Title: Chapter Three
1Chapter Three
- Topics in Consumer
- Behavior
2- This chapter contains four sessions
- Session one
- Session two
- Session three
- Session four
Finish
3Session One
- General goal
- To be familiar with a variety of specific
- types of utility functions duality theorem
- Detailed goals
- 1. Stone-Geary utility function
- 2. Separable utility functions
- 3. Additive utility functions
- 4. Homogeneous homothetic utility functions
- 5. Duality in consumptions
- 6. Evaluation
- Back
41. Stone-Geary utility function Linear
Expenditure system
- a. Description
- b. Demand functions optimization
- c. Expenditure functions
- Back to the main menu
52. Separable utility functions
- a. Strongly separable utility functions
- 1. Description
- 2. Properties
- 3. Example
- b. Weakly separable utility functions
- 1.Description
- Back to the main menu
-
63. Additive utility functions
- a. Strongly additive utility functions
- 1. Description
- 2. Properties
- 3. Example
- b. Weakly additive utility functions
- 1. Description
-
Back to the main menu
74. Homogeneous homothetic utility functions
- a. Homogeneous utility functions
- 1. Description
- 2. Properties
- b. Homothetic utility functions
- 1. Description
- 2. Properties
- 3. Example
- Back to the main menu
85. Duality in consumption
- a. Dual problem Shepherd lemma
- 1. Description
- 2. Dual problem shepherd lemma
- 3. Generalization
- b. Roys identity
- 1. Description
- 2. Generalization
- c. Slutsky equation
- d. Example
- Back to the main menu
9Evaluation
- 1. Questions 3.1, 3.2, 3.3, 3.4
- 2. Problems 5.6, 5.7, 5.8 Nicholson
10Session Two
- General goal
- 1. The theory of revealed preferences
- 2. Revealed preferences indifference curves
- Detailed goals
- 3. Weak axioms of revealed preferences
- 4. Strong axioms of revealed preferences
- Evaluation
- Evaluation
- Back
-
112. Revealed preferences indifference curves
- a. From revealed preferences to preference
- 1. The principle of revealed preference
- 2. Indirect revealed preference
- (fig.7.2 Varian)
- b. From revealed preferences to indifference
curves - 1. Description
- 2. Graph (fig.7.3 Varian)
- Back
123.The weak axiom of reveal preferences
- a. Definition
- b. Graph (fig.7.4, 7.5 Varian)
- (fig. 3.2a , 3.2b)
- c. Mathematics
- d. Generalization
- d. Checking WARP
- Back
134. The Strong axiom of revealed
preferences (SARP)
- a. Definition
- b. Graph (fig.7.2 Varian)
- c. Checking SARP
- d. Revealed preferences substitution effect
Back
14Evaluationses.2
ch.3
- 1. Question 3.5
- 2. Problems 7.1, 7.2, 7.3 Nicholson
-
15Session Three
- General goal
- Consumer surplus welfare changes
- Detailed goals
- 1. Compensating variation
- 2. Equivalent variation
- 3. Consumer surplus
- 4. Welfare changes Continue
16Session Three
- Introduction
- Constant real income and the compensating
variation in money income (C.V) - Constant real income and the equivalent variation
in money income (E.V) - Consumers surplus
- Evaluation
- Example
Back
17I. Introduction
- The income substitution effects (Review)
- (fig.3.3 Laidler)
- b. Money income real income
- (fig.3.4 Laidler)
-
- Back
18II. Constant real income the compensating
variation money income
- a. Description
- 1. Constant real income
- 2. Compensating variation
- b. Graph
- ooo(fig. 3.4, 3.11 Laidler) (fig. 14.4
Varian) - c. Mathematics
- 1. Expenditure function
- 2. Shepherds lemma
- 3. C.V (fig. 5.9 Nicholson)
Continue -
19III. Constant real income the equivalent
variation in Money income (E.V)
- a. Description
- b. Graph (fig.3.8, 3.11 Laidler)
- (fig. 14.4 Varian)
- c. Mathematics
- d. Example
- Back
20IV. Consumer Surplus
- a. Introduction
- b. Description
- 1. Definition
- 2. Measurement
- c. Mathematics a comparative approach
- (fig. 4.8Laidler) (fig. 5.10 Nich)
- d. Example
Back
21Evaluation
- 1. Problem 5.10 Nicholson (1992)
- 2. Question 3.7
- 3. Question 4.17 Laidler
- Back
22Session Four
- General goal
- Consumer behavior under risk uncertainty
- Detailed goals
- 1. Expected utility theory
- 2. Attitudes towards risk
- 3. Risk insurance
Continue
23Session Four
- Introduction
- Expected utility theory
- Risk aversion Attitudes towards risk
- Risk insurance
- Evaluation
Back
24I. Introduction
- a. Background
- b. Axioms for consumer behavior in uncertain
situations - 1.Complete ordering axiom
- 2.Continuity axiom
- 3.Independence axiom
- 4.Unequal probability axiom
- 5.Compound-lottery axiom
- c. Expected value
Back
25II. Expected utility theory
- a. Introduction Utility functions probability
- 1. Description
- 2. Examples
- b. Description
- c. Properties (theorems)
- d. Why expected utility is reasonable?
back
26III. Risk aversion Attitudes towards
risk(Behavior under Uncertainty) (Preference
towards risk)
- a. Introduction
- 1. Specified expected utility function
- 2. Risk Uncertainty
- b. Risk averse
- 1. Definition
- 2. Graph (fig.3.5) , (fig.3.1, 3.3
Griffiths) - (fig. 12.2 Varian)
- 3. Mathematics
- 4. Example
Continue
27III. Risk aversion Attitudes towards
risk(Behavior under Uncertainty) (Preference
towards risk)
- c. Risk neutral
- Definition
- Math
- Graph (fig. 3.1 Griffiths)
- d. Risk lover
- Definition
- Math
- Graph (fig.3.1 Griffiths) (fig. 12.2
Varian) - e. Measuring the risk premium (degree of risk)
- Definition
- Math
- Graph (fig. 3.3 Griffiths)
28IV. Risk Insurance
- a. Description
- b. Graph (fig.3.5, 3.6 Griffiths) Explain
- c. Mathematics
- 1. Introducing the model
- 2. Insurance premium
-
-
Back
29Evaluation
- 1. Example 8.4 Nicholson
- 2. Problem 8.5 Nicholson
- 3. Problem 3.2 Griffiths
- 4. Questions 3.8, 3.9, 3.10
- 5. Questions 12.2, 12.3 Varian
Back
Finish
30Fig.7.1 Varian, ch.3
Explanation
Back
31fig.7.2Varian Ch. 3
Back to11 Back to 13
Back to 113
32fig.7.3Varian Ch. 3
Back Explanation
33fig.7.4Varian Ch. 3
Back Explain
34fig.7.5Varian Ch. 3
Back
35fig.3.2aQuandt, Ch. 3
Back
36fig.3.2bQuandt Ch. 3
Back
37fig.3.3Laidler, Ch. 3
Back Explain
38 Explain 3.3Laidler Ch. 3
Back to fig Back to text
39Fig.3.4Laidler, Ch. 3
Back to 17 Explain
Back to 18
40 Explain 3.4Laidler, Ch. 3
Px? vary money income A?C respective
C.D.C
Back to 18
Back to fig Back to 17
41Fig.3.11Laidler, Ch. 3
Back Explain
42 Explain 3.11 Ladler, Ch. 3
CV the amount of income needed to buy y0-y1
units of Y since BC lie on the indifference
curves corresponding to y0 , y1
Back to fig Back to text
43Fig.14.4Varian, Ch. 3
Back to 18
Back to 19
44Fig.5.9Nicholson, Ch. 3
Back Explain
45Explain 5.9Nicholson, Ch. 3
Back to fig Back to text
46Fig.3.8Laidler, Ch. 3
Back Explain
47 Explain 3.8Laidler, Ch. 3
- A initial point
- B 2nd equilibrium
- To find a point (C) that lies on the I.C.C
that passes through A and brings about the same
satisfaction as B and is the tangency point of U
to a budget line with the slope as the first B.C
(3ll 1)
Back to fig Back to text
48Fig.3.11 Laidler, Ch. 3
Back Explain
49 Explain 3.11Laidler, Ch. 3
EVY2-Y0 the amount of income needed to buy Y2-Y0
of Y gives the consumer a gain in utility
equivalent to the one obtained moving from A to B.
Back to fig Back to text
50Q.4.17Laidler, Ch. 3
Back
51fig.3.5 Quant, Ch. 3
Back
52fig.12.2 Varian, Ch. 3
W15 W215 P .5 gamble
Explain
Back to 27
Back to 26
53fig.3.5 Griffiths Ch.3
Back Explain
54fig.3.6 Griffiths, Ch.3
Back Explain
55 Example .8.4nicholson Ch. 3
Back
56 problem 8.5Nicholson, Ch. 3
Back
57Problem 3.2Griffiths, Ch.3
Back
58Q.12.2Varian, Ch. 3
Back
59Q.12.3Varian, Ch. 3
Back
60fig.3.1 Griffiths, Ch.3
Back to 27
Back to 26
61fig.3.3 Griffiths, Ch.3
Explain
Back to 27
Back to 26
62 Problem .5.10 Nicholson, Ch. 3
Back
63a. Description
- It shows the relation between consumer demand
expenditure relations. - It clarifies the minimum subsistence quantity.
- It is useful for empirical works
- minimum subsistence quantity of Q1 ,
Q2. - It shows the share of every commodity in the U.F
the D.F. - Monotonic transformation
- Back
64b. Demand functions optimization
if
if
continue
65S.O.C
back
66Expenditure functions
- Multiply by p1 p2 gives
- They are linear income prices suitable for
linear regression system.
back
67Strongly separable utility functions
- Description
- U.F are assumed to be strictly quasi-concave,
differentiable, increasing . - A U.F is strongly separable in all of its
arguments if it can be written as
-
- F fi are increasing
- Back
68Example
back
69Properties
- - Rcs depends only upon the quantities qi qj
Back
70Weakly separable U.F
- If the variables can be partitioned in two (or
more) groups (q1 ,,qk) and (qk1 ,,qn ) such
that -
- U F f1(q1 ,,qk) f2 (qk1 ,,qn )
- RCS for pairs of variables within the same group
are unaffected by quantities for variables
outside the group. - e.g. U Ln (q1 q2 )2 v q3 q4
- Back
Back
71Description
- A U.F is strongly addictive if it can be written
as - U S fi (qi) fi is increasing
- It is a special case of seperability.
- Back
72Example
- U q1a q2ß q3?
- q2ß f2 (q2) , f2 gt 0
- Back
73Properties
- Any U.F that has a monotonic transformation
which is additive may be treated as being
additive for all theorems applicable to additive
function. e.g. Uq1a q2 is separable but not
additive but F(U)alnq1lnq2 (log-transformation)
is additive. Also the antilog of U ln(q1a q2ß
q3? ) is strongly additive. - U colog lnq1a q2 colog (Ln q1a
Ln q2 ) F(Sf i(qi)). - Continue
74- (ii) RCS q1q2 is only a function of q1 , q2.
- all cross partials are zero i.e.
- Regular strict quasi-concavity condition is
f11f12 f22f12lt 0
back
75Weakly additive U.F
- The variables can be partitioned in two
- (or more) groups (q1 ,,qk) and (qk1 ,,qn )
such that - U F f1(q1,,qk) f2 (qk1 ,,qn )
- Cross partials for pairs of commodities in
different groups are zero. - e.g. U ( q1q2 )2 vq3q4
Back
76Description
- A U.F is HDk if
- f (tq1 ,,tqn) tkf (q1,,qn)
- tgt0 , kcte
-
- Back
77Properties
- The partial derivatives of a function of HD(k)
are HD(k-1) - RCS is invariant with respect to proportionate
change in consumption levels. -
- proof
- (iii) If a consumer is indifferent between two
consumption bundles, he will be indifferent
between any other two bundles that use the same
multiple of the first pair. - back
78Description
- These properties can be exhibited for monotonic
transformation of homogeneous functions. - The U.F within this broad class, which includes
homogeneous functions are called homothetic.
Back
79Properties
- RCS will depend upon relative rather than
absolute commodity quantities. - Examination of RCS can indicate whether or not a
U.F is homothetic.
back
80Example
- is not homogeneous but is homothetic
- Since
-
Back
81Description
- It is an indirect approach to calculate
- O.D.C , C.D.C , expenditure function and
Slutsky equation. - It is more applicable than direct approach.
Back
82Dual problem shepherd lemma
- According to the envelope theorem
- Applying the envelope theorem to the expenditure
minimization problem provides the compensated
demand functions, i.e. it expresses how
compensated D.F can be derived from Exp.F - continue
83 This result sometimes called Shepherds lemma
after the economist who discovered it in the
context of input demand by firms (1953). back
84Generalization
- E (p1,, pn,U0 ) is the minimum expenditure
necessary to achieve a given level of utility
(U0). The partial derivation of expenditure
function with respect to the ith price gives the
ith compensated demand function - Shepherd's lemma
-
Continue -
85- Since the compensated demand function is
- obtained by minimizing expenditures for a
given level of U0 , change in total expenditures
that is due to a small change in a price is zero.
then -
back
86Description
- It shows how Marshallian demand functions can be
derived from the indirect utility function - Continue
(I.U.F)
87- Applying envelope theorem to the Laggrangian
form
This result is called Roys identity after its
discoverer (Roy 1942) BACK
88Generalization
- Normalizing prices
- (HDO supports this
modifications) - Continue
- 1. Ordinary demand function
89-Applying composite-function rule for
(3)Partial differentiation of (1) with
respect to
Continue
90Optimal commodity demand are related to the
derivatives of the I.U.F and the optimal value of
Lagrange multiplier. Or
Back
91Slutsky equation
At the optimal point original and dual solution
are equal. Back
92Example
- Considering the following utility function
- Calculate
- a. O.D.F, I.U.F Roys identity
- b. C.D.F, Expenditure F. Shepherd lemma
- c. Substitution effects
- d. Slutsky equation
Back
93Evaluation
- questions 3.1 , 3.2 , 3.3 , 3.4
- Problems 5.6 , 5.7 , 5.8 Nicholson
- Back
94The principles of revealed preferences
- If (x1 ,x2) is the chosen bundle when prices are
(p1, p2) , and if (y1, y2) be some other bundle
such that p1 x1 p2 x2 p1 y1 p2 y2 , then
if the consumer is choosing the most preferred
bundle she can afford, we must have - (x1 ,x2) gt (y1, y2)
- This principle is not circular, since
- i revealed preferences means that X was
chosen to Y when Y was affordable - ii Preference means that the consumer ranks
X ahead of Y. - iii Preference is the consequence of revealed
preferred - ( consumer behavior)
- iv If bundle X is chosen over Y bundle Y, then
X must be
preferred to Y.
Back
95Indirect revealed preference
- Definition if (y1, y2 ) is demanded at (q1 ,
q2) and it is revealed preferred to (z1, z2 ),
i.e. q1 y1 q2 y2 q1z1 q2 z2 , then we know
that (x1 , x2 ) gt (y1, y2 ) and (y1, y2 ) gt (z1,
z2 ), from transitivity assumption (x1 , x2 )
gt(z1, z2 ) so we say (x1 , x2 ) is indirectly
preferred to (z1, z2 ) . - If a bundle is either directly or indirectly
revealed preferred to another bundle we say that
the first bundle is revealed preferred to the
second. - (x1 , x2 ) is revealed preferred, either directly
or indirectly to all of the bundle in the shaded
area it is in fact preferred to those bundle. - The true indifference curve through (x1 , x2 )
must lie above the shaded area.
Back
96Description
- As we observe more and more choices, we can get
a better better estimate of what the consumers
preferences are like. - If we add more assumptions about consumer
preferences, we can get more precise estimate
about the shape of indifference curves. - If Y Z are revealed preferred to X, then all
of the weighted averages of Y Z are preferred
to X. and if preferences are monotonic, then all
the bundles that have more of both goods than X,
Y, Z or any of their weighted averages are also
preferred to X. Back
97Graph (fig.7.3 Varian)
- All of the bundles in the upper shaded area
better than (x1,x2) and that all the bundles in
the lower shaded area are worse than (x1,x2) . - The true indifference curve through
- must lie somewhere between the two shaded
areas.
Back
98(No Transcript)
991.Revealed preferencea. Introductionb.
Definitionc. Graph (fig .7.1 Varian )d.
Mathematicse. Generalization
Back to the main menu
100Introduction
- 1- The idea of revealed preferences was
introduced into consumer theory by Paul Samuelson
in 1938. - 2- The revealed preferences hypothesis has made
it possible to establish the law of demand by
direct observation of consumer behavior without
having to depend on the rather restrictive
assumption that we have noted as being necessary
for the use of indifference curve analysis. Since
in real life we notice the behavior. - 3- We will adopt a maintained hypothesis that the
consumers preferences are stable over the time
period for which we observe his choice behavior. - Back
101Definition
- If a consumer chooses bundle of goods A, in
preference to other bundle B,C and D, which also
available, then if none of the latter bundles is
more expensive than A, we can say that A has been
revealed preferred to the other bundles. - Back
102Explanation Fig.7.1 Varian
- (x1 , x2) a consumers demanded bundle the
optimal bundle. - (y1 , y2) an affordable bundle at the given
budget. - (x1 , x2) is better than (y1 , y2 ). This holds
for any bundle on - B.C or beneath it ( x1 , x2 ).
- - We assume unique demanded bundle by adopting
the convention that the preferences are strictly
convex. - If not , there will be more than one demanded
bundle since indifference curves have flat spots. - The shaded area is revealed worse than the
demanded bundle.
Back -
103 Mathematics
- P1y1 p2y2 m
- P1x1 p2x2 m
-
- P1x1 p2x2 P1y1 p2y2 (x1 , x2 ) is
chosen over (y1 , y2 ) - (x1, x2) is directly revealed preferred to (y1,
y2) - Revealed preference is a relation that holds
between the bundle that is actually demanded at
some budget the bundles that could have been
demanded at that budget. - It is better to say X is chosen over Y
instead of saying X is revealed preferred to Y
since inherently we have not anything to do
with preferences. - Back
104Generalization
- Commodities prices
- - If p0 q1 p0 q0 and q0 is chosen then q0 is
revealed to be
preferred to q1 - Back
105Definition
- If (x1 , x2 ) is directly revealed preferred to
(y1 , y2), and the two bundles are not the same,
then it cannot happen that (y1 , y2) is directly
preferred to (x1 , x2 ). - Back
106Explanation Figs.7.5, 7.4 Varian
- Fig.7.5 consumer choices satisfy WARP. It is
possible to find indifference curves for which
his behavior is optimal behavior. - Fig.7.4 violation to WARP if both of (x1 , x2
),(y 1,y2) - are revealed preferences. we know that
- 1- the consumer is not choosing the best bundle
he can afford. - 2- there is some other aspect of the choice
problem that has changed that we have not
observed e.g. the consumers taste or some other
aspects of his economic environment have changed.
Back
107Mathematics
- Simple case
- If (x1 , x2 ) is purchased of (f1 , f2) and a
different bundle (y1 , y2 ) is purchased ot
prices (q1 , q2 ), then if p1 x1 p2 x2 p1 y1
p2 y2 - it must not be the case that
- q1 y1 q2 y2 q1 x1 q2 x2
- If y-bundle is affordable when the x-bundle is
purchased, then when the y-bundle is purchased,
the x-bundle must not be affordable. - Back
108Generalization
- If q0 is revealed preferred to q1 , the latter
must never be revealed to be preferred to q0. - The only way in which q1 can be revealed to be
preferred to q0 is to have the consumer purchase
the combination q1 in some price situation in
which he could also afford to buy q0. - i.e. q1 is R.P to q0 if p1 q0 p1 q1 ()
- WARP states that if p0 q1 p0 q0 then () can
never hold so, if p0 q1 p0 q0 then p1 q0
p1 q1 - Back
109Checking WARP
- WARP is a condition that must be satisfied by a
consumer who is always choosing the things he can
afford. - Fig(7.1) (p1t , p2t ) the tot observation of
prices - and
- (x1t , x2t ) the tth
observation of choices. - Fig(7.2) The diagonal terms measures how much
money the consumer is spending at each choice
(aij ij ) - a31 How much the consumer would have to spend
at the third set of prices to purchase the first
bundle. - a31 lt a33 bundle one was affordable when
bundle 3 is R.P to one.
Continue
110- We put a star in the entry in row s, column t ,
if the number is that entry is less than in the
aij ij . - a22 How much the consumer actually spent at the
2nd set of prices to purchase the 2nd bundle. - A violation to WARP consists of two observations
t s such that row t , column s , contains a
star and row s , column t , contains a star.
Since this would wear that the bundle purchased
at s is revealed preferred to the bundle
purchased at t and vice versa. - a12 a21 contains a star observation 2 could
have been chosen when the consumer actually chose
observation one vise versa. - No stable preferences. Back
111Definition
- If (x1,x2) is revealed preferred to (y1,y2)
(either directly or indirectly) and (y1,y2) is
different from (x1, x2) , then (y1, y2) can not
be directly or indirectly revealed preferred to
(x1, x2). - If qo is revealed preferred to q1 which is
revealed preferred to q2 , , which is revealed
preferred to qk , qk must never be revealed
preferred to qo . - This axioms answer the transitivity of revealed
preferred. - Continue
112- SARP is a necessary sufficient condition for
optimizing behavior. If the observed choices
satisfy SARP , we can always find nice,
well-behaved preferences that could have
generated the observed choices. - back
113- F.O.C If choosing the best we can do?SARP
- S.O.C If SARP?we can find well-behaved
preferred I.C - Back Graph
114Checking SARP
- Direct revealed preferred
- Indirect revealed preferred
- If there is a situation where there is a star in
row t , column s , and also a star in row s ,
column t, then observation t is revealed
preferred to observation s , either directly or
indirectly and at the same time , observation s
is revealed preferred to t violation to SARP - Continue
115- If not , observation s are consistent with , eco.
Theory of consumer. - a12 10 1 is revealed preferred to 2
directly - a23 15 2 is revealed preferred to 3
directly - 1 is indirectly revealed preferred to 3
- a1322()
- Back
116Revealed preferences substitution effect
- The consumer is preferred to move along a given
indifference hyper face in n directions. - qo,q1 lie on the same indifference hyper face.
- If PPo he purchase qo
- If PP1 he purchase q1
- ? poqo poq1 ? po(qo-q1) 0 or -po(q1-qo)
0 - p1q1 p1qo ? p1(q1-qo) 0
- Sum (p1-po)(q1-qo) 0 ?
- back
117Evaluation
- Question 3.5
- Problem 5.9 Nicholson
- Questions 7.1 , 7.2 , 7.3 Varian
- back
118A initial equilibriumB 1nd equilibrium if px?
total effect AB a movement along P.C.CB is
also a point or an I.C.CC is another point along
I.C.C where B.C (y2x2) has the same slope and is
tangent to I.ABACCB S.EI.E
Fig.3.3 Laidler Back
The income substitution effects (Review)
119Money income real income
- O.D.C is derived holding money income Py
constant constant money income D.C - Real income is changed through income effect
- If we neglect , we will find a constant real
income curve compensated D.C - Back
120The ability to gain a particular constant level
of satisfaction from consumption compensated D.C
is derived.
Back
Constant real income
121Compensating variation (CV)
- The required change in money income just
compensates the consumer for income effects and
keep it on the initial satisfaction level, is
called compensating variation. i.e. we compensate
the welfare cost (gain) of the price change. - Back
122Expenditure function
Minimum expenditure necessary to achieve a
desired level of utility given the prices. Back
123Shepherds lemma
Back
124C.V
Nich shaded area Back
125Description
- An alternative way of analyzing the income the
substitution effect of a price change - The required change in money income just
equivalent to the income effect that keep the 2nd
utility level is called equivalent variation. It
is equal to the AC. - Back
126Mathematics
Back
127Example
128Introduction
- I.E measures the change in satisfaction or
utility as a result of a change in the price of a
good. - If ?U the gained utility because of an
equivalent variation in money income E.V - An alternative measure of the same gain is the
amount by which money income may be diminished in
order to leave the consumer just as well off as
initially (C.V). - The changes in utility we are discussing is
changes in C.S - Back
129Definition
- A consumer normally pays less for a commodity
than the maximum amount that he would pay rather
than forgo its consumption. - The difference between the actual payment of the
consumer and the potential willingness of him to
pay is called C.S. - Back
130Measurement
- (fig 4.1Laidler) (fig 3.3 , 3.4) , (fig 14.2 ,
14.3 Varian ) - C.V method
- E.V method
- Using marshallian D.
- Comparison
Back
131I. C.V method
- If we prohibit the consumption of X , how much
would we have to increase the consumers income
in order to compensate for this prohibition ? - 3.3 a 1st E D , I2 , OA M
- If Q0 ? D?A , I2?I1 , CVABcC.S
- 4.1 1st E A , I2 , oy1M
- If X0 ?A?B , I2?I1
- C.V BC y1-y0 the amount of income needed to
buy y1-y0 of y CS - Back
132II. E.V method
- Offering the consumer a choice between being
forbidden to consume X or accepting a reduction
in income. How large a reduction in income would
leave the consumer just as badly off as the
prohibition on the consumption of X. - The amount necessary to buy Y0-Y2 is
equivalent to this reduction in utility.
- Back
133III. Using marshallian D
IV. Comparison (fig 3.3.b)
Back
134Mathematics a comparative approach
The change in C.S is a rough average of the
equivalent compensating variation.
Back
135Example
5.5 Nicholson H.Q (back) D(p) 20 2p
?CS? P12 , P23
Back
136Example
Additional money needed to keep the consumer on
the same u
137 138Back
139a. Background
- The additional theory of consumer behavior does
not include an analysis of uncertain situations. - Von Neumann Morgenstain showed that under some
circumstances it is possible to construct a set
of numbers for a particular consumer that can be
used to predict his choices in uncertain
situations. - Great controversy has centered around the
question of whether the resulting utility index
is ordinal or cardinal
Continue
140- It will be shown that Von Neumann Morgenstain
utilities possess at least some cardinal
properties. - The consumer faces with a choice between two
alternatives - A choice whit certain outcome , (p1)
- He can obtain a lottery ticket with a chance of
winning a satisfactory situation (A) or an
unsatisfactory one (B) - L(P,A,B) A?B B?1-p
Back
141b. Axioms for consumer behavior in uncertainty
situations
- It is possible to construct a utility index can
be used to predict choice in uncertain situations
if the consumer conforms to the following five
axioms.
Back
1421. Complete ordering axiom
- APB or BPA or AIT completeness
- If APB BPC ?APC transitivity
Back
143 2.continuity axiom
- If APB BPC , then there exists 0ltplt1 , such
that the consumer is indifferent between B with
certainty L(P,A,C)
Back
1443. Independence axiom
- If AIB , C any outcome , L1(P,A,C) , L2(P,B,C)
?L1 I L2 - If APB , C any outcome , L1(P,A,C) , L2(P,B,C)
?L1 P L2
Back
1454. Unequal probability axiom
Back
1465. Compound-lottery axiom
- If L1(P1,A,B) , L2(P2,L3,L4) L3(P3,A,B) ,
L4(P4,A,B) L2 is a compound lottery in which the
prices are lottery tickets then L2 is equivalent
to L1 if P1 P2P3(1-P2)P4 - P2P3 the probability of obtaining A through L3
- (1-P2)P4 the probability of obtaining A through
L4 - P2P3(1-P2)P4the probability of obtaining A
through L2
Back
147c. Expected value
- E(x)P1X1 P2 X2
- Expected value in uncertain situation is a
weighted average of the values associated with
each possible outcome , Pi are the weights.
Back
148Description
- If the consumer has reasonable preferences about
consumption in difference circumstances we will
be able to use a utility function to describe
these preferences. - How a person values consumption in one state as
compared to another will depend on the
probability that the state in question will
actually occur. The preferences for
Continue
149- consumption in different states of nature will
depend on the beliefs of the individual about how
likely those states are. - In the states are mutually exclusive (rain
shine) u(C1, C2, ?1,1- ?1) if not u(C1, C2, ?1,
?2). This is a function that represent the
individuals preferences over consumption in each
state.
Back
150Examples
- Perfect substitutes u(C1, C2, ?1, ?2) ?1C1 ?2
C2 - Expected value of C1 , C2 -weighted average.
- Cobb-Douglas U.F
- Monotonic transformation
- Ln u(C1, C2, ?1, ?2) ?1Ln C1 ?2LnC2 represents
- the same preference.
Back
151Description
- If there is a utility index which conforms to the
five axioms, the expected utility for the
tow-outcome lottery L(P,A,B) is
Eu(L)Pu(A)(1-P)U(B) - Varian One convenient form of U.F might be
Continue
152- Utility is a weighted sum of some function of
consumption in each state - Perfect substitutes or expected value U.F V(c)
C - The Cobb-Douglas in logarithm V(c) LnC
- It shows the average utility or the expected
utility of the pattern of consumption (C1, C2). - It is called expected utility of the pattern or
Von-Neumann-Morgenstain U.F - The U.F has the additional form
Back
153Properties (theorems)
- Expected utility Ranking corresponds to lottery
rankings. - Expected utility monotonic transformation.
- Expected utility Increasing linear
transformation (positive affine transformation) - Expected utility and utility numbers
- Cardinal nature of expected utility
Back
154Expected utility ranking corresponds to lottery
rankings.
- If L1(P1,A1,A2) is preferred to L2(P2,A3,A4)
then EU(L1)gtEU(L2) - Proof
- We select outcomes B best ,W worst under
consideration - Continuality axioms there exist a probability
Qi such that Ai is indifferent to (Qi, B, W)
(i1, , 4)
Continue
155Compound-lottery axiom
Continue
156Unequal probability axiom
Back
157Expected utility monotonic transformation.
- For certain outcomes any positive monotonic
transformation of the utility functions leaves
the ranking of outcomes unchanged. - H.Q - for uncertain outcomes this result doesnt
hold. - U(A1)25 U(A2)64 U(A3)36 U(A4)49
- L1(0.5,A1,A2) gt L2(0.4,A3,A4) since
EU(L1)44.5gt43.8EU(L2) - But if VU.5 EV(L1)6.5lt6.6EV(L2)
Continue
158- Varian
- Any monotonic transformation of an expected
utility function is a utility function that
describes the same preferences but the additive
form representation turns out to be especially
convenient. - E.g. If the consumers preferences are
described by . But the latter doesnt have the
expected utility property, while the former dose.
Back
159Expected utility Increasing linear
transformation (positive affine transformation)
- The expected utility function can be subjected to
same kinds of monotonic transformation and still
have the expected U. property. - V(U)a(U)b , agt0
- It is not only represents the same preferences
(this is obvious since and affine transformation
is just a special kind of monotonic
transformation) but it also still has the
expected utility property.
continue
160back
161Expected utility and utility numbers
- The E.u formula may be used to construct utility
numbers for a person who conforms to the Von
Neumann Morgenstern axioms. - A2 gtA1 , U(A1)20 , U(A2)1000 A3 is between A1 ,
A2 Arbitrary assign utility numbers to two
certain incomes. - According to continuity axiom there is a
probability P such that (P, A1, A2) A3
Continue
162- If P .8 ? U (A3) .8 U (A1) 0.2U (A2)
216 - If A4 gtA2gtA3gtA1 then ask the consumer for a value
of P such that he is indifferent between A2 and
(P,A1,A4). If P .6 then - U(A2) .6 U(A1) .4 U(A4)
- 1000 .6 (20) .4 U(A4) ? U(A4) 2470
- The process can be continued indefinitely, and
will not lead to contradictory results as long as
the five axioms are obeyed.
Back
1635. Cardinal nature of expected utility
- The utilities in the Von-Neumann-Morgenstern
analysis are cardinal in a restricted sense.
Since - (i) They are derived by presenting him with
mutually exclusive choices it is meaningless to
infer from the utility of event A and the utility
of event B, the utility of the joint extent A and
B. - (ii) If U (A) KU (B) it is not meaningful to
assert that the consumer prefers A, k times as
much as B.
Continue
164- (iii) Utility ratios are not invariant under
linear transformation. -
-
- But the utility numbers provide an interval
scale, and differences between them are
meaningful (since the relative magnitudes of
differences between utility numbers are invariant
with respect to linear transformation
Back
165d. Why expected utility is reasonable?
- Why would we think that preferences over
uncertain choices would have the particular
structure implied by the expected utility
function? - The fact that outcomes of the random choice are
consumption goods that will be consumed in
different circumstances means that ultimately
only one of these outcomes is actually going to
occur. - E.g. either it will be a rainy day or a sunny
day.
Continue
166- Thus in choice under uncertainty there is a
natural kind of independence between the
different outcomes because they must be consumed
separately in different states of nature. - This assumption is known as independence
assumption. It implies that utility function for
contingent consumption will take a very special
structure it has to be additive across the
different contingent consumption bundles. i.e.
Continue
167- If C1, C2, C3 consumptions in different
states of nature and p1,p2,p3 are probabilities
that these 3 different states of nature
materialize, then U(C1, C2, C3) p1U(C1)
p2U(C2) p3U(C3) (expected U.F) - (independent of other goods)
Back
1681. Specified expected utility function
- We claimed that the expected utility function in
general had some very convenient properties for
analyzing choice under uncertainty. - It is now assumed that the utility function
- 1. has the single argument wealth
measured in monetary units - 2. is strictly increasing
- 3. is continuous with continuous first
second- order derivatives.
Back
1692. Risk uncertainty
- Although we shall often use the ideas of
uncertainty risk interchangeably, they strictly
refer to different situations. - Uncertainty refers to situations in which many
outcomes of a particular choice are possible but
the likelihood (probability) of each outcome is
unknown. - Risk It can only be measured accurately on the
assumption that we know all the possible outcomes
and the probability of each outcome occurring.
Back
1701. Definition
- He prefers a situation in which a given income
which is certain to a situation yielding the same
expected value but which involves uncertainty.
Back
1712. Mathematics
- L (P, W1, W2) ? EWPW1 (1-P)W2
- The utility of its expected value is greater than
the expected value of its utility (expected
utility of the gamble) - For all 0ltPlt1
- U PW1 (1-P)W2gtPU(W1) (1-P)U(W2)
- or UE(W)gtEU(W)
- The utility function is strictly concave over its
domain since (1) is identical to strict
concavity. - If (d2U/dw2)lt0 U.F is strictly concave he is
risk averter (Diminishing marginal utility
exists).
(1)
Back
1723. Graph (fig.3.5), (fig.3.1 Griffiths)
(fig.12.2 Varian)
- UE(W) UPW1(1-P)W2 U2.5 7.5 U(10) gt
.5 U(5) .5 U(15) PU(W1) (1-P) U(W2)
EU(W) - He currently has 10 of wealth certainly.
- The expected value of the gamble 10
E(W) 2.5 7.5 10
Back to graph Back to 27
Back to 26
1731. Definition
- He is indifferent between certain and uncertain
outcomes with the same expected value. - Constant MU along the relevant segment of the
total Uncured.
Back
1742. Mathematics
- The utility of the expected value of the game
equals the expected utility of the game.
Back
1751. Definition
- He would prefer a random distribution of wealth
to its expected value in the certain situation.
Back
1762. Mathematics
Back
1771. Definition
- It measures the amount of income that an
individual would give up to leave him indifferent
between a risky choice and a certain one.
Back
1782. Mathematics
- The sign of provides and indication of the
consumers attitude, but since it is invariant
under a linear transformation gt Not suitable. - Absolute risk aversion
- Linear transform
Continue
1792. Mathematics
- Relative risk aversion
- The willingness to pay to avoid a given gamble
depends on the individuals level of wealth. - It might be approximately constant.
Back
1803. Graph (fig.3.3 Griffiths)
- D reflects the expected value of the risky
situation (A of B P -5) - DE risk premium in that a certain income of 15
gives the same - Expected utility (U4) as the uncertain income of
2o. - The consumer is willing to give up 5 of expected
income from the - Risky choice to be indifferent between the
certain uncertain outcome. - The more risk averse, the greater R.P
Back to graph
Back to 26
Back to 27
1814. Examples
Continue
1824. Examples
- (ii) Constant risk aversion U.F
Back
183a. Description
- The essence of insurance is that in return for a
premium paid at the start of the period, some
agent guarantees to reimburse the decision maker
for any loss incurred during the period. i.e. by
paying a fee the decision maker can put him in a
position of certainty. - The trade off is as follows by reducing the
level of income (wealth) with which he or she
begins the period by the around of this fee
(insurance premium) he can guarantee that he will
end the period with the initial level of income
mines the premium.
Back
184b. Graph (fig.3.5 3.6 Griffiths)
- No insurance U(0.5, A, B) U(0.5,W1,W2)
0.5U(W1)0.5U(W2) - U(0.5W10.5W2)U3gt 0.5U(W1)0.5U(W2)U4
- U(W3)U3gtU(D)U4
- If insurance U(W3)U3
- CD V3 V4 Consumer surplus that arises from
certainty from buying insurance that would make
the wealth outcome W3 certain at the end of the
period. - W4 Certainty equivalent level of wealth to W3,
i.e. that wealth which if received with certainty
, yields the same utility (U4) as the fifty-fifty
gamble.
Continue
185- As long as the insurance premium is no more than
the difference W3 W4 (the risk premium) then
the decision maker will achieve higher utility by
insurance then by non-insurance, i.e. will be
above E on the total utility curve. - ED Maximum insurance premium that would be paid
by the decision maker given the degree of risk
aversion implied by the shape of the total
utility curve. - So long as max I.P gt minimum insurance premium
required by the insuring agent, there is
insurance market. - Risk Neautral (3.6.a) Risk Premium 0 gt No
insurance market - Risk lover (3.6.b) Risk Premium lt 0 gt No
insurance market
Back
186 c. Mathematics
- 1.Introducing the model
- Consumer faces a risk that will suffer A
dollars with P likelihood. - Equivalent to a gamble of (P, W0 A, W0).
Where W0 denotes initial wealth. - Insurance payment (Premium) R they will give
him a dollars if fire takes place. - The maximum insurance premium can be obtained by
solving - U(W0-R) U (P, W0 A, W0)
- U(W0-R) PU(W0 A) (1-P)U(W0)
Continue
187c. Mathematics
- Risk averse
- E(w0-A)P(W0-A)(1-P)W0W0- PAE(A)
- PA(1-P)(0)
- The expected value of loss PA
- If R gt PA, he buys insurance if its price is no
greater than R if the price is greater than R
gt No insurance buying despite his risk aversion - Profitability of insurance companies
gt price gt PA - In a perfect market all risk lovers, all risk
neutrals some risk averters will not buy
insurance.
Back
188c. Mathematics
- 2.Insurance premium
- Fair bet expected value of the prize is zero
- ( E(h) 0)
- P Size of insurance premium fair bet (h)
paying P with certainty to avoid gamble - EU(wh) U(w-p)
- Expanding by Taylors series
Continue
1892.Insurance premium
The amount that a risk averse is willing to pay
to avoid a fair bet is proportional to Pratts
risk aversion measure.
Back
190Fig.4.8 Laidler, ch.3
Back
191Fig.5.10 Nicholson, ch.3
Back
190
192The End Of Chapter III