Title: Delusions, beliefs, and actions: Pragmatic commitment reconsidered
1Delusions, beliefs, and actionsPragmatic
commitment reconsidered
Fabio Paglieri, Ryan McKay
European Society for Philosophy and Psychology -
Belfast, 25 August 2006
2Motivation
- To analyze the main objection raised against the
idea that delusions are beliefs the lack of
pragmatic commitment argument (LoPC) - To criticize the LoPC argument, using notions
derived from epistemology and action theory - To reformulate the LoPC argument
- To assess the import of this reformulation for a
theory of delusions
3What is a delusion?
- Informal definition A false mental
representation held with strong conviction
despite manifest evidence to the contrary - Delusions range from the exotic (e.g. Im God)
to the relatively mundane (My neighbours are
persecuting me) - Delusions are first-rank symptoms of
schizophrenia and feature prominently in numerous
other psychiatric and neurological conditions
4Examples of delusion
- Examples of monothematic delusions
- Capgras an impostor substituted for a spouse or
close relative - Cotard being dead, non-existent, putrefying or
missing internal organs - Fregoli being constantly followed by someone in
disguise - Many others
- Polythematic delusions figure often in cases of
schizophrenia (e.g. John Nashs fantasies)
5The standard view Delusions as beliefs
- Clinical definition Delusion A false belief
based on incorrect inference about external
reality that is firmly sustained despite what
almost everyone else believes and despite what
constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or
evidence to the contrary (DSM-IV-TR, 2000 821) - Defenders of the doxastic view agree with the DSM
that delusions are beliefs, but may disagree on
other points e.g., falsity (Peters, 2001)
6Objections to the doxastic view
- Lack of pragmatic commitment Deluded individuals
frequently fail to act in accordance with their
delusions - Lack of affective commitment The emotive and
affective responses seem inconsistent with the
contents of their delusions - Inability to provide convincing reasons
Difficulties in providing reasons for their
delusions, either because impossible to find
(e.g. the world will end tomorrow), or because
they seem not to be operative - Lack of integration with other beliefs Often
unconcerned by patent contradictions between
their delusions and their other beliefs
7Alternatives to the doxastic view
- Meta-cognitive thesis
- Currie, 2000 Currie, Jureidini, 2001 Currie,
Ravenscroft, 2002 Stephens, Graham, 2004 - No-content thesis
- Jaspers, 1963 Berrios, 1991 1996
- Loss-of-understanding thesis
- Campbell, 2001 Eilan, 2001
8The LoPC argument
- A given behaviour of a deluded patient
contradicts or does not follow from the content
of his/her delusion - Therefore, he/she does not really believe the
content of that delusion - Example Many Capgras patients do not file a
missing person report to the police, in spite of
their delusion that the spouse has been
substituted by an impostor. Hence, they do not
truly believe in their delusion - Bel(p) ? Do(A) therefore not-Do(A) ? not-Bel(p)
9Key premises of the LoPC argument
- Pragmatic commitment is lacking in delusional
patients - challenged by Bayne and Pacherie (2005), since
the evidence is not so B/W in this respect
(ODwyer, 1990 Förstl et al., 1991 Young,
Leafhead, 1996 Young, 2000) - A certain behaviour or action can be used to
pinpoint a single, specific mental attitude - The mental attitude revealed by action is belief
10Acting in spite of ones beliefs
- Observation Sometimes it seems rational to act
in spite of our beliefs, i.e. either accepting
for practical purposes something that we do not
believe, or failing to act on something we do
believe - Hypothesis It may be convenient to split two
functions that were usually collapsed in belief,
i.e. aiming at being true, and being used in
shaping action - Belief A mental representation that the subject
considers to be true, i.e. a correct image of
reality - Acceptance A mental representation that is used
to plan and carry on an action, as a map by which
the subject steers (Ramsey, 1931)
11Varieties of Acceptance (Bratman, 1992)
- When do acceptance and belief diverge?
- Simplification of ones reasoning
- e.g. taking for granted it will not rain in
planning a summer day out - Asymmetries in the cost of errors (prudential
reasons) - e.g. acting on pessimistic presumptions to avoid
costly surprises - Needs of social cooperation
- e.g. acting on socially agreed premises (possibly
without believing them individually) - Special relations to others
- e.g. acting as if my close friend is innocent, in
spite of strong evidence to the contrary - Pre-conditions for any practical reasoning at all
- e.g. a soldier in a war zone planning his day as
if he was confident he will survive it, although
he is rather sceptical about this
12Acceptance for prudential reason
- I plan for a major construction project to begin
next month. I need to decide now whether to do
the entire project at once or instead to break
the project into two parts, to be executed
separately. The rationale for the second strategy
is that I am unsure whether I presently have the
financial resources to do the whole thing at
once. I know that in the case of each
sub-contractor carpenter, plumber, and so on
it is only possible at present to get an estimate
of the range of potential costs. In the face of
this uncertainty I proceed in a cautious way In
the case of each sub-contractor I take it for
granted that the total costs will be at the top
of the estimated range. On the basis of these
assumptions I determine whether I have at present
enough money to do the whole project at once. In
contrast, if you offered me a bet on the actual
total cost of the project the winner being the
person whose guess is closer to the actual total
I would reason differently. (Bratman,
1992 6)
13Import for the LoPC argument
- This distinction defuses the LoPC argument,
because - Actions reveal acceptances, not beliefs
- Beliefs and acceptances do not always coincide
- Example Failure to file a missing person report
does not imply that the Capgras patient does not
believe the delusional content. Instead, this
content could be truly believed, and yet not
acted upon due to pragmatic concerns (e.g.
prudential reasons) - The belief vs. acceptance distinction undermines
the 3rd premise of the LoPC argument Delusions
could be beliefs that are not accepted for
practical purposes
14Critique of the B/A distinction
- The distinction is merely stipulative Actions
reveal acceptances rather than beliefs just
because we have defined these notions accordingly - The distinction turns belief into an unverifiable
quantity Since beliefs are not revealed by
action, and verbal behaviour is just one kind of
action, then how can we attribute beliefs
meaningfully to anyone? - Legitimate doubt Do we really need the notion of
acceptance, in order to account for those cases
in which we seem to act in spite of our beliefs?
15Alternative explanation of Bratmans example
- The subject believes that
- The project costs are likely to be in the average
of the expected range - However, it is possible, albeit unlikely, that
they will escalate to the top of the range - If the latter happens, the subject will be in
deep financial troubles - The subject intends to
- Conclude the construction works in a reasonable
amount of time - Avoid the risk of bankruptcy
- By bringing into the picture beliefs about
possibilities and motivations (and why not?),
this case is explained without any need to
contrive an additional notion of acceptance as
independent from belief
16Two birds with one stone?
- This critique undermines the B/A distinction, but
at the same time - calls into question the 2nd premise of the LoPC
argument, i.e. the idea that a certain action is
indicative of a single mental attitude - The B/A distinction pointed at the right problem
in the LoPC argument (the complex nexus between
belief and action), but offered the wrong
solution (dissociating belief from action)
17Critique of the LoPC argument
- Our alternative explanation of the construction
project example shows that a certain behaviour
cannot be used as a litmus test for a single
belief, but rather reveals a complex system of
beliefs and motivations - The same applies to delusional cases The Capgras
patient who fails to file a missing person report
may have excellent reasons ( other beliefs
motivations) for doing so, and if we have grounds
for attributing him/her such reasons, the LoPC
objection does not apply - The LoPC argument must be reformulated, to avoid
over-simplification of the link between actions,
beliefs, and motives
18LoPC argument reconsidered
- Given a single, specific delusional content, we
take any instance of behaviour that cannot be
properly explained by a system of beliefs (plus
motivations) which includes the delusional
content as indicating that the subject is not
acting on the ground of his/her delusion,
therefore he/she does not believe it. - Sensible concern Considering that there are
potentially infinite stories that we can devise
to account for ones action, is this
reformulation overly prudent or conservative? Are
we making the LoPC objection too weak?
19LoPC revised Key constraints
- Justification Additional beliefs and motives
must be backed up by some evidence in the
clinical history of the patient - No missing person report We cannot attribute to
a Capgras patient the belief that his wife ran
away of her own accord, unless we have evidence
to that effect - Cross-behavioural consistency They must be
consistent with beliefs and motives invoked to
explain other behaviours of the patient
(controversial, here meant as a practical
guideline for the observer and not as a cognitive
law for the subject) - No missing person report We cannot attribute to
a Capgras patient the goal of concealing his
bizarre conviction from others, if he is known to
frequently declare it in public places
20Musings on behavioural incongruence
- Pragmatic commitment in delusional patients is
not so much lacking, as rather inconsistent - Cases of non-verbal delusion-based behaviour
- Verbal delusion-based behaviour, i.e. patients
frequently assert the content of their delusions - From behavioural inertia to behavioural
incongruence - Our reformulation of the LoPC argument provides a
framework for dealing with behavioural
incongruence The contextual differences in the
pragmatic commitment showed towards ones
delusions may be attributed to other relevant
beliefs and motives of the deluded subject
21Musings on behavioural incongruence
- Why the diversity of PC across different
non-verbal behaviours? - HP More delusion-based action in presence of
positive expectations on the outcome - Comparing Capgras delusion (Young, 2000) and
erotomania (ODwyer, 1990) - Fact Delusion-based action is more frequent in
the second condition - Speculation Erotomaniacs are usually driven by
positive expectations, even when they act
violently (e.g. John Hinckley Jr. shooting Regan
for the love of Jodie Foster) the same does not
necessarily apply to Capgras patients - Limit Heterogeneous data, never meant to be
compared
22Musings on behavioural incongruence
- Why PC is much more frequent in verbal than in
non-verbal behaviour? - Talk is cheap, or cheaper than other actions
- Increase in delusion-based non-verbal behaviour
towards trusted interlocutors - Anecdotal evidence (thanks to Maria Miceli)
- An old lady, paranoid in several respects,
developed the conviction that the staff at her
nursing home wanted to kill her. This lady is
perfectly capable of voicing her belief and even
providing detailed reasons of why she formed it,
and she does so with trusted people, e.g. close
friends and some of her fellow patients. However,
she sternly refuses to give away this information
to the staff of the nursing home for the
obvious reason, she says, that this would make
them realize that she is aware of their
conspiracy, and this would further jeopardize her
predicament.
23Conclusions and future work
- The standard formulation of the LoPC argument is
mistaken, not because action does not relate to
belief, but because this relation is always
mediated by other beliefs and motives - It is possible to reformulate the LoPC argument,
rather than abandoning it - This reformulation will have to be tested against
many cases of delusions, to check if it is
applicable, and what are its consequences for the
debate about the nature of delusions - This reformulation also provides a framework for
discussing behavioural incongruence in delusional
patients - These speculations await further empirical
verification
24Thanks for your kind attention.
Fabio Paglieri paglieri_at_media.unisi.it Ryan
McKay rmckay_at_csu.edu.au
European Society for Philosophy and Psychology -
Belfast, 25 August 2006
25Outline
- Definition and examples of delusions
- The doxastic view Delusions as beliefs
- Main criticisms against the doxastic view
- The LoPC argument
- 1st attack Belief vs. acceptance
- Critique of the distinction between belief and
acceptance - 2nd attack Single beliefs vs. systems of beliefs
and goals - The LoPC argument reconsidered
- Some thoughts on behavioural incongruence
- Conclusions and future work
26Alternatives to the doxastic view
- Meta-cognitive thesis Delusions as higher order
cognitive phenomena, i.e. meta-evaluations.
Delusions as imaginings, which the subject
mistakenly consider to be believed
(meta-beliefs). Delusions as cognitive
hallucinations (Currie, 2000 Currie, Jureidini,
2001 Currie, Ravenscroft, 2002), revealing a
complex delusional stance (Stephens, Graham,
2004).
27Alternatives to the doxastic view
- No-content thesis Certain delusions are so
bizarre (violating biological, physical and
logical laws) that they are devoid of any
meaningful content (Jaspers, 1963 Berrios,
1991). Delusions are merely empty speech-acts
that disguise themselves as beliefs (Berrios,
1996 126).
28Alternatives to the doxastic view
- Loss-of-understanding thesis The way that
deluded subjects articulate their delusions
connotes a loss of understanding of the socially
shared meaning of the expressions that they are
using (Campbell, 2001 Eilan, 2001). This implies
that the delusional content (believed or not)
differs markedly from what would be implied in
normal usage of the same propositions.
29Defining Features Acceptance vs. belief
30B/A as Collective Mental States
- The problem of collective doxastic states
- Is it possible to attribute mental states such as
beliefs and acceptances to collective entities
(e.g., groups, institutions, etc.) in a
non-summative sense? - If so, are these collective mental states to be
interpreted as either beliefs or acceptances? - Disagreement believers (Gilbert, Tollefsen) vs.
rejectionists (Wray, Meijers) - Distinction between two sub-types of acceptance
(Engel, Tuomela) - acceptance as true / assent vs. pragmatic
acceptance
31Pragmatic Acceptance vs. Acceptance as True
32An Alternative Definitional Strategy
- Instead of listing similarities / differences, we
try to - find a truly distinctive feature
- show how all other differences follow from such
trait - Hakli (in press)
- voluntary acceptance vs. involuntary belief
(criticized by Bratman and Tollefsen) - Our proposal
- pragmatic value (acceptance)vs. truth-functional
value (belief)
33Belief and Acceptance in a Nutshell
- Bel(p) is usually a good reason to Acc(p), but
there are exceptions(cf. Bratman) - Acc(p) may lead, if the resulting action is
successful, to Bel(p)(cf. Pascals argument)
34Belief vs. Acceptance in Formal Models
- Bayesian models distinction not mentioned
- Reason Maintenance Systems distinction not
mentioned - Doxastic logics distinction not mentioned or
collapsed - e.g. in BDI beliefs are both truthful
representations of external reality and a basis
for deliberation and action - AGM belief revision distinction shortly
mentioned according to Stalnakers inclusive view - Acceptance is a broader concept than belief it
also includes such attitudes as assuming,
presupposing, and positing. To accept a
proposition is to treat it as true in one way or
another. This position entails that
acceptance is relative to context A person may
accept something in one context but reject it or
leave it indetermined in another. On my
account acceptance entails full belief.
(Gärdenfors, 1988 23)
35Beliefs vs. Acceptances Does It Matter?
- Beliefs vs. acceptances
- Significant differences between reasons to
believe and reasons to accept An
information-based approach may accommodate both - Different properties that should be considered to
avoid confusion / ambiguity in formal models (see
Cohens accusation)
36Two Puzzles and One Doubt
- There seems to be valid reasons to improve the
epistemological foundations of formal models of
belief dynamics (Pollock, Gillies, 2000). But
this leaves open two questions and one doubt - Question of Primacy What does it come first (in
both ontogenesis and phylogenesis), belief or
acceptance? - Question of Function If belief is a derivative
notion, why is it developed at all? What is the
adaptive function of belief thus conceived? Are
we insanely obsessed with truth, or is there an
added value in belief dynamics? - and yet
- Radical doubt Is acceptance for real, or is it
just a contrivance of harm-chair philosophy?
Would it be possible to reduce alleged examples
of acceptances to innocuous cases of belief?