Controversies In Cognition - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 25
About This Presentation
Title:

Controversies In Cognition

Description:

However, much evidence casts doubt on the idea of V4 being the primate brain's colour centre' ... What advantage do primates have over these animals? ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:36
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 26
Provided by: peter953
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Controversies In Cognition


1
Controversies In Cognition
  • Neuropsychology and the evolutionary value of
    colour

2
Aims
  • To identify whether colour vision fits easily
    into Milner and Goodales Two Visual Brains
    Theory .
  • To look at research that suggests that processing
    of colour information provides us with more than
    just the conscious experience of colour.
  • To look at the possible evolutionary benefits of
    colour vision.
  • To present Akins (2000) position on the role of
    colour vision.

3
Objectives
  • To be able to identify whether colour vision fits
    easily into Milner and Goodales Two Visual
    Brains Theory .
  • To be able to describe and discuss research that
    suggests that processing of colour information
    provides us with more than just the conscious
    experience of colour.
  • To be able to describe and discuss the possible
    evolutionary benefits of colour vision.
  • To be able to discuss Akins (2000) position on
    the role of colour vision.

4
Last week
  • We looked at Milner and Goodales Two Visual
    Brains Theory.
  • Neuropsychological evidence provides strong
    support for their theory of visual perception.
  • Using this evidence it should be possible to see
    the way in which the two streams differ in how
    they deal with incoming visual information.
  • However, despite strong support for this theory
    there are still gaps that need clarification.
  • One such gap relates to the role that colour
    processing plays in the ventral and dorsal
    framework.

5
Where does colour fit in?
  • Colour is clearly a key physical property of the
    visual world so it must have a place in Milner
    and Goodales framework.
  • There is some good evidence that colour
    information enters the ventral stream via input
    from the parvocellular (P) channel, which is,
    unlike the magnocellular (M) channel, mainly
    responsible for colour (Livingstone and Hubel,
    1987).
  • Further evidence for the link between colour and
    the ventral stream is that cells in this stream
    are often sensitive to colour (e.g. Zeki, 1980).
  • In addition, visual area V4 has often been
    regarded as the primate brains colour centre
    (e.g. Zeki, 1993) and, as this area is part of
    the ventral stream, this would be good grounds
    for assuming that the ventral stream provides the
    sole basis for the visual experience of colour.

6
Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
  • However, much evidence casts doubt on the idea of
    V4 being the primate brains colour centre.
  • Although Zeki (1973) reported that every one of
    the 77 cells he sampled in region V4 showed
    selectivity to wavelength, more recent evidence
    suggests that many cells in the region are
    strongly receptive to orientation and are even
    indifferent to wavelength (Schein, Marrocco and
    De Monasterio, 1982 Desimone and Schein, 1987).
  • It was also believed that monkeys with surgically
    induced lesions to V4 show major impairments to
    colour discrimination.
  • However, when monkeys with V4 lesions were
    tested, the results suggested only a mild
    impairment (Heywood and Cowey, 1987) or none at
    all (Dean, 1979).

7
Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
  • Furthermore, when luminance and chromaticity were
    carefully controlled on a display monitor for
    monkeys with V4 completely removed, there was no
    evidence of any impairment in colour oddity tasks
    (Heywood, Gadotti and Cowey, 1992).
  • Wild, Butler, Carden and Kulikowski (1985)
    monkeys with damage to V4 retain their colour
    vision (e.g. they can learn to pick up a yellow
    object) but lose colour constancy (the
    phenomenon whereby an objects colour is
    perceived as unvarying or fairly stable despite
    considerable variation in the spectral
    composition of the illuminant (Heywood and
    Cowey, 1999, p.29)) (e.g. they cannot find the
    same yellow object under blue overhead lighting).
  • For humans with damage to an area that straddles
    the temporal and parietal cortices, which may
    correspond to the monkey area V4, there is a
    similar loss of colour constancy though colour
    recognition remains intact (Ruttiger, Braun,
    Gegenfurtner, Petersen, Schonle and Sharpe,
    1999).

8
Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
  • It now seems reasonable to say that V4 is either
    responsible for, or has a crucial role in, colour
    constancy. Its also reasonable to suggest that
    another region (for example, V8) or, more likely,
    several regions in combination, beyond V4 are
    responsible for constructing colour.
  • It still seems likely, though, that the colour
    centre is based within the ventral and not the
    dorsal stream.
  • The link between colour and the ventral stream
    may be an intuitive one because, in the
    terminology of Milner and Goodale, we commonly
    use colour as part of our internal representation
    of the world, plus we are consciously aware of
    it, i.e. we can report on our experience of any
    given colour we see, we can name it and compare
    it with, or distinguish it from, other colours.

9
Is there any neuropsychological evidence for this
assumption?
  • If colour perception could fit easily into
    Goodales and Milners framework then one would
    expect there to be evidence of neuropsychological
    dissociations like those mentioned last week.
  • There are many cases of individuals with impaired
    colour perception resulting from brain damage.
  • Example 1 cerebral achromatopsia.

10
What achromatopsics can do with colour
  • Although they are without an awareness of colour,
    these patients can still somehow use differences
    in wavelength to make certain distinctions of
    form and movement.
  • E.g. patient MS is densely achromatopsic and
    yet can do some tasks involving colours that abut
    each other (Heywood, Cowey, and Newcombe, 1991,
    1994). His verbal replies suggest that he is
    successful in these tasks because he can detect
    edges between stimuli, even though the stimuli
    appear to him to be identical.

11
What achromatopsics can do with colour
  • This ability of MS, to detect chromatically
    generated contours (Heywood, Kentridge, and
    Cowey, 1998a), has also been shown in other
    achromatopsic patients (Barbur, Harlow and Plant,
    1994).
  • MS, and other achromatopsics, can somehow detect
    chromatic information without experiencing the
    colours themselves. These findings suggest that
    at some level, their colour processing remains
    intact. They have no phenomenal experience of
    colour, and yet retain some colour abilities but
    not others.
  • However, cerebral achromatopsia is not
    blindsight for colour (Heywood, Kentridge, and
    Cowey, 1998b).

12
Example 2 Colour Blindsight
  • The blindsight phenomenon suggests that the
    subcortical pathways can carry considerable
    amounts of visual information. Some evidence
    suggests that this may include information about
    colour.
  • Bender and Krieger (1951) Perenin, Ruel, and
    Hecaen (1980) Blythe, Kennard, and Ruddock,
    (1987) Stoerig, (1987) Stoerig and Cowey (1989,
    1992) all reported that wavelength discrimination
    was possible in the blind fields of patients.
  • However, the evidence for colour blindsight is
    still not clear-cut.

13
Colour blindsight (2)
  • E.g. two out of the 10 patients who Stoerig
    (1987) tested failed to reach the .05 level of
    statistical significance, suggesting that this
    residual chromatic processing is not always
    demonstrable and that even when it is it is
    seriously impoverished.
  • Until there is stronger evidence for the reality
    of colour blindsight it may be that it cannot
    be reliably distinguished from standard cases
    of achromatic blindsight.

14
Unconscious Processing of Colour in Normal
Observers
  • There is other evidence for the unconscious
    processing of colour (colour processing without
    actual experience of colour). Some of this work
    has moved away from focusing only on patients
    with neuropsychological deficits and instead has
    concentrated on normal observers however this
    work has been slow in coming and is somewhat
    controversial.
  • Vision science has long assumed that colour is
    a term that refers only to something that can be
    consciously experienced, perhaps because the idea
    of non-conscious perception of colour might
    seem like a contradiction in terms (Schmidt,
    2000).

15
Unconscious Processing of Colour in Normal
Observers (2)
  • Its important to be cautious, as some of this
    evidence comes from studies of subliminal
    perception which have often been shown to be
    unreliable and susceptible to response bias
    (Holender, 1986). Many experiments have been
    criticised for their failure to establish that
    the stimulus was not consciously perceived during
    presentation (Schmidt, 2000 Eriksen, 1960
    Holender, 1986).
  • Nevertheless, during a stimulus-detection study,
    Rollman and Nachmias (1972) presented their
    participants with chromatic discs. Whenever the
    participants incorrectly reported the stimulus as
    absent they were asked to guess what colour the
    disc would have been if it had actually been
    presented. These guesses proved correct
    significantly more often than would have been
    expected by chance.

16
Colour Processing is not just about seeing colour
  • Taken as a whole these findings suggest that
    colour processing need not actually lead to the
    experience of seeing colour (Schmidt, 2000).
  • Colour vision is assumed to be a single entity,
    but it may in fact be made up of (at least) two
    separate components.
  • Colour in fact seems to be used in several, quite
    distinct ways, to extract information from the
    visual scene.
  • What we typically call colour is actually
    surface colour, which gives us information about
    the surface properties of an object (and of
    gases, liquids, etc.).
  • This is colour as we normally come to think of
    it, what we would call the qualitative experience
    associated with colour perception, or colour
    qualia.

17
Colour Boundaries
  • The other type of information is information
    about form and this is obtained via colour
    boundaries, i.e. chromatic signals create spatial
    structures.
  • It seems likely that it is this detection of
    coloured boundaries that is intact in
    achromatopsics and it is this that enables them
    to make certain colour distinctions without being
    able to see the colours themselves.
  • Heywood, Cowey, and Newcombe (1994) describing
    the pattern of abilities of patient MS He
    canuse wavelength to extract form but his
    performance on tasks of colour discrimination
    suggest he has no phenomenal experience of colour
    itself. (p.253)
  • Presumably achromatopsics have damage to brain
    regions that are indispensable for the production
    of object colour. The regions that enable
    chromatic information to signal form, however,
    are still intact.

18
Research on infants
  • It has long been known that infants as young as
    two months can make chromatic discriminations.
  • But what mediates these discriminations? Either
    infants have normal colour vision in the ordinary
    sense, i.e. preserving information about
    wavelength, or they use edge cues as the basis
    for their response discriminations.
  • Thomasson and Teller (2000) manipulated the
    juxtaposed stimulus fields of earlier
    experiments, eliminating the sharp chromatic
    edges to see whether infants (16-week-olds) could
    still make the chromatic discriminations without
    them.
  • In all cases, manipulating the edge led to poorer
    performances, but performance still remained
    reliably above chance for most cases of chromatic
    stimuli. This suggests that infants as young
    16-weeks can make chromatic discriminations in
    the absence of sharp chromatically defined edges.
    However, as performance was affected by the lack
    of edges this suggests that they still play an
    important part in human colour discrimination.

19
Does this make sense?
  • If colour is defined as two distinct things then
    this conflicts with our phenomenological
    experience of the world, that the only role of
    colour vision is to enable us to see various
    media as coloured.
  • But as Akins (2000) points out, we should not
    necessarily be asking questions about colour only
    as it exists in our standard phenomenology, where
    the emphasis is on seeing coloured surfaces, we
    may need to ask broadly what value spectral
    information has for the visual system.
  • This may involve considering the original
    evolutionary benefits of colour vision (akin to
    what Pinker, 1997, calls the logic of reverse
    engineering using evolutionary theory as a
    guide to gain insight into how the visual system
    and the mind works), something well discuss next.

20
Evolutionary benefits of colour vision
  • We need to question common sense notions about
    the use of colour vision and instead look at its
    original evolutionary benefits. Can we account
    for both the experience of surface colour and the
    detection of boundaries through colour?
  • Given that there not only appear to be
    specialised mechanisms that process
    colour/wavelength information but that there may
    also be separate mechanisms for surface and edge
    colour it is not unreasonable to reconsider the
    functional role of colour in everyday life.
  • Theories of colour vision need to have some sense
    of biological utility they should focus on
    what the organism in its visual environment may
    actually need the components of colour vision for.

21
Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (2)
  • Other mammals have dichromatic or monochromatic
    colour vision but only primates have the three
    types of cone receptors that provide trichomatic
    colour vision. What advantage do primates have
    over these animals?
  • The detection of form through colour might offer
    considerable benefits for survival. As much of
    human vision involves spotting stimuli quickly
    and accurately in cluttered environments this
    additional method of detecting form would be
    advantageous in a number of ways for example, it
    would be useful for the avoidance of predators,
    for distinguishing ripe fruit amongst the leaves
    of trees, etc.

22
Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (3)
  • Regan, et al. (1998) and Sumner and Mollon (2000)
    found that primate photopigments are ideal for
    differentiating edible fruits and young leaves
    against a background of mature leaves.
  • This sort of research has mainly looked at the
    optimality of red and green cone responses to the
    spectral properties of red objects (ripe fruit,
    flowers, young leaves) amongst green objects and
    backgrounds (unripe fruit and mature leaves), the
    assumption being that the red/green system helps
    to distinguish the edible from the inedible
    (Dominy and Lucas, 2001).

23
Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (4)
  • Questions remain about the role of the
    yellow/blue system and why it developed.
  • Troscianko, Parraga and Tolhurst (2002) suggest
    that not all monkeys eat a diet that consisting
    only of red fruit and leaves, they also eat green
    leaves from certain trees but not others.
  • Perhaps the red/green and yellow/blue systems
    work together to help distinguish the
    different types of leaves, particularly under
    different levels of illumination.
  • Troscianko et al. found that, as well as being
    able to pick out red fruit and leaves from green
    foliage, the red/green system is indeed also good
    at discriminating between different tree types,
    though found no compelling evidence that the
    yellow/blue system is particularly suited to make
    these discriminations.
  • This does not rule out the possibility that both
    the red/green and yellow/blue system provided an
    evolutionary advantage by helping to detect
    colour edges, just that it is at present unclear
    what the yellow/blue system's contribution is.

24
Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (5)
  • The experience of surface colour, or colour
    qualia, on the other hand, has very different
    advantages, including being an essential feature
    for long-range planning, communication and other
    cognitive activities (Goodale and Humphrey,
    1998, p.193).
  • This aspect of colour is more clearly linked to
    our internal representation of the world and to
    consciousness, which might suggest that it is, in
    evolutionary terms, the more recent development
    of the two aspects of colour perception. We take
    for granted that the primary or even the sole
    function of colour vision is to enable us to see
    the world in colour, but in fact it may be a
    secondary function or even a bi-product (Akins,
    2000). This might also explain why there are
    apparent dissociations between conscious and
    non-conscious aspects of colour processing that
    relate to surface colour and boundary colour
    respectively.

25
Recommended Reading
  • Akins, K. A. (2000). More Than Mere Colouring A
    Dialogue Between Philosophy and Neuroscience on
    the Nature of Spectral Vision. Essay submitted to
    the Mcdonnell Foundation in application for the
    Mcdonnell Centennial Fellowship. Available at
  • http//www.stu.ca./neurophilosophy/members/akins/a
    ppessay.htm
  • Heywood, C. A., and Cowey, A. (1999). Cerebral
    achromatopsia. In G. W. Humphreys (Ed.)
    Neuropsychology of Vision. Hove Psychology Press
    Ltd.
  • Schmidt, T. (2000). Visual Perception Without
    Awareness Priming Responses by Color. In T.
    Metzinger (ed.) Neural Correlates of
    Consciousness empirical and conceptual
    questions. Cambridge, Mass. London MIT Press.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com