementary action is individually
proscribed e.g. - NoDevoicing.
- NoInsertion.
- NoDeletion.
17The Two Classes of Criteria
- Markedness. Judging the outcome.
- Demands compliance with output standards
- Faithfulness. Judging the action.
- Enforces reluctance to act
18Penalties
- Constraints assess only penalties
- no rewards for good behavior
- Actions are reluctant because constraints on
action always favor inaction by penalizing
change. - Actions happen because constraints on outcome
force violation of constraints against action.
19Conflicts Abound
- The faithfulness constraints disagree among
themselves - And MDiff disagrees with FNoDevoicing.
20Conflicts Abound
- The faithfulness constraints disagree among
themselves
? W marks preference for desired winner ? L
preference for desired loser
21Conflicts Abound
- The faithfulness constraints disagree among
themselves - And MDiff disagrees with FNoDev.
22All Conflicts Resolved
- Impose a strict priority order gtgt on the set of
constraints - Here Gem, Diff gtgt NoIns gtgtNoDel
- In any pairwise comparison of x vs. y
- x ? y x is better than y
- iff the highest-ranked constraint
distinguishing x from y - prefers x.
- Optimal. x is optimal iff x ? y for every y
- y violationwise distinct from x
23Lexicographic
- Better Than, ? lexicographic order on the
alternatives. - Sort by the highest ranked constraint
- If it does not decide, on to the next highest.
- And so on.
- Like sorting by first letter (able lt baker)
- and then the next, if that doesnt decide
(aardvarkltabacus) - and then the next (azimuth lt azure), and so on.
- Or ordering numerals by place
- 100 lt 200 119 lt 130 2235 lt 2270
24Optimality Theory
- Alternatives.
- A set of (input,output) pairs.
- A given input is matched with every possible
output. - Criteria.
- A set of constraints, of two species
- Markedness judging outcomes
- Faithfulness judging actions
- Collective judgment.
- Derives from a strict prioritization of the
constraint set. - Imposes lexicographic order on alternatives. Take
the best.
25Universality
- To make maximal use of theoretical resources
- and minimal commitment to extraneous devices,
assume - Fixed.
- The set of alternatives is universal.
- Fixed.
- The set of constraints is universal.
- Varying.
- Languages differ freely in the ranking of the
constraint set.
26Harmonic Ascent?
- Getting better all the time
27Beyond Replication
- Faithful mapping InOut
- nabbed næbd ? næbd
- What does it take to beat the faithful candidate?
- Moreton 2002, 2004 asks and answers this
question. - Fully Faithful ?x?x? satisfies every F
constraint. - Nothing can do better than that on the Fs.
- Nonfaithful ?x?y? beats faithful ?x?x? iff
- The highest ranked constraint distinguishing them
- prefers ?x?y?
28Beyond Replication
- Faithful mapping InOut
- nabbed næbd ? næbd
- What does it take to beat the faithful candidate?
- Moreton 2002, 2004 asks and answers this
question. - Fully Faithful ?x?x? satisfies every F
constraint. - Nothing can do better than that on the Fs.
- Nonfaithful ?x?y? beats faithful ?x?x? iff
- The highest ranked constraint distinguishing them
- prefers ?x?y?
29Triumph of Markedness
- That decisive constraint must be a Markedness
constraint. - Since every F is happy with the faithful
candidate.
30Triumph of Markedness
- That decisive constraint must be a Markedness
constraint. - Since every F is happy with the faithful
candidate.
31Harmonic Ascent Markedness Descent
- For a constraint hierarchy H, let HM be the
subhierarchy of Markedness constraints within it. - If Ha ? f, for f fully faithful, then HM a ? f
- If things do not stay the same, they must get
better. - Analysis and results due to Moreton 2002, 2004.
32Markedness Rating by HM
- M Diff(voi) gtgt MVoi
- pt, bd (0) pt (0)
- bd (2)
- bt, pd (1) bt, pd (1)
Good
Bad
? Note lexicographic refinement of classes
Constraints from Lombardi 1999
33Markedness-Admissible Mappings
Good
Bad
? Where you stop the ascent, and if you can,
depends on HF.
34Utterly Impossible Mappings
Good
Bad
35Consequences of Harmonic Ascent
- No Circular Shifts in MF/OT
- Shifts that happen
- Western Basque (Kirchner 1995)
- a ? e alabaa ? alabea
- e ? i semee ? semie
- Catalan (Mascaró 1978, Wheeler 1979)
- nt ? n kuntent ? kunten
- n ? Ø plan ? pla
- ? Analyzed recently in Moreton Smolensky 2002
36? No Circular Shifts
- Harmonic Ascent
- Any such shift must result in betterment
vis-Ã -vis HM. - The goodness order imposed on alternatives is
- Asymmetric NOT a ?b b ?a
- Transitive a ?b b ?c ? a ?b
- Cant have
- x ? y
- y ? z
- z ? x
- Such a cycle would give x ? x (contradiction!)
37Way Up ? Way Down
Good
Bad
38Shift Data
- Large numbers exist
- Moreton Smolensky collect 35 segmental cases
- 3 doubtful, 4 inferred 28 robustly evidenced.
- One potential counterexample
- Taiwanese/ Xiamen Tone Circle
- See Yip 2002, Moreton 2002, and many others for
discussion.
39Coastal Taiwanese Tone Shifts
Diagram from Feng-fan Hsieh, http//www.ling.nthu
.edu.tw/teal/TEAL_oral_FengFan_Hsieh.pdf
40Not the True Article?
- No basis in justifiable Markedness for shifts
(Yip). - Paradigm Replacement
- Moreton 2002. Yip 1980, 2002. Chen 2002.
Mortensen 2004. Hsieh 2004. Chen 2000. -
41? No Endless Shifts
42? No Endless Shifts
- NO x ? y ?z ? ?
- E.g Add one syllable to input
43? No Endless Shifts
- NO x ? y ?z ? ?
- E.g Add one syllable to input
- Because constraints only penalize,
- there is an end to getting better.
44? No Endless Shifts
- NO x ? y ?z ? ?
- E.g Add one syllable to input
- Because constraints only penalize,
- there is an end to getting better.
- This is certainly a correct result.
- we can add one syllable to hit a fixed target
(e.g. 2 sylls.) - not merely to expand regardless of shape of
outcome.
45Conclusions
- Harmonic Ascent and its consequences nontrivial,
since mod of theory can easily eliminate. E.g.
Antifaithfulness. - Design of the theory succeeds in taking property
of atomic components (single M constraint) and
propagating it to the aggregate judgment. - Requires transitive, asymmetric order,
commitment to penalization, strict limitation to
M F constraints.
46Concord?
47Constraints in conflict
48Constraints in conflict
49Constraints in conflict
50Constraints need not conflict
51Constraints need not conflict
52Constraints need not conflict
53Constraints need not conflict
54Constraints need not conflict
55Constraints need not conflict
56Constraints need not conflict
57Constraints need not conflict
58Constraints need not conflict
59Constraints and Scales
- Imagine a goodness scale a ? b ? c ? d
60Abstract Scale
better
61Constraints and Scales
- a ? b ? c ? d
- Consider every bifurcation good ? bad
-
- abc ? d B1 d
- ab ? cd B2 c,d
- a ? bcd B3 (b,c,d
62B1
better
63B2
better
64B3
better
65Binary Constraints in Stringency Relation
66Generating Conflations
- From B1, B2, B3 any respectful coarsening of the
scale - may be generated
- B1 B2 ab ? c ? d
- i.e., abc ?d ab?cd
- B2 B3 a ? b ? cd
- i.e., ab?cd a ?bcd
- B1 B2 B3 a ? b ? c ? d and so on
67Generating Conflations
- From B1, B2, B3 any respectful coarsening of the
scale - may be generated
- B1 B2 ab ? c ? d
- i.e., abc ?d ab?cd
- B2 B3 a ? b ? cd
- i.e., ab?cd a ?bcd
- B1 B2 B3 a ? b ? c ? d and so on
68Generating Conflations
- From B1, B2, B3 any respectful coarsening of the
scale - may be generated
- B1 B2 ab ? c ? d
- i.e., abc ?d ab?cd
- B2 B3 a ? b ? cd
- i.e., ab?cd a?bcd
- B1 B2 B3 a ? b ? c ? d and so on
69Generating Conflations
- From B1, B2, B3 any respectful coarsening of the
scale - may be generated
- B1 B2 ab ? c ? d
- i.e., abc ?d ab?cd
- B2 B3 a ? b ? cd
- i.e., ab?cd a ?bcd
- B1 B2 B3 a ? b ? c ? d and so on
70B1 B2
better
71Full DNC on 4 candidates
?These Do Not Conflict ?
72Full DNC on 4 candidates
73Full DNC on 4 candidates
? B1 B2 T12
74B1 B2
better
75Ecological Examples Abound
- Positional Faithfulness vs. general Faithfulness
- Id/Ovoi vs. Idvoi
- be faithful to voicing in Onset vs. be
faithful to voicing -
- Contextual Markedness vs. Less so
- VoicedGemObstruent vs. VoicedObstruent
- (s? vs. ?
- Natural featural subset/superset relations
- hi vs. -low i,u vs. i,u,e,o
- Relations arising between between constraints
mid-hierarchy as conflict-inducing candidates
drop out.
76Special / General as Stringency
- S/G. Such examples show nonconflicting
constraints tracking the special case/ general
case relationship. - Stringency. We study only the extensional impact
of the relationship, as embodied in violation
profiles. - i.e. in ordinal classes imposed by viol.
profiles. - We dont care about the exact violation
quantities - Constraints form a hierarchy of increasing
stringency, as more and more is rejected.
77Linguistic Scales
- Particularly informative is the relation between
scales of relative sonority and placement of
stress. - This allows us to probe the varying behavior of
similar scales across languages.
78Intrinsic Sonority of vowels
79Sonority-Sensitive Stress
- Main-stress falls in a certain position
- say, 2nd to last syllable xXx
- Except when adjacent vowel has greater sonority
- then the stronger vowel attracts the stress Xxx
- This perturbation evidences the fine structure of
the scale.
80Sonority-Sensitive Stress
- Chukchi (Kenstowicz 1994, Spencer 1999)
- Typically base-final when suffixed xXx
- jará-?a migcirét-?k
- reqokál-g?n wir�-?k
- welól-g?n ekwét-?k
- pi?é-pi? nuté-nut
- But one syll. back when stronger available Xxx
- céri-cer cerÃ-cer egti
- kéli-kel
- wéni-wen
81Sonority-Sensitive Stress
- Schwa yields to any other vowel
- ?tlá
- ??ló
- ?nré
- ??nÃn
- ??nún
- ? a,o, e, i, u gt ?
- But behaves normally with itself
- ?tl?q
- ?tt?m
- k?t??t
- c?m??
- ? ? ?
NB. stress typically avoids the last syllable of
the word.
82Chukchi Scale
- These considerations motivate a scale like this
-
- aeogt iu gt ?
- In terms of goodness of fit wrt stress
-
- áéó ? Ãú ? ?
83Intrinsic Sonority of vowels
84Flattened Chukchi Scale
better
85B1 B2
86Achieving Chukchi
- How does this relate to the full scale that
registers every level of distinction? - To coarsen the scale in the Chukchi fashion,
- we must disable B3 and activate both B1 and B2.
- Ranking will yield this.
87Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
88Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
- Transitivity. Find a constraint C with which they
conflict.
89Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
- Transitivity. Find a constraint C with which they
conflict. - B1, B2 gtgt C
90Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
- Transitivity. Find a constraint C with which they
conflict. - B1, B2 gtgt C gtgt B3
91Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
- Transitivity. Find a constraint C with which they
conflict. - B1, B2 gtgt C gtgt B3
92Ranking?
- How can the Bis be ranked? They dont conflict!
- Transitivity. Find a constraint C with which they
conflict. - B1, B2 gtgt C gtgt B3
- ? Here C demands stress in a certain position
93The Hierarchy
94The Hierarchy
- B1, B2 gtgt POS gtgt B3
- Stress flees from ? to iueoa (B1)
95The Hierarchy
- B1, B2 gtgt POS gtgt B3
- Stress flees from ? to iueoa (B1)
- Stress flees from ?iu to eoa (B2)
96The Hierarchy
- B1, B2 gtgt POS gtgt B3
- Stress flees from ? to iueoa (B1)
- Stress flees from ?iu to eoa (B2)
- The distinction eo/a is ignored (B3)
97The Hierarchy
- B1, B2 gtgt POS gtgt B3
- Stress flees from ? to iueoa (B1)
- Stress flees from ?iu to eoa (B2)
- The distinction eo/a is ignored.
- Conjunctivity.
- Because B1 and B2 do not conflict, their demands
are both met. - see Samek-Lodovici Prince 1999, 21 Favoring
Intersection Lemma
98The Optima
99The Optima
100The Optima
101The Optima
102The Optima
103The Optima
104The Ranking
105Known Conflations
- Kobon (Kenstowicz 1994). a gt e,o gt
i,u gt ö,? - In a final 2 s window, stress the most sonorous,
else initial in window. - Chukchi (K 94) a, e, o gt i,u gt
? - In base-final words, penult stress unless
antepenult is greater on scale. - Nganasan (de Lacy 2002) a, e, o gt
i, ü, u, ?, ? - Penult, except antepenult when a.p. stronger
precedes weaker pen. - Mari (K 94) a, ä, e, o, i, u gt ?
- Rightmost nonfinal full V, else leftmost V.
106Currently Known Conflations
Adapted from de Lacy 2002
107Conclusion
- All types currently attested except B2B3
- Assumptions
- Simplest binary interpretation of scale in
constraints - Free ranking of all constraints, as usual
- Result
- All respectful collapses are generated
- Nonconflict automatically provides a theory of
scales in OT
108Optimality?
109Here Comes Everybody
- Alternatives. Come in multitudes.
- But many rankings produce the same optima.
- Not all constraints conflict
- Extreme formal symmetry to produce all possible
optima - Not often encountered ecologically
110Completeness Symmetry
- Perfect System on 3 constraints.
111Completeness Symmetry
- Perfect System on 3 constraints.
112Completeness Symmetry
- Perfect System on 3 constraints.
113Completeness Symmetry
- Perfect System on 3 constraints.
114Optima and Alternatives
- Limited range of possible optima
- Much, much less than n! for n constraint system
- But there are Alternatives Without Limit.
- Augmenting actions (insertion, adjunction, etc.)
increase size and number of alternatives, no end
in sight. - Where is everybody?
115Harmonic Bounding
- Many candidates almost all can never be
optimal
116Harmonic Bounding
- Many candidates almost all can never be
optimal - Example Profuse insertion
117Harmonic Bounding
- Many candidates almost all can never be
optimal - Example Profuse insertion
Candidate (b) has nothing going for it.
?It is equal to (a) or worse than it on every
constraint
118Harmonic Bounding
- Attempt the overinserted candidate as desired
optimum - It cant win this competition
- no constraint prefers it,
- and one prefers its competitor !
119Harmonic Bounding
- Generically
- If there is no constraint on which a ? ß, for a
? ß violationwise, - no W in the row and at least one L
- then a can never be optimal.
- ß is always better, so a cant be the best
- Even if ß itself is not optimal, or not possibly
optimal ! - e.g. 19 is not the smallest positive number
because 18lt19.
120Harmonic Bounding
- Harmonic Bounding is a powerful effect
- E.g. Almost all insertional candidates are
bounded - This gives us a highly predictive theory of
insertion
121Harmonic Bounding
- Harmonic Bounding is a powerful effect
- E.g. Almost all insertional candidates are
bounded - This gives us a highly predictive theory of
insertion - Even though there are restrictions on insertions
at all in defining the set of possible
alternatives!
122Harmonic Bounding
- Harmonic Bounding is a powerful effect
- E.g. Almost all insertional candidates are
bounded - This gives us a highly predictive theory of
insertion - Even though there are restrictions on insertion
at all in defining the set of possible
alternatives! - But were not done.
- Simple Harmonic Bounding works without ranking
- Any positively weighted combination of violation
scores will show the effect.
123Collective Harmonic Bounding
- A ranking will not exist unless all competitions
- can be won simultaneously
- Neither C1 nor C2 may be ranked above the other
- If C1gtgtC2, then d ? a
- If C2 gtgtC1 then ß ? a
- ß and d cooperate to stifle a
124Collective Harmonic Bounding
- An example from Basic Syllable Theory
125Collective Harmonic Bounding
- An example from Basic Syllable Theory
126Collective Harmonic Bounding
- The middle way is no way.
127General Harmonic Bounding
- Def. Candidate a is harmonically bounded
- by a nonempty set of candidates B, x?B, over a
constraint set S iff for every x?B, and for
every C?S, - if C a?x, then there is a y?B such that
C y?a. - If any member of B is beaten by a on a constraint
C, another member of B comes to the rescue,
beating a. - If any ax earns W, then some ay earns L.
- If B has only one member, then a can never beat
it. - No harmonically bounded candidate can be optimal.
-
128General Harmonic Bounding
- Def. Candidate a is harmonically bounded
- by a nonempty set of candidates B, x?B, over a
constraint set S iff for every x?B, and for
every C?S, - if C a?x, then there is a y?B such that
C y?a. - If any member of B is beaten by a on a constraint
C, another member of B comes to the rescue,
beating a. - If any ax earns W, then some ay earns L.
- If B has only one member, then a can never beat
it. - No harmonically bounded candidate can be optimal.
-
129General Harmonic Bounding
- Def. Candidate a is harmonically bounded
- by a nonempty set of candidates B, x?B, over a
constraint set S iff for every x?B, and for
every C?S, - if C a?x, then there is a y?B such that
C y?a. - If any member of B is beaten by a on a constraint
C, another member of B comes to the rescue,
beating a. - If any ax earns W, then some ay earns L.
- If B has only one member, then a can never beat
it. - No harmonically bounded candidate can be optimal.
-
130Some Stats
- Tesar 1999 studies a system of 10 prosodic
constraints. - with a large number of prosodic systems generated
- Among the 4 syllable alternatives
- ca. 75 are bounded on average
- ca. 16 are collectively bounded (approx. 1/5 of
bounding cases) - Among the 5 syllable alternatives
- ca. 62 are bounded
- ca. 20 are collectively bounded (approx. 1/3 of
bounding cases) - ? Calculated in Samek-Lodovici
Prince 1999
131Some Stats
- Tesar 1999 studies a system of 10 prosodic
constraints. - with a large number of prosodic systems generated
- Among the 4 syllable alternatives
- ca. 75 are bounded on average
- ca. 16 are collectively bounded (approx. 1/5 of
bounding cases) - Among the 5 syllable alternatives
- ca. 62 are bounded
- ca. 20 are collectively bounded (approx. 1/3 of
bounding cases) - ? Calculated in Samek-Lodovici
Prince 1999
132Bounding in the Large
- Simple Harmonic Bounding is Pareto optimality
- An assignment of goods is Pareto optimal or
efficient if theres no way of increasing one
individuals holdings without decreasing somebody
elses. - Likewise, it is non-efficient if someones
holdings can be increased without decreasing
anybody elses. - A simply bounded alternative is
non-Pareto-optimal. We can better its performance
on some constraint(s) without worsening it on any
constraint. - Collective Harmonic Bounding is the creature of
freely permutable lexicographic order. - See Samek-Lodovici Prince 1999 for discussion.
133Intuitive Force of Bounding
- Simple Bounding relates to the need for
individual constraints to be minimally violated. - If we can get (0,0,1,0) we dont care about
(0,0,2,0).
134Intuitive Force of Bounding
- Collective Bounding reflects the taste of
lexicographic ordering for extreme solutions. - If a constraint is dominated, it will accept any
number of violations to improve the performance
of a dominator. - There is no compensation for a high-ranking
violation - If (1,1) meets (0,k), the value of k is
irrelevant.
135Explanation from Bounding
- Bounded alternatives are linguistically
impossible. - Yet their impossibility is not due to a direct
restriction on linguistic structure. - Impossibility follows from the interaction of
constraints under ranking. - Explanation emerges from the architecture of the
theory.
136Grammar as Choice?
- Conclusion, retrospect, overview
137Among the Cognitive Sciences
- Perspectives on cognitive theory tend to
bifurcate
?See esp. Smolenskys work for analysis
138Among the Cognitive Sciences
- OT sits on the left side of every opposition
- But in every case there is currently an active
technical interchange between advocates and
critics leading to new understanding of the
relations between apparent dichotomies. - In psychology of reasoning, e.g., Gigerenzer and
colleagues argue for the use of criteria under
lexicographic order.
139Gigerenzer Goldstein 1996
140Fast and Frugal
- For Gigerenzer et al. the main contrast is with
Bayesian probabilistic calculation over
alternatives. - Lexicographic choice is one reason decision
making - i.e. at the level of deciding between 2
alternatives - Therefore, fast and frugal.
- OT aims for neither speed nor frugality, but
deploys the same mechanism of lexicographic
decision-making
141Looking Both Ways
- OT seeks to explain the basic properties of human
language through a formal theory of the
linguistic faculty. - OT, as a lexicographic theory of ordinal
preference, points toward new kinds of
connections with the cognitive apparatus that
acquires and uses grammatical knowledge. - ?
142Thanks
- Thanks to Vieri Samek-Lodovici, Paul Smolensky,
John McCarthy, Jane Grimshaw, Paul de Lacy,
Alison Prince, Adrian Brasoveanu, Naz Merchant,
Bruce Tesar, Moira Yip.
143Where to learn more about OT
- http//roa.rutgers.edu
- Many researchers have made their work freely
available at the Rutgers Optimality Archive. - Thanks to the Faculty of Arts Sciences, Rutgers
University for support.
144References
- ROA http//roa.rutgers.edu
- Alderete, J. 1999. Morphologically governed
accent in Optimality Theory. ROA-393. - Arrow, K. 1951. Social choice and Individual
Values. Yale. - Bakovic, E. 2004. Partial Identity Avoidance as
Cooperative Interaction. ROA-698. - Chen, M. 2000. Tone Sandhi. CUP.
- de Lacy, Paul. 2002. The Formal Expression of
Markedness. ROA-542. - Gigerenzer, G., P. Todd, and the ABC Research
Group. Simple Heuristics that Make us Smart. OUP. - Gigerenzer, G. and D. Goldstein. 1996. Reasoning
the fast and frugal way Models of bounded
rationality. Psych. Rev. 103, 650-669. - Hsieh, Feng-fan. 2004. Tonal Chain-shifts as
Anti-neutralization-induced Tone Sandhi. In
Proceedings of the 28th Penn Linguistics
Colloquium. http//web.mit.edu/ffhsieh/www/ANTS.pd
f - Kager, R. Optimality Theory. Textbook. CUP.
- Kirchner, 1995. Going the distance synchronic
chain shifts in OT. ROA-66. - Kirchner, Robert. 1996. Synchronic chain shifts
in optimality theory. LI 272 341-350. - Lombardi, L. 1999. Positional Faithfulness and
Voicing Assimilation in Optimality Theory. NLLT
17, 267-302. - Lubowicz, A. 2002. Contrast Preservation in
Phonological Mappings. ROA-554 - Mascaró, J. 1978. Catalan Phonology and the
Phonological Cycle. Ph. D. - dissertation, MIT. Distributed by Indiana
University Linguistics Club.
145References
- McCarthy, J. 2002. A Thematic Guide to Optimality
Theory. CUP. - McCarthy, J., ed. 2004. Optimality Theory in
Phonology. Blackwell. - Moreton, E. 2002, 2004. Non-Computable Functions
in Optimality Theory. ROA-364. Revised, in
McCarthy 2004, pp.141-163. - Moreton, E. and P. Smolensky. 2002. Typological
consequences of local constraint conjunction.
ROA-525. - Mortensen, D. 2004. Abstract Scales in Phonology.
ROA-667. - Prince, A. 1997ff. Paninian Relations.
http//ling.rutgers.edu/faculty/prince.html - Prince, A.2002. Entailed Ranking Arguments.
ROA-500 - Prince, A. 2002. Arguing Optimality. ROA-562.
- Prince, A. and P. Smolensky, 1993/2004.
Optimality Theory Constraint Interaction in
Generative Grammar. Blackwell. ROA-537. - Samek-Lodovici, V. and A. Prince. 1999. Optima.
ROA-363. - Samek-Lodovici, V. and A. Prince. Fundamental
Properties of Harmonic Bounding. RuCCS-TR-71.
http//ruccs.rutgers.edu/tech_rpt/harmonicbounding
.pdf - Smolensky, P and G. Legendre. To appear 2005. The
Harmonic Mind. MIT. - Spencer, A. 1999. Chukchee. http//privatewww.es
sex.ac.uk/spena/Chukchee/chapter2.htmlstress - Wheeler, Max. 1979. Phonology of Catalan.
Blackwell. - Yip, M. 2002. Tone. CUP.
146Grammar as Choice?
- Conflict, concord, optimality