First-Order Logic - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

First-Order Logic

Description:

This includes the objects presumed or hypothesized to exist in the world and ... Objects can be concrete (book, earth, ... We can think of as a big disjunction. ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:40
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 31
Provided by: tho9
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: First-Order Logic


1
First-Order Logic
2
Conceptualization
  • The formalization of knowledge begins with a
    conceptualization.
  • This includes the objects presumed or
    hypothesized to exist in the world and their
    relationships.
  • An object can be anything about we want to say
    something.
  • Objects can be concrete (book, earth, sun, etc)
  • Objects can be abstract (the number 2, the set of
    all integers, the justice etc)
  • Objects can be primitive or composite (a circuit
    that contains many circuits)
  • Objects can be fictional (Sherlock Holmes, Miss
    Right)
  • A knowledge-representation task doesnt require
    that we consider all the objects in the world
    only those objects in a particular set are
    relevant.
  • The set of objects about which knowledge is being
    expressed is called a universe of discourse.

3
Example Blocks World
A
B
D
C
E
  • Here we conceptualize the blocks. Some could
    conceptualize also the table, but we ignore it.
  • The universe of discourse corresponding to this
    conceptualization is
  • A,B,C,D,E
  • Although in this example the universe of
    discourse is finite, this is not always the case.
  • E.g. it is common in math to consider as the
    universe of discourse the set of all integers,
    the set of all real numbers etc.

4
More about Conceptualization I
  • A function is a kind of interrelationship among
    the objects in a universe of discourse.
  • Although we can define many functions for a given
    set of objects, in conceptualizing a portion of
    the world we usually emphasize some functions and
    ignore others.
  • The set of functions emphasized in a
    conceptualization is called the functional basis
    set.
  • E.g. in our blocks world, it would make sense to
    define a (partial) function Hat that maps a block
    into the block on top of it, if such exists. The
    tuples corresponding to this function are
  • ltB,Agt, ltC,Bgt, ltE,Dgt

5
More about Conceptualization II
  • A relation is the second kind of
    interrelationship among the objects in a universe
    of dicourse.
  • The set of relations emphasized in a
    conceptualization is called the relational basis
    set.
  • E.g. in our blocks world, we can consider the On
    relation
  • ltA,Bgt, ltB,Cgt, ltD,Egt
  • Also, we can consider the Above relation
  • ltA,Bgt, ltB,Cgt, ltA,Cgt, ltD,Egt
  • More, we can consider the unary Clear relation
  • ltAgt, ltDgt
  • Or, the unary Table relation
  • ltCgt, ltEgt

6
Formally
  • A conceptualization is a triple consisting of
  • a universe of discourse,
  • a functional basis set for that universe of
    discourse and
  • a relational basis set.
  • E.g. ltA,B,C,D,E, Hat, On,Above,Clear,Tablegt
  • No matter how we choose to conceptualize the
    world, there are other conceptualizations as
    well.
  • What makes a conceptualization more appropriate
    than another for knowledge formalization?

7
Reification
  • E.g. consider a Blocks World conceptualization in
    which there are five blocks, no functions, and
    there are three unary relations
  • ltA,B,C,D,E, , Red,White,Bluegt
  • This conceptualization allows us to consider the
    color of blocks but not the properties of colors.
  • In order to overcome this, we reify the relations
    and have instead the conceptualization
  • ltA,B,C,D,E, Red,White,Blue, Color, Nicegt
  • The advantage of this is that it allows us to
    consider properties of of properties.

8
First-Order Logic
  • Given a conceptualization of the world, we begin
    to formalize knowledge in a language appropriate
    to that conceptualization.
  • E.g. we can express the fact that the block A is
    above block B by taking a relation symbol such as
    above and object symbols a and b and writing
  • above(a,b)
  • We can combine sentences by using logical
    operators (?,?,?,?,?,?) in order to create more
    complex sentences.
  • above(a,b) ? above(b,a)
  • The names we use, such as above, a, b are
    irrelevant.
  • We could have said
  • abnwyrcn(pjkj, oiuy) ? abnwyrcn(oiuy, pjkj)
  • What really matters is that they should should
    have identifiable referents in the real world,
    (better saying in the conceptualization that we
    choose)

9
Syntax
10
Constants
  • Constants refer to objects, functions and
    relationships.
  • joe, mary, loves, happy,
  • Simple sentences express relationships among
    objects.
  • loves(joe,mary)
  • They are called atoms.
  • Compound sentences capture relationships among
    relations.
  • loves(x,y) Þ loves(y,x)
  • loves(x,y) Ù loves(y,x) Þ happy(x)
  • Relations can be unary as well.
  • tall(amy)

11
Lets blur the distinction
  • Constants refer to objects, functions and
    relationships.
  • joe, mary, loves, happy, hat
  • Ok, in order to be formal we should use object
    constant, function constant, and relation
    constant, but this is painful.
  • So, lets say for
  • Object constant object
  • Function constant function
  • Relation constant relation
  • It should be clear that the ones on the left are
    different from ones on the right We are doing
    this for the ease of presentation.

12
Example with Functions
E.g. Quincy loves his dog. loves(quincy, dog_of
(quincy)) Note We are allowed to relate
sentences only. So, we can say loves(quincy,
dog_of (quincy)) Ù loves(quincy, cat_of
(quincy)) But not, loves(quincy, dog_of
(quincy) Ù cat_of (quincy)) because dog_of
(quincy), cat_of (quincy) arent sentences, they
are objects.
  • E.g. How about saying that Jimmy Durante has a
    big nose?
  • durante is an object and
  • nose_of (durante)
  • is a function that constructs an object from the
    argument object.
  • Then, we can write
  • big(nose_of (durante))

13
Full-blown First-Order Logic ?,?
  • The language that we have described so far,
    consisting of atoms and the connectives
    (?,?,?,?,?,?) is typically called predicate
    logic.
  • To extend it to first-order logic, we need to add
    quantifiers.
  • The purpose of quantifiers is to allow us to say
    things about sets of objects.
  • To say that Quincy loves everything we write
  • ?x. loves (quincy, x)
  • We can think of ? as a big conjunction. For
    example, if there are only three objects quincy,
    dog, and cat, what the above asserts is
  • loves (quincy, dog) ? loves (quincy, cat) ?
    loves (quincy, quincy)
  • To say that Quincy loves something we write
  • ?x. loves (quincy, x)
  • We can think of ? as a big disjunction. For
    example, if there are only three objects as
    above, then what we are asserting is
  • loves (quincy, dog) ? loves (quincy, cat) ?
    loves (quincy, quincy)

14
Mushrooms
  • The universe of discourse is the set of all
    plants.
  • There is a unary relation for being mushroom,
    another one for being purple, and a third for
    being poisonous.
  • We designate these relations with the unary
    relation symbols mushroom, purple, and poisonous.
  • All purple mushrooms are poisonous.
  • ?x (purple(x) ? mushroom(x) ? poisonous(x))
  • A mushroom is poisonous only if it is purple.
  • ?x (mushroom(x) ? poisonous(x) ? purple(x))
  • No purple mushroom is poisonous.
  • ?x ?(purple(x) ? mushroom(x) ? poisonous(x))
  • There is exactly one mushroom.
  • ?x mushroom(x) ? (?y y?x ? ?mushroom(y))

15
Reverse translation
  • Translate the following into English.
  • ?x hesitates(x) ? lost(x)
  • He who hesitates is lost.
  • ??x business(x) ? like(x,Showbusiness)
  • There is no business like show business.
  • ??x glitters(x) ? gold(x)
  • Not everything that glitters is gold.
  • ?x ?t person(x) ? time(t) ? canfool(x,t)
  • You can fool some of the people all the time.

16
Semantics
17
Models
  • This is all well and good, but there isnt much
    value to saying what sentences belong to a
    language unless we also say what those sentences
    mean.
  • Simply said, we are interested in the truth value
    of given (possibly compound) sentences.
  • Suppose that our first-order language had no
    logical connectives at all, just objects,
    functions, and relations.
  • In that case, the sentences in our language would
    be simply what we called atoms.
  • Let, A be the set of all atoms in our
    impoverished language.
  • A model M is a subset of the set of atoms A.
  • By a model M ? A, we will mean the state of
    affairs in which all of the atoms in M are true
    and all of the atoms not in M are false.
  • Given a model it is obviously straightforward to
    decide whether or not some particular atom a is
    true in M its true if a?M and false if a?M.
  • What makes first-order logic powerful, is that we
    can also determine whether compound sentences are
    true or false in M.

18
Example
  • Suppose that Tom is our only object, and that we
    have two relations, rich and poor.
  • Now,
  • A rich(tom), poor(tom)
  • is the set of all atoms. So, we have 4 possible
    models.
  • In M1?, Tom is neither rich nor poor.
  • In M2rich(tom), Tom is rich and not poor.
  • In M3poor(tom), tom is poor and not rich.
  • In M4rich(tom), poor(tom), Tom is both rich
    and poor.
  • Now, consider the sentence
  • poor(tom) ? ?rich(tom)
  • Using the truth table for the implication, the
    above sentence will be true in M1, M2, M3 and
    false only in M4. (try it)

19
Entailment
  • Definition.
  • Given two sentences ? and ?, we will say that ?
    entails ?, writing ? ?, if ? holds in every
    model that ? holds.
  • Example Consider
  • ?? (???) ?
  • For any sentences ? and ?, any model M in which
    ?? (???) holds is model in which ? holds and also
    a model in which ??? holds.
  • But since ? holds in M, it must be the case that
    ? holds in M as well.
  • By the definition of entailment, the claim
    follows.

20
Entailment II
  • A set of premises logically entails a conclusion
    if and only if every interpretation that
    satisfies the premises also satisfies conclusion.
  • In the case of Propositional Logic, the number of
    interpretations is finite, and so it is possible
    to check logical entailment directly in finite
    time.
  • In the case of Relational Logic, the number of
    models is infinite, and so a direct check of
    logical entailment is not feasible.

21
Example
  • p(a)
  • q(a)
  • p(a),q(a)
  • p(b)
  • q(b)
  • p(b),q(b)
  • p(a), p(b)
  • p(a), p(b), q(a)
  • p(a), p(b), q(b)
  • p(a), p(b), q(a), q(b)
  • ...
  • Infinitely many models.

22
Good News
  • Given any set of sentences, there is a specially
    defined subset of interpretations called Herbrand
    interpretations.
  • Under certain conditions, checking just the
    Herbrand models suffices to determine logical
    entailment.
  • Checking just the Herbrand interpretations is
    less work than checking all interpretations.

23
Herbrand
  • The Herbrand universe for a set of sentences is
    the set of all ground terms that can be formed
    from just the constants used in those sentences.
  • Ground terms are either object constants or
    functions applied to object constants.
  • The Herbrand base for a set of sentences is the
    set of all ground atomic sentences that can be
    formed using just the elements in the Herbrand
    universe.
  • A Herbrand model for a set of sentences is any
    subset of the Herbrand base for those sentences.

24
Example
  • Sentences
  • "x. (r(a,x) Þ r(x,b))
  • "x."y."z. (r(x,y) Ù r(x,y) Þ r(x,z))
  • Herbrand Universe (constants used in sentences
    only)
  • a,b
  • Herbrand Base
  • r(a,a), r(a,b), r(b,a), r(b,b)

25
Herbrand Models
  • r(a,a)
  • r(a,b)
  • r(b,a)
  • r(b,b)
  • r(a,a), r(a,b)
  • r(a,a), r(b,a)
  • r(a,a), r(b,b)
  • r(a,b), r(b,a)
  • r(a,b), r(b,b)
  • r(b,a), r(b,b)
  • r(a,a), r(a,b), r(b,a)
  • r(a,a), r(a,b), r(b,b)
  • r(a,a), r(b,a), r(b,b)
  • r(a,b), r(b,a), r(b,b)
  • r(a,a), r(a,b), r(b,a), r(b,b)
  • 16 Herbrand interpretations in all. Note 16lt.

26
Herbrand Theorem
  • Herbrand Theorem A set of (pure) ?-free
    sentences is satisfiable if and only if it has a
    Herbrand model that satisfies it.
  • Proof.
  • If a set of ?-free sentences is satisfiable, then
    there is a model that satisfies it.
  • Take the intersection of this model with the
    Herbrand base. This is a Herbrand model.
  • Moreover, it is easy to see that it satisfies the
    sentences.
  • If the sentences contain variables, the instances
    must all be true, including those in which the
    variables are replaced only by elements in the
    Herbrand universe.
  • Note. With ?-free we mean pure ?-free. E.g.
    ??p(x), is nothing else but ??p(x). So, pure
    ?-free no negations preceding ?.

27
Example
  • Premises
  • ?x. p(x) Þ q(x)
  • p(a) Ú q(a)
  • Conclusion
  • q(a)
  • Herbrand Models
  • p(a)
  • q(a)
  • p(a),q(a)

28
Herbrand Method
  • Add negation of conclusion to the premises to
    form the satisfaction set.
  • Loop over Herbrand interpretations. Cross out
    each interpretation that does not satisfy the
    sentences in the satisfaction set.
  • If all Herbrand interpretations are crossed out,
    by the Herbrand Theorem, the set is
    unsatisfiable.
  • Sound and Complete Negating the conclusion leads
    to a contradiction therefore, the premises
    logically entail the conclusion.
  • Termination Since there are only finitely many
    Herbrand interpretations, the process halts.

29
Example
  • Premises
  • ?x. p(x) Þ q(x)
  • p(a) Ú q(a)
  • Conclusion
  • q(a)
  • Satisfaction Set
  • ?x. p(x) Þ q(x)
  • p(a) Ú q(a)
  • Øq(a)
  • Herbrand Models
  • p(a)
  • q(a)
  • p(a),q(a)
  • By considering ? as a big conjunction we can
    verify that the satisfaction set is unsatisfiable
    in each Herbrand model.

30
Herbrand for the rest of FOL
  • In the presence of function constants, all ground
    functional terms are included.
  • E.g. if we find in our sentences a,b,f,g then the
    Herbrand universe is
  • a, b, f(a), f(b), g(a), g(b), f(f(a)), f(f(b)),
    f(g(a)), f(g(b)), ...
  • Sad The size of the Herbrand universe for a
    functional language is infinite.
  • Upshot Checking the Herbrand models for a
    language to determine logical entailment is not
    feasible in finite time.
  • Solution Use formal proofs!
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com