Title: Financial Intermediation
1Financial Intermediation
- Lecture 7
- Decision-Making Under Uncertainty
2Contents of this chapter
- The difference between certainty and uncertainty
- Decision making under uncertainty
- Theory of expected utility
- Stochastic dominance and risk attitude
- Mean-variance analysis as an example
3Certainty versus uncertainty
- A set of feasible actions a. S set of
possible states of the world s, C set of
consequences c c f(s,a) - If f is constant with respect to the state of the
world (the state of the world does not influence
the consequence which arises) decision with
respect to a is certain. If f is not constant
uncertainty!
4Example
?
?
?p?(l)-wl
?(l)
?(s2,l)
0
l
l
0
certainty
?(s1,l)
uncertainty
5Decision making under uncertainty
- States of the world are uncertain model this by
a probability measure on S (see next slide for a
definition) - Choice of an action can be seen as (1) choice of
a state-dependent outcome, or (2) the choice of a
probability distribution of outcomes
6Probability measure
- E an event which is a subset of the states of
the world E?S. ? is a set of well-behaved subsets
(say intervals or unions) of events is called a
sigma algebra - A probability measure is a mapping ? ??? with
the properties (1) ?(E )? 0 for all E ? ?, (2)
?(S) 1, (3) if Fi ? ?, i 1,2,3,.. and Fi ? Fj
? for all i,j (i?j), then ?(?iFi) ?i?(Fi) - A triple (S, ?, ?) is a probability space
7Example 1
- Rain s1 and sunshine s2 are the relevant states
- Ss1,s2 set of states
- ??,s1,s2,s1,s2 set of events
(sigma-algebra) - ?(?) 0, ?(s1) ½ ?(s2) and ?(S)
1 is a probability measure
8Example 2
- Suppose we have a distribution function G(x)
(e.g. the exponential or normal distribution).
The probability space defined by this
distribution can be described by - S ? state space
- ? any interval and its complement sigma
algebra - ?( (a,b) ) G(b) - G(a) for any a ? b
probability measure. Sometimes we see the
support of a measure the smallest subset of S
with measure 1
9How do we represent uncertain outcomes? A lottery
- Let S si, i 1,.,T be a finite set of
outcomes - Let pi be the nonnegative probability of
occurrence of si with ?pi 1 - A lottery is a vector (s1,p1s2,p2,.sT,pT)
- We can represent a lottery by (p1,,pT)
- Example for S 3 we have a lottery (p1,p3) in ?2
10Example representation of a lottery
p3
1
p31-p2-p1
p1
0
1
11Alternative representation in terms of
consequences
- In the previous slide we denoted the lottery in
terms of the interrelation between probabilities
of various states - We can also denote the lottery in terms of
outcomes in the space of consequences - Take a two by two example c1 and c2 are
functions of two actions a1 and a2
12Lottery in terms of consequences
c2
c2(a2)
c2(a1)
0
c1
c1(a1)
c1(a2)
13Expected utility
- A decision maker can see a specific choice as a
state-contingent outcome or as a probability
distribution - But how should one order either the
state-contingent outcomes or the probability
distributions over outcomes? - Utility theory gives the answers
14Preferences
- Suppose there is a finite set CSc1,.,cs. If
preferences on the set CS satisfy completeness,
transitivity and continuity they can be
represented by a utility function V(c1,..,cs)
c2
V2
V1
c1
0
15Properties
- Completeness requires the ordering to order any
pair of probability distributions - Transitivity if the decision maker prefers p
over q and q over r she will prefer p over r - Continuity no abrupt changes of preferences for
probability distributions
16Probabilities
- Each action determines a vector of probabilities
from the set ?n(p1,,pn)?pi1 with
piprob(s?Sf(s,a)ci) - One can have a preference ordering of such
probability distributions. If preferences are
complete, transitive and continuous they can be
represented by U(p1,,pn)
17Probabilities (2)
p3
1
U1
U1gtU2gtU3
U2
U3
c3 is the most preferred outcome the utility
curves increase in the direction of p3
1
p1
0
18Expected utility
- One additional assumption independence of
preferences - Expected utility representation in probabilities
U(p1,,pn) ?piu(ci), or in state-contingent
outcomes V(c1,,cn) ?piu(ci). Note that there
is a linearity. This linearity property changes
some things
19The consequences of linearity
- Suppose we have a set of lotteries with three
outcomes x1,x2,x3 and u(x1) gt
u(x2) gt u(x3). We describe these lotteries by
(p1, p2, p3) the probabilities of outcomes x1,
x2, x3 . p2 1 - p1 - p3 - Up1 u(x1) p2 u(x2) p3 u(x3) for various U.
- So p3 U - u(x2)/(u(x3) - u(x2)) -
u(x1) - u(x2)/(u(x3) - u(x2)) p1
20Indifference curves of the utility function over
probabilities
p3
u(c1) gt u(c2) gt u(c3)
1
1
p1
21Indifference curves for state-contingent outcomes
c2
dc2/dc1 -p1.u(c1)/p2.u(c2) for all 450
tangent slopes
-p1/p2
c1
0
22Continuous time linear adding up changes to
integrals
- g(c) is a density function
- G(c) is a distribution function
23First-order stochastic dominance
- If F(x) ? G(x) for all x ? C the probability
distribution F dominates G according to
first-order stochastic dominance
For each probability F has a higher pay-off
Probability
G
F
x
0
24Second-order stochastic dominance
- If ?xF(y)dy ? ?xG(y)dy for all x ? C, F dominates
G according to second-order stochastic dominance. - So the surface under the distribution function F
up to x should be smaller than for G for all x - A SSD-dominant distribution will have less mass
in its tails (more concentrated around the mean) - So SSD can be used to rank distributions with
equal means according to their riskiness
25Example
- Suppose we have to risk classes H and L
- Both have equal means, so there is no observable
difference in returns - But there is SSD of the distribution of returns
of H over L the riskiness of class L is larger
26Risk attitudes
- u(x) is linear risk neutral, risk premium 0
- u(x) is concave risk averse, risk premium is
positive - u(x) is convex risk loving, risk premium is
negative
27Risk aversion
u(x)
1-2 certainty equivalent
3
2-3 risk premium
2
1
x
28Measures of risk aversion
- Absolute risk aversion Ra(x) -u(x)/u(x)
- Relative risk aversion Rr(x) -x.u(x)/u(x)
- Constant absolute risk aversion (CARA) example
u(x) exp(?x) - Certainty equivalent ? - 1/2Ra?2
29Application Mean-variance analysis risk aversion
- Suppose we have a wealth variable W with expected
value ? and variance ?2. Utility is represented
by U(W) aW2W for a lt 0 and W lt -1/2a. Ra(W)
-2a / (2aW1)
u(W)
0
W
30A risk averse portfolio manager
- Reduces the variance for a certain return
- Suppose that a number of risky assets can give a
certain market return - Combination with a riskless asset gives an
income line - It depends on the shape of the utility function
which point is optimal
31Mean variance analysis
?W
u(W)
Wealth restriction
?W
0
32Summary
- Distinction between certainty and uncertainty
- Expected utility theory provides a means to order
preferences - Properties of distribution functions and utility
functions - Risk aversion applies to portfolio analysis