Title: Controversies In Cognition
1Controversies In Cognition
- Neuropsychology and the evolutionary value of
colour
2Aims
- To identify whether colour vision fits easily
into Milner and Goodales Two Visual Brains
Theory . - To look at research that suggests that processing
of colour information provides us with more than
just the conscious experience of colour. - To look at the possible evolutionary benefits of
colour vision. - To present Akins (2000) position on the role of
colour vision.
3Objectives
- To be able to identify whether colour vision fits
easily into Milner and Goodales Two Visual
Brains Theory . - To be able to describe and discuss research that
suggests that processing of colour information
provides us with more than just the conscious
experience of colour. - To be able to describe and discuss the possible
evolutionary benefits of colour vision. - To be able to discuss Akins (2000) position on
the role of colour vision.
4Last week
- We looked at Milner and Goodales Two Visual
Brains Theory. - Neuropsychological evidence provides strong
support for their theory of visual perception. - Using this evidence it should be possible to see
the way in which the two streams differ in how
they deal with incoming visual information. - However, despite strong support for this theory
there are still gaps that need clarification. - One such gap relates to the role that colour
processing plays in the ventral and dorsal
framework.
5Where does colour fit in?
- Colour is clearly a key physical property of the
visual world so it must have a place in Milner
and Goodales framework. - There is some good evidence that colour
information enters the ventral stream via input
from the parvocellular (P) channel, which is,
unlike the magnocellular (M) channel, mainly
responsible for colour (Livingstone and Hubel,
1987). - Further evidence for the link between colour and
the ventral stream is that cells in this stream
are often sensitive to colour (e.g. Zeki, 1980). - In addition, visual area V4 has often been
regarded as the primate brains colour centre
(e.g. Zeki, 1993) and, as this area is part of
the ventral stream, this would be good grounds
for assuming that the ventral stream provides the
sole basis for the visual experience of colour.
6Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
- However, much evidence casts doubt on the idea of
V4 being the primate brains colour centre. - Although Zeki (1973) reported that every one of
the 77 cells he sampled in region V4 showed
selectivity to wavelength, more recent evidence
suggests that many cells in the region are
strongly receptive to orientation and are even
indifferent to wavelength (Schein, Marrocco and
De Monasterio, 1982 Desimone and Schein, 1987). - It was also believed that monkeys with surgically
induced lesions to V4 show major impairments to
colour discrimination. - However, when monkeys with V4 lesions were
tested, the results suggested only a mild
impairment (Heywood and Cowey, 1987) or none at
all (Dean, 1979).
7Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
- Furthermore, when luminance and chromaticity were
carefully controlled on a display monitor for
monkeys with V4 completely removed, there was no
evidence of any impairment in colour oddity tasks
(Heywood, Gadotti and Cowey, 1992). - Wild, Butler, Carden and Kulikowski (1985)
monkeys with damage to V4 retain their colour
vision (e.g. they can learn to pick up a yellow
object) but lose colour constancy (the
phenomenon whereby an objects colour is
perceived as unvarying or fairly stable despite
considerable variation in the spectral
composition of the illuminant (Heywood and
Cowey, 1999, p.29)) (e.g. they cannot find the
same yellow object under blue overhead lighting).
- For humans with damage to an area that straddles
the temporal and parietal cortices, which may
correspond to the monkey area V4, there is a
similar loss of colour constancy though colour
recognition remains intact (Ruttiger, Braun,
Gegenfurtner, Petersen, Schonle and Sharpe,
1999).
8Is V4 the primate brains colour centre?
- It now seems reasonable to say that V4 is either
responsible for, or has a crucial role in, colour
constancy. Its also reasonable to suggest that
another region (for example, V8) or, more likely,
several regions in combination, beyond V4 are
responsible for constructing colour. - It still seems likely, though, that the colour
centre is based within the ventral and not the
dorsal stream. - The link between colour and the ventral stream
may be an intuitive one because, in the
terminology of Milner and Goodale, we commonly
use colour as part of our internal representation
of the world, plus we are consciously aware of
it, i.e. we can report on our experience of any
given colour we see, we can name it and compare
it with, or distinguish it from, other colours.
9Is there any neuropsychological evidence for this
assumption?
- If colour perception could fit easily into
Goodales and Milners framework then one would
expect there to be evidence of neuropsychological
dissociations like those mentioned last week. - There are many cases of individuals with impaired
colour perception resulting from brain damage. - Example 1 cerebral achromatopsia.
10What achromatopsics can do with colour
- Although they are without an awareness of colour,
these patients can still somehow use differences
in wavelength to make certain distinctions of
form and movement. - E.g. patient MS is densely achromatopsic and
yet can do some tasks involving colours that abut
each other (Heywood, Cowey, and Newcombe, 1991,
1994). His verbal replies suggest that he is
successful in these tasks because he can detect
edges between stimuli, even though the stimuli
appear to him to be identical.
11What achromatopsics can do with colour
- This ability of MS, to detect chromatically
generated contours (Heywood, Kentridge, and
Cowey, 1998a), has also been shown in other
achromatopsic patients (Barbur, Harlow and Plant,
1994). - MS, and other achromatopsics, can somehow detect
chromatic information without experiencing the
colours themselves. These findings suggest that
at some level, their colour processing remains
intact. They have no phenomenal experience of
colour, and yet retain some colour abilities but
not others. - However, cerebral achromatopsia is not
blindsight for colour (Heywood, Kentridge, and
Cowey, 1998b).
12Example 2 Colour Blindsight
- The blindsight phenomenon suggests that the
subcortical pathways can carry considerable
amounts of visual information. Some evidence
suggests that this may include information about
colour. - Bender and Krieger (1951) Perenin, Ruel, and
Hecaen (1980) Blythe, Kennard, and Ruddock,
(1987) Stoerig, (1987) Stoerig and Cowey (1989,
1992) all reported that wavelength discrimination
was possible in the blind fields of patients. - However, the evidence for colour blindsight is
still not clear-cut.
13Colour blindsight (2)
- E.g. two out of the 10 patients who Stoerig
(1987) tested failed to reach the .05 level of
statistical significance, suggesting that this
residual chromatic processing is not always
demonstrable and that even when it is it is
seriously impoverished. - Until there is stronger evidence for the reality
of colour blindsight it may be that it cannot
be reliably distinguished from standard cases
of achromatic blindsight.
14Unconscious Processing of Colour in Normal
Observers
- There is other evidence for the unconscious
processing of colour (colour processing without
actual experience of colour). Some of this work
has moved away from focusing only on patients
with neuropsychological deficits and instead has
concentrated on normal observers however this
work has been slow in coming and is somewhat
controversial. - Vision science has long assumed that colour is
a term that refers only to something that can be
consciously experienced, perhaps because the idea
of non-conscious perception of colour might
seem like a contradiction in terms (Schmidt,
2000).
15Unconscious Processing of Colour in Normal
Observers (2)
- Its important to be cautious, as some of this
evidence comes from studies of subliminal
perception which have often been shown to be
unreliable and susceptible to response bias
(Holender, 1986). Many experiments have been
criticised for their failure to establish that
the stimulus was not consciously perceived during
presentation (Schmidt, 2000 Eriksen, 1960
Holender, 1986). - Nevertheless, during a stimulus-detection study,
Rollman and Nachmias (1972) presented their
participants with chromatic discs. Whenever the
participants incorrectly reported the stimulus as
absent they were asked to guess what colour the
disc would have been if it had actually been
presented. These guesses proved correct
significantly more often than would have been
expected by chance.
16Colour Processing is not just about seeing colour
- Taken as a whole these findings suggest that
colour processing need not actually lead to the
experience of seeing colour (Schmidt, 2000). - Colour vision is assumed to be a single entity,
but it may in fact be made up of (at least) two
separate components. - Colour in fact seems to be used in several, quite
distinct ways, to extract information from the
visual scene. - What we typically call colour is actually
surface colour, which gives us information about
the surface properties of an object (and of
gases, liquids, etc.). - This is colour as we normally come to think of
it, what we would call the qualitative experience
associated with colour perception, or colour
qualia.
17Colour Boundaries
- The other type of information is information
about form and this is obtained via colour
boundaries, i.e. chromatic signals create spatial
structures. - It seems likely that it is this detection of
coloured boundaries that is intact in
achromatopsics and it is this that enables them
to make certain colour distinctions without being
able to see the colours themselves. - Heywood, Cowey, and Newcombe (1994) describing
the pattern of abilities of patient MS He
canuse wavelength to extract form but his
performance on tasks of colour discrimination
suggest he has no phenomenal experience of colour
itself. (p.253) - Presumably achromatopsics have damage to brain
regions that are indispensable for the production
of object colour. The regions that enable
chromatic information to signal form, however,
are still intact.
18Research on infants
- It has long been known that infants as young as
two months can make chromatic discriminations. - But what mediates these discriminations? Either
infants have normal colour vision in the ordinary
sense, i.e. preserving information about
wavelength, or they use edge cues as the basis
for their response discriminations. - Thomasson and Teller (2000) manipulated the
juxtaposed stimulus fields of earlier
experiments, eliminating the sharp chromatic
edges to see whether infants (16-week-olds) could
still make the chromatic discriminations without
them. - In all cases, manipulating the edge led to poorer
performances, but performance still remained
reliably above chance for most cases of chromatic
stimuli. This suggests that infants as young
16-weeks can make chromatic discriminations in
the absence of sharp chromatically defined edges.
However, as performance was affected by the lack
of edges this suggests that they still play an
important part in human colour discrimination.
19Does this make sense?
- If colour is defined as two distinct things then
this conflicts with our phenomenological
experience of the world, that the only role of
colour vision is to enable us to see various
media as coloured. - But as Akins (2000) points out, we should not
necessarily be asking questions about colour only
as it exists in our standard phenomenology, where
the emphasis is on seeing coloured surfaces, we
may need to ask broadly what value spectral
information has for the visual system. - This may involve considering the original
evolutionary benefits of colour vision (akin to
what Pinker, 1997, calls the logic of reverse
engineering using evolutionary theory as a
guide to gain insight into how the visual system
and the mind works), something well discuss next.
20Evolutionary benefits of colour vision
- We need to question common sense notions about
the use of colour vision and instead look at its
original evolutionary benefits. Can we account
for both the experience of surface colour and the
detection of boundaries through colour? - Given that there not only appear to be
specialised mechanisms that process
colour/wavelength information but that there may
also be separate mechanisms for surface and edge
colour it is not unreasonable to reconsider the
functional role of colour in everyday life. - Theories of colour vision need to have some sense
of biological utility they should focus on
what the organism in its visual environment may
actually need the components of colour vision for.
21Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (2)
- Other mammals have dichromatic or monochromatic
colour vision but only primates have the three
types of cone receptors that provide trichomatic
colour vision. What advantage do primates have
over these animals? - The detection of form through colour might offer
considerable benefits for survival. As much of
human vision involves spotting stimuli quickly
and accurately in cluttered environments this
additional method of detecting form would be
advantageous in a number of ways for example, it
would be useful for the avoidance of predators,
for distinguishing ripe fruit amongst the leaves
of trees, etc.
22Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (3)
- Regan, et al. (1998) and Sumner and Mollon (2000)
found that primate photopigments are ideal for
differentiating edible fruits and young leaves
against a background of mature leaves. - This sort of research has mainly looked at the
optimality of red and green cone responses to the
spectral properties of red objects (ripe fruit,
flowers, young leaves) amongst green objects and
backgrounds (unripe fruit and mature leaves), the
assumption being that the red/green system helps
to distinguish the edible from the inedible
(Dominy and Lucas, 2001).
23Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (4)
- Questions remain about the role of the
yellow/blue system and why it developed. - Troscianko, Parraga and Tolhurst (2002) suggest
that not all monkeys eat a diet that consisting
only of red fruit and leaves, they also eat green
leaves from certain trees but not others. - Perhaps the red/green and yellow/blue systems
work together to help distinguish the
different types of leaves, particularly under
different levels of illumination. - Troscianko et al. found that, as well as being
able to pick out red fruit and leaves from green
foliage, the red/green system is indeed also good
at discriminating between different tree types,
though found no compelling evidence that the
yellow/blue system is particularly suited to make
these discriminations. - This does not rule out the possibility that both
the red/green and yellow/blue system provided an
evolutionary advantage by helping to detect
colour edges, just that it is at present unclear
what the yellow/blue system's contribution is.
24Evolutionary benefits of colour vision (5)
- The experience of surface colour, or colour
qualia, on the other hand, has very different
advantages, including being an essential feature
for long-range planning, communication and other
cognitive activities (Goodale and Humphrey,
1998, p.193). - This aspect of colour is more clearly linked to
our internal representation of the world and to
consciousness, which might suggest that it is, in
evolutionary terms, the more recent development
of the two aspects of colour perception. We take
for granted that the primary or even the sole
function of colour vision is to enable us to see
the world in colour, but in fact it may be a
secondary function or even a bi-product (Akins,
2000). This might also explain why there are
apparent dissociations between conscious and
non-conscious aspects of colour processing that
relate to surface colour and boundary colour
respectively.
25Recommended Reading
- Akins, K. A. (2000). More Than Mere Colouring A
Dialogue Between Philosophy and Neuroscience on
the Nature of Spectral Vision. Essay submitted to
the Mcdonnell Foundation in application for the
Mcdonnell Centennial Fellowship. Available at - http//www.stu.ca./neurophilosophy/members/akins/a
ppessay.htm - Heywood, C. A., and Cowey, A. (1999). Cerebral
achromatopsia. In G. W. Humphreys (Ed.)
Neuropsychology of Vision. Hove Psychology Press
Ltd. - Schmidt, T. (2000). Visual Perception Without
Awareness Priming Responses by Color. In T.
Metzinger (ed.) Neural Correlates of
Consciousness empirical and conceptual
questions. Cambridge, Mass. London MIT Press.