Delusions, beliefs, and actions: Pragmatic commitment reconsidered - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 24
About This Presentation
Title:

Delusions, beliefs, and actions: Pragmatic commitment reconsidered

Description:

To criticize the LoPC argument, using notions derived from ... Regan for the love of Jodie Foster); the same does not necessarily apply to Capgras patients ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:73
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 25
Provided by: fabiopa
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Delusions, beliefs, and actions: Pragmatic commitment reconsidered


1
Delusions, beliefs, and actionsPragmatic
commitment reconsidered
Fabio Paglieri, Ryan McKay
European Society for Philosophy and Psychology -
Belfast, 25 August 2006
2
Motivation
  • To analyze the main objection raised against the
    idea that delusions are beliefs the lack of
    pragmatic commitment argument (LoPC)
  • To criticize the LoPC argument, using notions
    derived from epistemology and action theory
  • To reformulate the LoPC argument
  • To assess the import of this reformulation for a
    theory of delusions

3
What is a delusion?
  • Informal definition A false mental
    representation held with strong conviction
    despite manifest evidence to the contrary
  • Delusions range from the exotic (e.g. Im God)
    to the relatively mundane (My neighbours are
    persecuting me)
  • Delusions are first-rank symptoms of
    schizophrenia and feature prominently in numerous
    other psychiatric and neurological conditions

4
Examples of delusion
  • Examples of monothematic delusions
  • Capgras an impostor substituted for a spouse or
    close relative
  • Cotard being dead, non-existent, putrefying or
    missing internal organs
  • Fregoli being constantly followed by someone in
    disguise
  • Many others
  • Polythematic delusions figure often in cases of
    schizophrenia (e.g. John Nashs fantasies)

5
The standard view Delusions as beliefs
  • Clinical definition Delusion A false belief
    based on incorrect inference about external
    reality that is firmly sustained despite what
    almost everyone else believes and despite what
    constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or
    evidence to the contrary (DSM-IV-TR, 2000 821)
  • Defenders of the doxastic view agree with the DSM
    that delusions are beliefs, but may disagree on
    other points e.g., falsity (Peters, 2001)

6
Objections to the doxastic view
  • Lack of pragmatic commitment Deluded individuals
    frequently fail to act in accordance with their
    delusions
  • Lack of affective commitment The emotive and
    affective responses seem inconsistent with the
    contents of their delusions
  • Inability to provide convincing reasons
    Difficulties in providing reasons for their
    delusions, either because impossible to find
    (e.g. the world will end tomorrow), or because
    they seem not to be operative
  • Lack of integration with other beliefs Often
    unconcerned by patent contradictions between
    their delusions and their other beliefs

7
Alternatives to the doxastic view
  • Meta-cognitive thesis
  • Currie, 2000 Currie, Jureidini, 2001 Currie,
    Ravenscroft, 2002 Stephens, Graham, 2004
  • No-content thesis
  • Jaspers, 1963 Berrios, 1991 1996
  • Loss-of-understanding thesis
  • Campbell, 2001 Eilan, 2001

8
The LoPC argument
  • A given behaviour of a deluded patient
    contradicts or does not follow from the content
    of his/her delusion
  • Therefore, he/she does not really believe the
    content of that delusion
  • Example Many Capgras patients do not file a
    missing person report to the police, in spite of
    their delusion that the spouse has been
    substituted by an impostor. Hence, they do not
    truly believe in their delusion
  • Bel(p) ? Do(A) therefore not-Do(A) ? not-Bel(p)

9
Key premises of the LoPC argument
  • Pragmatic commitment is lacking in delusional
    patients
  • challenged by Bayne and Pacherie (2005), since
    the evidence is not so B/W in this respect
    (ODwyer, 1990 Förstl et al., 1991 Young,
    Leafhead, 1996 Young, 2000)
  • A certain behaviour or action can be used to
    pinpoint a single, specific mental attitude
  • The mental attitude revealed by action is belief

10
Acting in spite of ones beliefs
  • Observation Sometimes it seems rational to act
    in spite of our beliefs, i.e. either accepting
    for practical purposes something that we do not
    believe, or failing to act on something we do
    believe
  • Hypothesis It may be convenient to split two
    functions that were usually collapsed in belief,
    i.e. aiming at being true, and being used in
    shaping action
  • Belief A mental representation that the subject
    considers to be true, i.e. a correct image of
    reality
  • Acceptance A mental representation that is used
    to plan and carry on an action, as a map by which
    the subject steers (Ramsey, 1931)

11
Varieties of Acceptance (Bratman, 1992)
  • When do acceptance and belief diverge?
  • Simplification of ones reasoning
  • e.g. taking for granted it will not rain in
    planning a summer day out
  • Asymmetries in the cost of errors (prudential
    reasons)
  • e.g. acting on pessimistic presumptions to avoid
    costly surprises
  • Needs of social cooperation
  • e.g. acting on socially agreed premises (possibly
    without believing them individually)
  • Special relations to others
  • e.g. acting as if my close friend is innocent, in
    spite of strong evidence to the contrary
  • Pre-conditions for any practical reasoning at all
  • e.g. a soldier in a war zone planning his day as
    if he was confident he will survive it, although
    he is rather sceptical about this

12
Acceptance for prudential reason
  • I plan for a major construction project to begin
    next month. I need to decide now whether to do
    the entire project at once or instead to break
    the project into two parts, to be executed
    separately. The rationale for the second strategy
    is that I am unsure whether I presently have the
    financial resources to do the whole thing at
    once. I know that in the case of each
    sub-contractor carpenter, plumber, and so on
    it is only possible at present to get an estimate
    of the range of potential costs. In the face of
    this uncertainty I proceed in a cautious way In
    the case of each sub-contractor I take it for
    granted that the total costs will be at the top
    of the estimated range. On the basis of these
    assumptions I determine whether I have at present
    enough money to do the whole project at once. In
    contrast, if you offered me a bet on the actual
    total cost of the project the winner being the
    person whose guess is closer to the actual total
    I would reason differently. (Bratman,
    1992 6)

13
Import for the LoPC argument
  • This distinction defuses the LoPC argument,
    because
  • Actions reveal acceptances, not beliefs
  • Beliefs and acceptances do not always coincide
  • Example Failure to file a missing person report
    does not imply that the Capgras patient does not
    believe the delusional content. Instead, this
    content could be truly believed, and yet not
    acted upon due to pragmatic concerns (e.g.
    prudential reasons)
  • The belief vs. acceptance distinction undermines
    the 3rd premise of the LoPC argument Delusions
    could be beliefs that are not accepted for
    practical purposes

14
Critique of the B/A distinction
  • The distinction is merely stipulative Actions
    reveal acceptances rather than beliefs just
    because we have defined these notions accordingly
  • The distinction turns belief into an unverifiable
    quantity Since beliefs are not revealed by
    action, and verbal behaviour is just one kind of
    action, then how can we attribute beliefs
    meaningfully to anyone?
  • Legitimate doubt Do we really need the notion of
    acceptance, in order to account for those cases
    in which we seem to act in spite of our beliefs?

15
Alternative explanation of Bratmans example
  • The subject believes that
  • The project costs are likely to be in the average
    of the expected range
  • However, it is possible, albeit unlikely, that
    they will escalate to the top of the range
  • If the latter happens, the subject will be in
    deep financial troubles
  • The subject intends to
  • Conclude the construction works in a reasonable
    amount of time
  • Avoid the risk of bankruptcy
  • By bringing into the picture beliefs about
    possibilities and motivations (and why not?),
    this case is explained without any need to
    contrive an additional notion of acceptance as
    independent from belief

16
Two birds with one stone?
  • This critique undermines the B/A distinction, but
    at the same time
  • calls into question the 2nd premise of the LoPC
    argument, i.e. the idea that a certain action is
    indicative of a single mental attitude
  • The B/A distinction pointed at the right problem
    in the LoPC argument (the complex nexus between
    belief and action), but offered the wrong
    solution (dissociating belief from action)

17
Critique of the LoPC argument
  • Our alternative explanation of the construction
    project example shows that a certain behaviour
    cannot be used as a litmus test for a single
    belief, but rather reveals a complex system of
    beliefs and motivations
  • The same applies to delusional cases The Capgras
    patient who fails to file a missing person report
    may have excellent reasons ( other beliefs
    motivations) for doing so, and if we have grounds
    for attributing him/her such reasons, the LoPC
    objection does not apply
  • The LoPC argument must be reformulated, to avoid
    over-simplification of the link between actions,
    beliefs, and motives

18
LoPC argument reconsidered
  • Given a single, specific delusional content, we
    take any instance of behaviour that cannot be
    properly explained by a system of beliefs (plus
    motivations) which includes the delusional
    content as indicating that the subject is not
    acting on the ground of his/her delusion,
    therefore he/she does not believe it.
  • Sensible concern Considering that there are
    potentially infinite stories that we can devise
    to account for ones action, is this
    reformulation overly prudent or conservative? Are
    we making the LoPC objection too weak?

19
LoPC revised Key constraints
  • Justification Additional beliefs and motives
    must be backed up by some evidence in the
    clinical history of the patient
  • No missing person report We cannot attribute to
    a Capgras patient the belief that his wife ran
    away of her own accord, unless we have evidence
    to that effect
  • Cross-behavioural consistency They must be
    consistent with beliefs and motives invoked to
    explain other behaviours of the patient
    (controversial, here meant as a practical
    guideline for the observer and not as a cognitive
    law for the subject)
  • No missing person report We cannot attribute to
    a Capgras patient the goal of concealing his
    bizarre conviction from others, if he is known to
    frequently declare it in public places

20
Musings on behavioural incongruence
  • Pragmatic commitment in delusional patients is
    not so much lacking, as rather inconsistent
  • Cases of non-verbal delusion-based behaviour
  • Verbal delusion-based behaviour, i.e. patients
    frequently assert the content of their delusions
  • From behavioural inertia to behavioural
    incongruence
  • Our reformulation of the LoPC argument provides a
    framework for dealing with behavioural
    incongruence The contextual differences in the
    pragmatic commitment showed towards ones
    delusions may be attributed to other relevant
    beliefs and motives of the deluded subject

21
Musings on behavioural incongruence
  • Why the diversity of PC across different
    non-verbal behaviours?
  • HP More delusion-based action in presence of
    positive expectations on the outcome
  • Comparing Capgras delusion (Young, 2000) and
    erotomania (ODwyer, 1990)
  • Fact Delusion-based action is more frequent in
    the second condition
  • Speculation Erotomaniacs are usually driven by
    positive expectations, even when they act
    violently (e.g. John Hinckley Jr. shooting Regan
    for the love of Jodie Foster) the same does not
    necessarily apply to Capgras patients
  • Limit Heterogeneous data, never meant to be
    compared

22
Musings on behavioural incongruence
  • Why PC is much more frequent in verbal than in
    non-verbal behaviour?
  • Talk is cheap, or cheaper than other actions
  • Increase in delusion-based non-verbal behaviour
    towards trusted interlocutors
  • Anecdotal evidence (thanks to Maria Miceli)
  • An old lady, paranoid in several respects,
    developed the conviction that the staff at her
    nursing home wanted to kill her. This lady is
    perfectly capable of voicing her belief and even
    providing detailed reasons of why she formed it,
    and she does so with trusted people, e.g. close
    friends and some of her fellow patients. However,
    she sternly refuses to give away this information
    to the staff of the nursing home for the
    obvious reason, she says, that this would make
    them realize that she is aware of their
    conspiracy, and this would further jeopardize her
    predicament.

23
Conclusions and future work
  • The standard formulation of the LoPC argument is
    mistaken, not because action does not relate to
    belief, but because this relation is always
    mediated by other beliefs and motives
  • It is possible to reformulate the LoPC argument,
    rather than abandoning it
  • This reformulation will have to be tested against
    many cases of delusions, to check if it is
    applicable, and what are its consequences for the
    debate about the nature of delusions
  • This reformulation also provides a framework for
    discussing behavioural incongruence in delusional
    patients
  • These speculations await further empirical
    verification

24
Thanks for your kind attention.
Fabio Paglieri paglieri_at_media.unisi.it Ryan
McKay rmckay_at_csu.edu.au
European Society for Philosophy and Psychology -
Belfast, 25 August 2006
25
Outline
  • Definition and examples of delusions
  • The doxastic view Delusions as beliefs
  • Main criticisms against the doxastic view
  • The LoPC argument
  • 1st attack Belief vs. acceptance
  • Critique of the distinction between belief and
    acceptance
  • 2nd attack Single beliefs vs. systems of beliefs
    and goals
  • The LoPC argument reconsidered
  • Some thoughts on behavioural incongruence
  • Conclusions and future work

26
Alternatives to the doxastic view
  • Meta-cognitive thesis Delusions as higher order
    cognitive phenomena, i.e. meta-evaluations.
    Delusions as imaginings, which the subject
    mistakenly consider to be believed
    (meta-beliefs). Delusions as cognitive
    hallucinations (Currie, 2000 Currie, Jureidini,
    2001 Currie, Ravenscroft, 2002), revealing a
    complex delusional stance (Stephens, Graham,
    2004).

27
Alternatives to the doxastic view
  • No-content thesis Certain delusions are so
    bizarre (violating biological, physical and
    logical laws) that they are devoid of any
    meaningful content (Jaspers, 1963 Berrios,
    1991). Delusions are merely empty speech-acts
    that disguise themselves as beliefs (Berrios,
    1996 126).

28
Alternatives to the doxastic view
  • Loss-of-understanding thesis The way that
    deluded subjects articulate their delusions
    connotes a loss of understanding of the socially
    shared meaning of the expressions that they are
    using (Campbell, 2001 Eilan, 2001). This implies
    that the delusional content (believed or not)
    differs markedly from what would be implied in
    normal usage of the same propositions.

29
Defining Features Acceptance vs. belief
30
B/A as Collective Mental States
  • The problem of collective doxastic states
  • Is it possible to attribute mental states such as
    beliefs and acceptances to collective entities
    (e.g., groups, institutions, etc.) in a
    non-summative sense?
  • If so, are these collective mental states to be
    interpreted as either beliefs or acceptances?
  • Disagreement believers (Gilbert, Tollefsen) vs.
    rejectionists (Wray, Meijers)
  • Distinction between two sub-types of acceptance
    (Engel, Tuomela)
  • acceptance as true / assent vs. pragmatic
    acceptance

31
Pragmatic Acceptance vs. Acceptance as True
32
An Alternative Definitional Strategy
  • Instead of listing similarities / differences, we
    try to
  • find a truly distinctive feature
  • show how all other differences follow from such
    trait
  • Hakli (in press)
  • voluntary acceptance vs. involuntary belief
    (criticized by Bratman and Tollefsen)
  • Our proposal
  • pragmatic value (acceptance)vs. truth-functional
    value (belief)

33
Belief and Acceptance in a Nutshell
  • Bel(p) is usually a good reason to Acc(p), but
    there are exceptions(cf. Bratman)
  • Acc(p) may lead, if the resulting action is
    successful, to Bel(p)(cf. Pascals argument)

34
Belief vs. Acceptance in Formal Models
  • Bayesian models distinction not mentioned
  • Reason Maintenance Systems distinction not
    mentioned
  • Doxastic logics distinction not mentioned or
    collapsed
  • e.g. in BDI beliefs are both truthful
    representations of external reality and a basis
    for deliberation and action
  • AGM belief revision distinction shortly
    mentioned according to Stalnakers inclusive view
  • Acceptance is a broader concept than belief it
    also includes such attitudes as assuming,
    presupposing, and positing. To accept a
    proposition is to treat it as true in one way or
    another. This position entails that
    acceptance is relative to context A person may
    accept something in one context but reject it or
    leave it indetermined in another. On my
    account acceptance entails full belief.
    (Gärdenfors, 1988 23)

35
Beliefs vs. Acceptances Does It Matter?
  • Beliefs vs. acceptances
  • Significant differences between reasons to
    believe and reasons to accept An
    information-based approach may accommodate both
  • Different properties that should be considered to
    avoid confusion / ambiguity in formal models (see
    Cohens accusation)

36
Two Puzzles and One Doubt
  • There seems to be valid reasons to improve the
    epistemological foundations of formal models of
    belief dynamics (Pollock, Gillies, 2000). But
    this leaves open two questions and one doubt
  • Question of Primacy What does it come first (in
    both ontogenesis and phylogenesis), belief or
    acceptance?
  • Question of Function If belief is a derivative
    notion, why is it developed at all? What is the
    adaptive function of belief thus conceived? Are
    we insanely obsessed with truth, or is there an
    added value in belief dynamics?
  • and yet
  • Radical doubt Is acceptance for real, or is it
    just a contrivance of harm-chair philosophy?
    Would it be possible to reduce alleged examples
    of acceptances to innocuous cases of belief?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com