Title: PREFERENCES AND UTILITY
1Part 2
2Objectives of the chapter
- Study a way to represent consumers preferences
about bundles of goods - What are bundles of goods? combinations of
goods. For instance - Xslices of pizza
- Yglasses of juice
- Bundles
- P X1, Y1
- Q X3, Y0
- R Y3, X0
- S X2, Y1
3Objectives of the chapter
- Johns preferences are such that
- P is preferred to both Q and R
- S is preferred to P
- This way of representing preferences would be
very messy if we have many bundles - In this chapter we study a simple way of
representing preferences over bundles of goods - This is useful because in reality there are many
bundles of goods
4Axioms of rational choice
- Before describing this simple method to represent
preferences over bundles, we will study what
requirements must the preferences satisfy in
order for the method to work - These requirements are the axioms of rational
choice - Without these requirements, it would be very
difficult to come up with a simple method to
represent preferences over many bundles of goods - It is easy to read a tube map, but not so much to
read a tube-bus-and rail map !!!!
5Axioms of Rational Choice
- Completeness
- if A and B are any two bundles, an individual can
always specify exactly one of these
possibilities - A is preferred to B
- B is preferred to A
- A and B are equally attractive
- In other words, preferences must exist in order
to be able to describe them through a simple
method
6Axioms of Rational Choice
- Transitivity
- if A is preferred to B, and B is preferred to C,
then A is preferred to C - assumes that the individuals choices are
internally consistent - If transitivity does not hold, we would need a
very complicated method to describe preferences
over many bundles of goods
7Axioms of Rational Choice
- Continuity
- if A is preferred to B, then bundles suitably
close to A must also be preferred to B - If this does not hold, we would need a very
complicated method to describe individuals
preferences
8Utility
- Given these assumptions, it is possible to show
that people are able to rank all possible
bundles from least desirable to most - Economists call this ranking utility
- if A is preferred to B, then the utility assigned
to A exceeds the utility assigned to B - U(A) gt U(B)
9Utility
- Game
- Someone state the preferences using numbers from
1 to 10 - Can someone use different numbers from 1 to 10
but state the same ordering? - Can someone use numbers 1 to 100 and state the
same preferences?
10Utility
- Game
- Clearly, the numbers are arbitrary
- The only consistent thing is the ranking that we
obtain
11Utility
- Utility could be represented by a Table
Bundles Example Utility
P 1
Q 0
R 0
S 2
U(P)1gtU(Q)0 because we said that P was
preferred to Q U(B)U(C) because Q and R are
equally preferred
12Utility
- Notice that several tables of utility can
represent the same ranking
Bundles Another example Example Utility
P 1 1
Q 0 0
R 0 0
S 4 2
- We can think that the rankings are real. They are
in anyones mind. However, utility numbers are an
economists invention - The difference (2-1, 4-1) in the utility numbers
is meaningless. The only important thing about
the numbers is that they can be used to represent
rankings (orderings)
13Utility
- Utility rankings are ordinal in nature
- they record the relative desirability of
commodity bundles - Because utility measures are not unique, it makes
no sense to consider how much more utility is
gained from A than from B. This gain in utility
will depend on the scale which is arbitrary - It is also impossible to compare utilities
between people. They might be using different
scales.
14Utility
- If we have many bundles of goods, a Table is not
a convenient way to represent an ordering. The
table would have to be too long. - Economist prefer to use a mathematical function
to assign numbers to consumption bundles - This is called a utility function
- utility U(X,Y)
- Check that the previous example of the three
columns table is obtained with the following
utility functions - UXY,
- and U(XY)2
15Utility
- Clearly, for an economist it is the same to use
UXY than to use U(XY)2 because both
represent the same ranking (see the table), so
both functions will give us the same answer in
terms of which bundles of good are preferred to
others - Any transformation that preserves the ordering
(multiply by a positive number, take it at a
power of a positive number, take ln) will give
us the same ordering and hence the same answer - We can use this property to simplify some
mathematical computations that we will see in the
future
16Economic Goods
- In the utility function, the x and y are assumed
to be goods - more is preferred to less
Quantity of y
y
Quantity of x
x
17Indifference Curves
- An indifference curve shows a set of consumption
bundles among which the individual is indifferent
Quantity of y
Combinations (x1, y1) and (x2, y2) provide the
same level of utility
y1
y2
U1
Quantity of x
x1
x2
18Indifference Curve Map
- Each point must have an indifference curve
through it
Quantity of y
U1 lt U2 lt U3
Quantity of x
19Transitivity
- Can any two of an individuals indifference
curves intersect?
The individual is indifferent between A and
C. The individual is indifferent between B and
C. Transitivity suggests that the
individual should be indifferent between A and B
Quantity of y
But B is preferred to A because B contains more x
and y than A
C
B
U2
A
U1
Quantity of x
20Convexity
- Economist believe that
- Balanced bundles of goods are preferred to
extreme bundles - This assumption is formally known as the
assumption of convexity of preferences - Using a graph, shows that if this assumption
holds, then the indifference curves cannot be
strictly concave, they must be strictly convex
21Convexity
- Formally, If the indifference curve is convex,
then the combination (x1 x2)/2, (y1 y2)/2
will be preferred to either (x1,y1) or (x2,y2)
This means that well-balanced bundles are
preferred to bundles that are heavily weighted
toward one Commodity (extreme bundles). The
middle points are better than the Extremes, so
the middle is at a higher indifference Curve.
Quantity of y
y1
(y1 y2)/2
y2
U1
Quantity of x
x1
(x1 x2)/2
x2
22Marginal Rate of Substitution
- Important concept !!
- MRSYX is the number of units of good Y that a
consumer is willing to give up in return for
getting one more unit of X in order to keep her
utility unchanged - Lets do a graph in the whiteboard !!!
- MRSYX is the negative of the slope of the
indiference curve (where Y is in the ordinates
axis)
23Marginal Rate of Substitution
- The negative of the slope of the indifference
curve at any point is called the marginal rate of
substitution (MRS)
Quantity of y
y1
y2
U1
Quantity of x
x1
x2
24Marginal Rate of Substitution
- Notice that if indifference curves are strictly
convex, then the MRS is decreasing (as x
increases, the MRSyx decreases) - See it in a graph As x increases, the amount
of y that the consumer is gives up to stay in
the same indifference curve (that is MRSyx)
decreases - If the assumption that balanced bundles are
preferred to extreme bundles (convexity of
preferences assumption holds then the MRSyx is
decreasing!!
25Marginal Rate of Substitution
- MRS changes as x and y change
- and it is decreasing
Quantity of y
y1
y2
U1
Quantity of x
x1
x2
26Utility and the MRS
- Suppose an individuals preferences for
hamburgers (y) and soft drinks (x) can be
represented by
Solving for y, we get the indifference curve for
level 10 y 100/x
- Taking derivatives, we get the MRS -dy/dx
- MRS -dy/dx 100/x2
27Utility and the MRS
- MRSyx -dy/dx 100/x2
- Note that as x rises, MRS falls
- when x 5, MRSyx 4
- when x 20, MRSyx 0.25
- When x20, then the individual does not value
much an additional unit of x. He is only willing
to give 0.25 units of y to get an additional unit
of x.
28Another way of computing the MRS
- Suppose that an individual has a utility function
of the form - utility U(x,y)
- The total differential of U is
Along any indifference curve, utility is constant
(dU 0) dU/dy and dU/dx are the marginal
utility of y and x respectively
29Another way of computing the MRS
MRS is the ratio of the marginal utility of x to
the marginal utility of y Marginal utilities are
generally positive (goods)
30Example of MRS
- Suppose that the utility function is
We can simplify the algebra by taking the
logarithm of this function (we have explained
before that taking the logarithm does not change
the result because it preserves the ordering,
though it can make algebra easier) U(x,y)
lnU(x,y) 0.5 ln x 0.5 ln y
31Deriving the MRS
Notice that the MRS is decreasing in x The MRS
falls when x increases
32Examples of Utility Functions
- Cobb-Douglas Utility
- utility U(x,y) x?y?
- where ? and ? are positive constants
- The relative sizes of ? and ? indicate the
relative importance of the goods - The algebra can usually be simplified by taking
ln(). Lets do it in the blackboard.
33Examples of Utility Functions
- Perfect Substitutes
- U(x,y) U ?x ?y
- Y -(?/ ? )x (1/ ? )U , indifference curve for
level U
The indifference curves will be linear. The MRS
(?/ ? ) is constant along the indifference
curve.
Quantity of y
Quantity of x
34Examples of Utility Functions
- Perfect Substitutes
- U(x,y) U ?x ?y
- dU ?dx ?dy
- Notice that the change in utility will be the
same if (dx ? and dy 0) or if (dx 0 and dy
?). So x and y are exchanged at a fixed rate
independently of how much x and y the consumer is
consumed - It is as if x and y were substitutes. That is why
we call them like that
35Examples of Utility Functions
- Perfect Complements
- utility U(x,y) min (?x, ?y)
The indifference curves will be L-shaped. It is
called complements because if we Are in the
kink then utility does not increase by we
increase the quantity of only one good. The
quantity of both Goods must increase in order to
increase utility
Quantity of y
Quantity of x
36Examples of Utility Functions
- CES Utility (Constant elasticity of substitution)
- utility U(x,y) x?/? y?/?
- when ? ? 0 and
- utility U(x,y) ln x ln y
- when ? 0
- Perfect substitutes ? ? 1
- Cobb-Douglas ? ? 0
- Perfect complements ? ? -?
37Examples of Utility Functions
- CES Utility (Constant elasticity of substitution)
- The elasticity of substitution (?) is equal to
1/(1 - ?) - Perfect substitutes ? ? ?
- Fixed proportions ? ? 0