Title: pragmatics
1pragmatics
from utterance to understanding
Any observation of normal conversational behavior
makes it immediately clear that people never say
exactly what they mean, and people always infer
more than what was said. The question becomes,
how are we able to accomplish this? How do we
manage to say so little yet communicate so much?
How do we communicate in spite of a languages
limitations?
2Some incomplete messages
- Wanna get a bite?
- Have you got the time?
- Q Wheres Mikey?
- A There was an accident on H-2.
- Q Wanna get a beer?
- A I got a paper due tomorrow.
- A Its my girlfriends birthday.
- A Im broke.
3communication as a joint activity
Clark begins to answer these questions by looking
at communication as an example of a joint
activity. These are activities in which persons
are seen as collaborating in order to accomplish
some action or goal of mutual concern. The goal
of communication is to establish a level of
understanding sufficient to serve some secondary
purpose.
4The construal problem
Clark claims that in order to establish
understanding via communication we must resolve
the construal problem. This refers to the
establishing of some agreement as to what each
party intends by what they have said. We rarely
do this via explicit and effortful communicative
behavior. However we do assume that our
communicative partner is behaving cooperatively.
5The cooperative principle
Grice dealt with our ability to find meaning
beyond the surface meaning of an utterance by
invoking a cooperative principle which states
that one should Make your conversational
contribution such as is required, at the stage at
which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or
direction of the talk exchange in which you are
engaged.
6conversational implicatures
According to Grice, one way in which we are able
to mean more than we say (i.e., activate more
meaning than was evident in a surface analysis of
an utterance) is by using conversational
implicatures and appropriate inference-making.
7Properties of conversational implicatures
Conversational implicatures have three main
characteristics
- They are non-conventional.
- The implicature is not a logical consequence of
the utterance. - They are calculable.
- It is assumed that the hearer will be able to
figure out the intended meaning. - The are defeasible.
- The speaker can cancel or opt out of the
implicature.
8conversational maxims
- Grice claimed that adhering to the cooperative
principle would manifest in people following four
maxims - Quantity -- Make your contribution as
informative as is required. - Quality -- Try to make your contribution true,
one for which you have adequate evidence. - Manner -- Be clear. Avoid ambiguity and
obscurity. - Relation -- Make your contribution relevant for
the exchange.
9Adhering to conversational maxims
- Following the maxims need not be obvious.
Cooperation is assumed consequently
communicators must figure out how utterances are
consistent with the maxims. For instance a
communicator may flout a maxim. Flouting refers
to violating a maxim so blatantly (i.e.,
apparently committing a quality violation) that
any reasonable person knows the utterance is not
intended to be taken at face value.
10deception and implicature
What constitutes deception? Most theorists define
deception as bringing about in another a belief
that one does not personally believe. In short,
getting you to believe X even though I dont
believe X. Most deception theorists identify
roughly four methods of bringing about deception
(i.e., four deception types) fabrication,
denial, omission, and exaggeration. The problem
is only the first two actually involve what is
commonly perceived as lying. The latter two can
lead to deception without any untruths being
told. So why and how are they deceptive?
11information manipulation theory (imt)
Steve McCornack argued that what people commonly
called deception was a function of Grices
conversational maxims. Specifically, McCornack
argued that covert violations of the maxims would
be perceived as deceptive. Remember, flouts
appear to be violations of maxims but they are
designed to be overt. So McCornack argued that
the failure to adhere to a maxim in a manner that
was meant to go undetected would be seen as an
attempt to produce a deception.
12information manipulation theory
McCornack et al., (1992) tested IMT by having
research participants read a scenario in which
one of the stimuli persons told something to
another that covertly violated a maxim. In one
scenario the person was completely disclosive
(i.e., honest). Then the participants rated the
degree of honesty of the stimulus person. Not
surprisingly (and consistent with hypotheses)
complete disclosure was rated as most honest and
all of the violations were perceived to be
significantly less honest than complete
disclosure.
13information manipulation theory
The honest ratings of the maxim violations were
particularly interesting.
- Complete disclosure 21.88
- Quantity violation 16.78
- Clarity violation 13.70
- Relevance violation 11.71
- Quality violation 6.99
Each of the ratings were significantly different
from the others.
14information manipulation theory
The results are supportive of IMT but they raise
a new question of theoretical significance Why
are the various maxim violations perceived as
differing in terms of honesty/deceptiveness? If
deceptiveness were simply a function of covertly
violating a maxim, each of the violations should
have been perceived as equally deceptive. Yet
they are systematically different. Why?
15explaining degrees of deceptiveness
Consider the specific and ordered differences
across the honesty attributions. From least
deceptive to most deceptive they are ordered
quantity violation, clarity violation, relevance
violation, quality violation. What might explain
our perceptions that each of these maxim
violations is rated as significantly more
deceptive than the next violation? Ask the
questions, how was the deception accomplished?
who is to blame for the targets being deceived?
16communicative responsibility theory
Aune (1998) introduced a theory of communicative
responsibility (CRT) that begins with three
simple assumptions
- Communicators believe the primary goal of
communication is to create a desired state of
understanding between themselves. - The degree to which they hold themselves and
their communicative partners responsible for
creating this state of understanding is variable.
- Judgments of communicative responsibility will
affect communicative behavior.
17communicative responsibility theory
CRT builds on Grices theory of conversational
implicature by addressing the question how do we
know how implicit/explicit to be in any
conversation? A message of a given level of
explicitness can seem oblique in one setting,
appropriate in another, and condescending in yet
another. Interrogation can be appropriate in a
journalistic setting but inappropriate between a
boyfriend and girlfriend in casual conversation.
18communicative responsibility theory
Communicative responsibility (CR) can be
described using two continua, one for each
communicator in an interaction. Two continua must
be use because they can vary independently. This
leads to two dimensions used to describe CR in a
communicative event
- Degree of symmetry in participants communicative
responsibility - Magnitude of each communicators CR.
19communicative responsibility theory
How does CR affect communicative behavior?
- As personal assessments of CR increase,
communicators will engage in less implicating and
less inference-making. - As personal assessments of ones CR increase, one
will increase the extent to which one is being
explicit in message encoding.
20communicative responsibility theory
So a message source can be expected to
- increase the use of redundancy via
- repetition of information
- creation of associations among units of
information - incorporation of additional codes and media
- increase the amount of information offered.
Conversely, increases in CR will lead receivers
to solicit more redundancy of the forms described
above.
21communicative responsibility theory
Several aspects of a communicative situation can
produce variance in judgments of CR.
- Locus of Meaning the extent to which meaning is
seen to reside in one person is associated with
that persons CR - Common Ground the extent to which communicators
believe they share relevant knowledge. - Communicators Ingroup-based Norms.
22communicative responsibility theory
- Perceived ability of the participants to process
the message - How fully articulated the meaning is
- The extent to which the meaning can be presented
in a commonly shared code - The extent to which communicative participants
are believed to be familiar with the code. - Motivation to Create Understanding
23research support for Crt
Several studies have been conducted to test the
predictions made by CRT. The first study tested
whether people do, in fact, systematically assign
levels of CR to communicative participants.
Research participants read pairs of scenarios
that were designed to differ in how symmetrically
distributed CR would be between the communicators
in the scenarios.
24research support for Crt
- Jordan is studying for a midterm with a group of
friends. She is trying to explain one of the most
important theories to the group. Jordan believes
she understands the theory and is confident that
she can explain it well to others. (asymmetric
CR) - Jordan is studying.understands the theory but
she is not so sure she can explain it to somebody
else. (symmetric CR)
25research support for Crt
- James is giving directions to Chris on how to get
to Johns house. James has been to Johns house
numerous time before but Chris has never been
there. (asymmetric CR) - James and Chris are looking at a map and
discussing the best way to get to Johns house.
Neither James nor Chris have been to Johns house
before. (symmetric CR)
26research support for Crt
Ten pairs of scenarios were tested. The perceived
CR was assessed for each character in the
scenario. A difference score was created by
subtracting the CR score of the character
expected to have the lower responsibility from
the CR score of the character expected to have
the higher responsibility. A positive number
would indicate that the character we expected to
have more CR was indeed perceived by research
participants as having higher CR.
27research support for Crt
In 8 of the 10 scenarios the difference score was
positive and 7 of these scores were significantly
different (i.e., probably not due to chance).
These results provide evidence that we do make
judgments of communicators communicative
responsibility. But.do our judgments of
communicative responsibility affect the way we
communicate?
28research support for Crt
A second study was conducted to assess whether
judgments of CR affect communicative behavior.
Research participants were asked to give
directions based on a map of a fictitious town
to a stranger who was described as another UH
student (i.e., culturally similar condition) or a
student from University of Pretoria, South Africa
( i.e., culturally dissimilar condition). We were
testing the effect of perceived common ground
(i.e., shared knowledge) on CR and subsequent
communicative behavior. We expected that
29research support for Crt
- Hypothesis Perceived personal CR would be higher
for the person in the culturally dissimilar
condition. - Results Participants giving directions to the
South Africa student rated their CR significantly
higher than did participants giving directions to
the UH student.
30research support for Crt
- Hypothesis Higher CR would lead to increases in
message redundancy and elaboration. - Results A significant positive correlation was
found between participants personal CR and the
length of the directions (i.e., number of words
used). - Additional support A significant negative
correlation was found between the type-token
ration (i.e., ration of unique words to total
words) and CR, indicating greater repetition.
31research support for Crt
Last, after controlling for the total number of
words used, a significant correlation was found
between judgments of personal CR and the number
of references to natural landmarks. This shows
that higher CR participants were making reference
to more generalizable information. In sum, CR
was shown to vary in a systematic fashion and
that judgments of CR had both quantitative and
qualitative effects on one communicative
behavior.
32research support for Crt
The studies reviewed so far demonstrate that we
do form systematic judgments of CR and that these
judgments affect our communicative behavior. The
final study was designed to examine how we
respond to anothers violation of our judgment of
his/her CR. Specifically we exposed research
participants to conversation scenarios that were
created to be interrogation-appropriate or
interrogation-inappropriate.
33research support for Crt
We developed a dialogue involving Anna and
Mike in which Anna interrogates Mike as to his
previous evenings social behavior, i.e., who did
he go out with? what did he do? where did he
go? However, we manipulated the communicative
context. In one case Anna and Mike were
girlfriend/boyfriend having lunch
(interrogation-inappropriate condition). In the
other situation Anna was an Anthropology
professor who was researching recreational
behavior of college students. Mike was a research
participant (interrogation-appropriate).
34research support for Crt
We assessed perceptions of Mikes and Annas CR
and how inappropriate the communicative behavior
was perceived to be. Results showed that
- Anna/anth was judged higher in CR than was
Anna/gf. - Mike/bf was judged slightly higher in CR than was
Mike/subj. - Anna/gfs behavior was seen as more inappropriate
than was Anna/anths. - Mike/bfs behavior was seen as slightly less
appropriate than was Mike/anth/s.
35Politeness and language production
Communicative responsibility provides one
explanation for the extent to which we engage in
implicature and inference-making in conversation.
Another explanation can be found in Politeness
Theory. The main proponents, Brown Levinson,
draw heavily from Goffmans writings on Face
Work. Face is the positive social value a person
effectively claims for himself by the line others
assume he has taken during a particular contact.
36Politeness and language production
Brown Levinson see two aspects to face
positive face the desire for connection with
others and negative face the desire for
autonomy. We may engage in face work to
accomplish positive and negative face
needs. Face needs enter into communicative
situations and affect our behavior not only
because our own face needs affect our behavior
but because we infer others face needs and
adjust our behavior accordingly.
37Politeness and language production
Consider, for example, a compliment. When we
offer a compliment we may feel it adds to our
positive face needs and the person to whom we
offer the compliment. On the other hand, a
compliment can threaten a receivers negative
face needs by making him/her feel obligated to
respond in a similar manner, thus imposing on
that person. Similarly requests are inherently
face threatening both to the speaker and the
hearer.
38types of face threats
39Politeness STRATEGIES
So we have an inherent conflict in every
communicative situation we want to manage each
others face needs at the same time we want to
perform social acts that are inherently face
threatening. In fact we could think of politeness
as any deviation from Grices Cooperative
Principle given that politeness involves
deviations from maximal communicative efficiency.
Brown Levinson offer a typology of five
superstrategies that range on a continuum from
very impolite to very polite.
40Politeness STRATEGIES
- Bald-on-record
- Positive Politeness
- Claim common ground
- Convey cooperation
- Fulfill hearers wants
- Negative Politeness
- Conventional indirectness
- Avoid assumptions
- Avoid coercion
- Communicate desire to avoid impingement
- Incur a debt
- Off-record Politeness (face threatening act must
be inferred) - Violate conversational maxims
- Quality
- Quantity
- Manner
- Relation
41Speech Act Theory
Debate used to rage over what an utterance
meant. Attempts were made to impose
truth-conditional approaches on language. That
works for 336 or other forms of reasoning
such as All Xs are Ys. B is an X, therefore B
is a Y. But linguistic utterances often dont
mean something definitive.
42Speech Act Theory
A truth value could be determined for the
following utterance It is raining
outside. But not for this utterance I
apologize for what I said. John Austin referred
to the latter as a performative utterance and the
former as a constative utterance.
43Speech Act Theory
The rain utterance could be assessed as true or
false but the apology utterance could, at best,
misfire or be infelicitous (i.e., basically
fail to work properly). In other words, the
apology utterance may not be seen as sincere,
it may not be well-formed or well-stated, or it
may not count as an apology. Consider Clyde
Arakawas apology for manslaughter Im sorry
for what happened. A well-formed apology should
indicate acceptance of responsibility for the
offending action and sincere regret for the
action.
44Speech Act forces
A speech act is described in terms of three
forces associated with any communicative
utterance
- Locutionary force the actual utterance what is
spoken and heard. - Illocutionary force what the speaker intends by
the utterance the intended meaning to be
activated by the utterance. - Perlocutionary force the actual effect of the
utterance on the hearer may or may not be
consistent with the illocutionary force.
45Types of Speech Act s
- Directives world to words (hearer) requesting,
ordering, interrogating. - Assertives words to world asserting,
concluding, informing, reporting, predicting. - Commissives world to words (speaker)
promising, threatening, guaranteeing. - Declaratives world to words vice versa
performing a marriage, declaring war, calling a
runner out. - Expressives null thanking, complaining,
greeting, apologizing.
46felicity conditions
According to John Searle, for a speech act to be
effective it must satisfy four felicity
conditions
- Propositional content the MAP as constrained by
the illocutionary force of the utterance. - Preparatory conditions what must be already
true about the world or the communicators prior
to the speech act. - Sincerity condition speaker must mean it.
- Essential condition the utterance must count
as a performance of the relevant act.
47communication accommodation theory
CAT was developed by Howard Giles and was
referred to originally as Speech Accommodation
Theory. It was developed to explain how and why
convergence and divergence of communicative
behavior occur in communicative interaction(s).
In short, Giles argued that our communicative
styles tend to converge or diverge as a function
of perceptions of affiliation with conversational
partners.
48communication accommodation theory
Convergence and divergence can be accomplished
several ways
- Upward vs. Downward
- Full vs. Partial vs. Hyper
- Large vs. Moderate
- Uni- vs. Multicodal
- Symmetrical vs. Asymmetrical
- Subjective vs. Objective
49communication accommodation theory
Motives for and outcomes of accommodation
- A speakers (often unconscious) need for social
integration or identification with another. - Social approval.
- Social attractiveness.
- Perceived similarity.
- Perceptions of power.
- Social influence Compliance