Title: Lecture 5: Consequential Ethics
1Lecture 5 Consequential Ethics Deontological
Ethics
2Consider these quotes
- The remarkable thing is that we really love our
neighbor as ourselves we do unto others as we do
unto ourselves. We hate others when we hate
ourselves. We are tolerant toward others when we
tolerate ourselves. We forgive others when we
forgive ourselves. We are prone to sacrifice
others when we are ready to sacrifice ourselves.
Eric Hoffer
3Consider these quotes
- We can discover this meaning in life in three
different ways (1) by doing a deed (2) by
experiencing a value and (3) by suffering.
Victor Frankl.
4Consider these quotes
- Never let your sense of morals get in the way
of doing what's right. Isaac Asimov. - When morality comes up against profit, it is
seldom that profit loses. Shirley Chisholm
5Consider these quotes
- Actions are right in proportion as they tend to
promote happiness wrong as they tend to produce
the reverse of happiness. By happiness is
intended pleasure and the absence of pain.
John Stuart Mill
6Major Ideas
- Virtue Ethics An action is right iff it is what
the virtuous agent would do. 1. An action is
right iff it is what a virtuous agent would do in
the circumstances 1a. A virtuous agent is one
who acts virtuously, i.e., one who has
exercises the virtues. 2 A virtue is a character
trait a human being needs to flourish or live
well. What is essential is to note the conceptual
link between virtue flourishing (living well or
eudaimonia).
7Major Ideas
- Deontological Ethics An action is right iff it
is in accordance with a moral rule or principle.
A moral rule is one that is(a) laid on us by God,
(b) required by natural law, (c) laid on us by
reason, (d) required by rationality, (e) would
command universal rational acceptance, or (f)
would be the object of choice of all rational
beings. What is essential is the link between
right action, moral rule, rationality.
8Major Ideas
- Consequential Ethics An action is right iff it
promotes the best consequences. The best
consequences are those in which happiness is
maximized. What is essential to note is that it
forges a link between consequences happiness.
9Major Ideas
- Before we consider consequential and
deontological ethics, lets explore some other
basic terms that are important to know - Good ideas have good consequences, bad ideas have
bad consequences.
10 What is Pluralism?
- There are definite standards of right behavior
but that more than one right standard exists. - - There are several right course of action.
-
11 What is Relativism?
- The theory that there are no absolute standards
and that all truth is relative to a person or
culture. - - No universal moral law or norm of goodness or
rightness exists. - - What seems right to a person or group is
right there is no higher court of appeal.
12A. Relativism assumes the following
- 1. The context or situational setting in which
any talk occurs influences its outcome or the
conclusions that arise from it. - 2. Relativism leads to the conclusion that the
situational character of all conversations have
no access to a standpoint from which we could
reach conclusions about what is absolute or
universally right or wrong, good or evil, just or
unjust.
13Relativism assumes the following
- 3. Moral relativism declares that assertions
about the right and the good, as well as laws or
principles that guide human moral behavior are
contextually determined.
14 3a. Cultural Relativism
- A form of pluralism, this theory holds that
different standards of right and wrong arise in
different cultures. Within a given culture there
are distinct standards, but these standards may
vary from culture to culture. - - No culture is in a position to make ethical
judgments about the behaviors of other
cultures. - - Ex. One culture may have a prohibition
against slavery, whereas another culture does
not. In this view, slavery is right for the one
culture but wrong for the other. -
15 3b. Individual Relativism
- A form of pluralism, individual relativism is
the doctrine that states that what is right
depends on the view of a specific individual. - Ex. If a lady believes that extramarital
affairs are morally permissible but her husband
does not, then extramarital affairs are right for
her, but wrong for him.
16In contrast, what is Absolutism?
- There are definite and universal standards of
ethical behavior, that we can know what they are,
that all people have an obligation to act on
them. - a. Believed to be standards which are dictated
or generated by human reason (Kantian ethics ). - b. These ethical standards are either
religious in nature (e.g., special revelation
the Bible.).
17 3c. A Problem of Relativist Theories
- A. They seem unable to account to how strongly
people feel about certain immoral acts. -
- Ex. If a Nazi soldier believes that torturing
Jewish children is morally permissible, can we
only say that such behavior is right for him but
that it is not right for us? - B. They are unable to offer a strong account for
justice vs. injustice good vs. evil, right.
vs wrong it is counter-intuitive.
18 3c. A Problem of Relativist Theories
- C. Unlivable and inconsistent with reality.
19Disastrous Effects of Relativism According to
John Piper (Christian Thought)
- Relativism commits treason against God
- Relativism cultivates duplicity (dishonesty).
- Relativism conceals doctrinal defects.
- Relativism cloaks greed with flattery.
- Relativism cloaks pride in the guise of humility.
- Relativism enslaves people.
- Relativism leads to a brutal totalitarianism.
- Relativism silences personal identity.
- Relativism poisons personal character.
20Lets now turn to consequential ethics
21 Consequential Ethics
- We choose the actions that bring about the best
outcomes. There are many kinds of consequential
forms of ethics. Lets consider the following - - Egoism we should always act to maximize our
own individual interests. -
22 A. Consequential Ethics
-
- We choose the actions that
- bring about the best outcomes
-
- - Egoism we should always act to maximize our
own individual interests. - - Utilitarianism we should act to maximize the
happiness of all affected by the action. -
23 A closer look at Utilitarianism
- This theory that holds that an act is right or
wrong according to the utility or value of its
consequences. - An act that produces more good than harm has
greater value than act that produces more harm
than good.
24 A closer look at Utilitarianism
- Utilitarianism believe in the value of ethical
laws in helping people determine which action
will probably bring about the greatest good for
the greatest number of people. - While they are not against laws or values
(antinomians), they are not absolutists either. - Every act is judged by its results, not by it
intrinsic and universal value.
25 A closer look at Utilitarianism
- In order to do determine the best consequence,
some argue that you must add up the happiness in
one person and then multiply the total happiness
in the total number of people and subtract the
total pain. - If the result is positive then the action is
good. - If the result is negative then the action is bad.
26A closer look at Utilitarianism
- Uses of Utilitarian Ethics in terms of Pleasure
vs. Pain (Peter Singer) - 1. When we testify the safety of a new
shampoo, we drip the shampoo in concentrated form
into the eye of rabbits, causing them terrible
pain. But does shampoo leaving your hair
lustrous and manageable, sufficient to justify
the infliction of so much suffering?
27 A closer look at Utilitarianism
- 2. The taste of a char-grilled steak, juicy
and tender, is a genuine source of pleasure. But
can this gourmet pleasure (which is not essential
to sustain our lives), and in fact may shorten
our lives by contributing to LDL levels, justify
the infliction of suffering on cattle that are
raised on crowded feedlots, and then herded into
slaughter houses?
28A closer look at Utilitarianism
- 3. It must be delightful to live in an elegant
home, richly equipped with a Jacuzzi and sauna in
addition to having a master bedroom suite with an
entire wall-covered entertainment system. But is
it really right to spend that much on luxuries
that add only a small increase to our pleasure
when the same resources could be used to care for
impoverished children living in hunger? For
example, 21.00 US dollars can feed over 150
elementary students in Ghana for two weeks (rice
mixed with yams).
29A closer look at Utilitarianism
- 4. I purchase another expensive GQ suit to
add to my already stuffed closet-for it will
bring me pleasure. But is that small increment
of pleasure even remotely comparable to the
pleasure and relief of suffering that would
result if I took that same money and purchased
clothes to orphan children or a threadbare
family?
30A closer look at Utilitarianism
- 5. A tummy tuck will certainly improve sagging
appearances and make some of us feel better. But
the cost of a tummy tuck can be used to drill a
water well and provide clean and pure water to an
entire village in most third world countries.
31A closer look at Utilitarianism
- 6. Utilitarian Ethics and Public Policy
- If we are trying to decide whether a new
football stadium with luxury boxes for the very
rich is a better investment than decent
inner-city schools and health care for the poor,
is utilitarian calculations a better guide for
making such decisions than deontological ethics? -
32 Problems with Utilitarianism
- The end does not justify the means.
- An act is not automatically good simply because
it has a good goal. - The road to destruction is paved with good
intentions (Prov. 1412). -
- Ex. President Nixons goal of national security
was noble, but the criminal activity of Watergate
was not justified. -
33 Problems with Utilitarianism
- Utilitarian acts have no intrinsic value.
- Ex. The attempt to save a life is not an
intrinsically valuable act. - No benevolence, no sacrifice, no love has any
value unless it happens to have good results. - Ex. If forced to choose to save either a
medical doctor or a poor child from a destructive
house fire, one is obligated to save the medical
doctor.
34 Problems with Utilitarianism
- People are subject to the greater good of
statistics - Ex. If forced to choose to save either a medical
doctor or a poor child from a destructive house
fire, one is obligated to save the medical doctor
because we know he is able to help people we
dont know the future of the child.
35 Problems with Utilitarianism
- The need for an absolute standard
- Relative norms do no stand alone. They must be
relative to something which is not relative. So,
unless there is a standard, how can they know
what is the greater good.
36 Problems with Utilitarianism
- The end is an ambiguous term
- If the utilitarian contends that ethics should
be based on what will bring the best results in
the long run, how long is long? A few years?
a life-time? Eternity? Anything beyond the
immediate present is outside of the human range.
37 Problems with Utilitarianism
- Ambiguous as well in determining whether the
end means for the greatest number or for all
individuals. - Could good could be achieved or the most people
if basic rights were denied to some people? Is
this intuitively right?
38Problems with Utilitarianism
- Pleasure vs. Pain
- Pain and Pleasure are not exact opposites. Is
this true? - How do you measure pain and pleasure?
- Can pain be beneficial over and against pleasure?
39Conclusion to Consequentialism
- Consequentialists believe that consequences are
the only things that matter - A. We do not necessarily know the outcome.
- B. The consequences of our own action may be
unpredictable.
40Conclusion to Consequentialism
- C. he consequences of other peoples actions
which impact on our actions may also be
unpredictable. - D. We do not know what the consequences will be
of our action in the long term. - E. We cant necessarily control the consequences.
41Concluding thought to Consequentialism
- Dostoyeskys Challenge to Utilitarian Ethicists
- Tell me honestly, I challenge you-answer me
imagine that you are charged with building the
edifice of human destiny, the ultimate aim of
which is to bring people happiness, to give them
peace and contentment at last, but that in order
to achieve this it is essential and unavoidable
to torture just one speck of creation,
thatlittle child beating her chest with her
little fists, and imagine that this edifice has
to be erected on her unexpiated suffering for
having done nothing wrong tears. Would you agree
to be the architect under those conditions? Tell
me honestly! - The Karamazov Brothers, trans. Ignat Avsey
(Oxford Oxford University Press, 1994).
42- Lets now explore Deontological Ethics
43 Deontological Ethics
- We should choose actions based on their
inherent, intrinsic worth evangelical approaches
to ethics are deontological because it
presupposes Scripture as revelation. - Deontological comes from the Greek word
deon, meaning that which is binding, in
particular a binding duty. So, you are bound to
your duty.
44Deontological Framework
- An action is right if and only if (iff) it is in
accordance with a moral rule or principle. - This is a purely formal specification, forging a
link between the concepts of right and action and
moral rule, and gives one no guidance until one
knows what a moral rule is.
45Deontological Framework
- Therefore, the links between right action, moral
rule, and rationality based upon moral rule
given by God or required by natural or laid on us
by reason or required by rationality or would
command universal rational acceptance or would by
the object of choice of all rational beingare
all essential aspects to any deontological
framework.
46Deontological Framework
- So, the next thing the theory needs is a premise
about that A moral rule is one that would have
been historically - A. Theistic
- 1. Given to us by God
- 2. Is required by Natural Law (theistic
connection) - B. Secular (though can still be connected to
God) - 1. Is laid on us by reason.
- 2. Is required by rationality
- 3. Would command universal acceptance
- 4. Would be the object of choice of all
rational beings.
47 Deontological Ethics
- It holds that acts are right or wrong in and of
themselves because of the kinds of acts they are
and not simply because of their ends or
consequences. - - The ends do not justify the means.
- - A good end or purpose does not justify a bad
actions. - - You are duty-bound binding is not dependent
on consequences, no matter if it is painful or
pleasurable.
48 Deontological Ethics
- For example
- 1. You are duty-bound to keep your promise to be
faithful to your spouse, even if a more
attractive person comes along. - 2. You are duty-bound to always telling the
truth, even if it cost you a job. - Duty is not based on what is pleasant or
beneficial, but rather upon the obligation itself.
49Deontological Ethics
- For example, a deontologist might argue that a
promise ought to be kept simply because it is
right to keep a promise, regardless whether the
doing so will have good or bad consequences. - In contrast, a utilitarian will argue that we
should keep our promises only when keeping them
results in better consequences than the
alternatives.
50Overview of Ethical Systems Immanuel Kant
(1724-1804)
. To act morally you must be motivated
exclusively by rational commitment to the
universal moral law or the categorical
Imperative Act in conformity with that maxim,
and that maxim only, that you can will at the
same time be a universal law. Right actions
flow out of right principles
To act morally requires the rational power to
recognize absolute moral laws that transcend our
natural world.
To act morally requires the power of the will to
rise above all natural feelings and inclinations.
This raises us above our natural world.
Second form of categorical imperative Act in
such a way that you always treat humans not
merely as a means to an end but also as an end.
Do the act that is motivated by the sincere
belief that what you are doing is the right thing
not merely for you, but for anybody seeking to
act properly in any situation.
51Basic Terms to Know
- 1. Deontological Ethics "rule or duty-based
morality ...emphasizes right action over good
consequences - 2. a priori "not in any way derived from
experience or dependent upon it" concepts
derived a priori are universal rules that
determine, in advance, the conditions for
knowledge in a particular domain - 3. maxim rule of conduct
- 4. Hypothetical imperative an action that is
good only as a means to something else - 5. Categorical imperative an action that is good
in itself and conforms to reason categorical
imperatives act as universal rules governing a
situation regardless of circumstance
52Summary
- Thus, Kantian ethics states an action is right
iff it is in accord with the Categorical
Imperative (the supreme principle of morality).
Right actions flow from right principles. - From using our capacity to reason Kant believes
the Categorical Imperative can be formulated in
at least three ways they are all equivalent with
the first formulation being the basis. Though
they bring out various aspects of the moral law,
they cannot tell us more than what the first
formula does.
53Categorical Imperative
- The CI does not depend on a logically prior
condition though it assumes the predisposition
that one wishes to be rational and will follow
what rationally determined duty dictates (in
contrast to hypothetical imperatives which means
that the consequent depends upon the antecedent
If p, then q). Thus, morality is a function of
human reason. Human reason is governed by Logic.
Q.E.D., to be irrational is to be inhuman. To be
sure, there are perfect and imperfect duties.
Actions are characterized as perfect because they
follow directly from an application of the
universalization of the Categorical Imperative in
contrast to imperfect duties that follow from CI
only after considering other factors (e.g.,
seeking our own happiness). An imperfect duty is
just as strong in its action guiding force as a
perfect duty. Thus, their point of origin
highlights their differences.
54Three Formulations of the Categorical Imperative
- First formulation Act in conformity with the
maxim and the maxim only, that you can will at
the same time a universal law. This means that
what I consider doing, it must be something that
I can will or accept that all do (universal) it
is replacing individual preferences with purely
universal terms. - Second formulation Act in such a way that you
treat humanity, whether in your own person or in
that of another, always an end and never as a
means only. In essence, every person has
intrinsic value and that humanity is a limit or
constraint on our action. - Third formulation Therefore, every rational
being must act as if he were through his maxim
always a legislating member in the universal
kingdom of ends. In other words, we have to
will what is consistent with the operations of
the kingdom as a whole. In sum, all people
should consider themselves as both members and
heads
55Major Points to Consider
- 1. What gives an act moral worth is our motives
because we cant necessarily control the
consequences of our act or/and things do not
always turn out as we want. He calls this motive
the good will. Therefore, we are responsible
for our motives to do good or bad, and thus it is
for this that we are held morally accountable. - 2. What is the right motive is acting out of a
will to do the right thing only an act motivated
by this concern for the moral law is right. - Consider the following Shopkeeper illustration
56Major Points to Consider
- 3. Kants Shopkeeper illustration A shopkeeper
charges her customers a fair price and charges
the same to all. But what is the shopkeepers
motive? - A. If the shopkeepers motive for charging a
fair price is that it serves her own best
interest, then this motive is not praiseworthy. - B. If the shopkeepers motive for charging a
fair price is because she is sympathetic toward
her customers, then this motive is still not
praiseworthy. - C. If the shopkeepers motive is to do the right
thing because it is the right thing, then her
motive is indeed praiseworthy. Only doing that
which is morally right is praiseworthy. -
- We do not always know when our acts are
motivated by self-interest, inclination or pure
respect for morality. Also, we often act from
mixed motives. However, we are certain that the
motive is pure when we do what is right
regardless how we feel or/and the consequences.
57Major Points to Consider
- 4. In order for our action to have moral worth we
must not only act out of a right motivation but
we must also do what is right. -
Right Motive
Right Act
The motive and the act must be morally right! We
must not only act of duty (have the right motive)
but also according to duty or as duty
requires (do what is right).
58- 5. How we are to know what the right thing to do
is to test our motives and actions against the
categorical imperative. If our motive and acts
meets the criteria of the categorical imperative
we are obligated to do it. -
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE Oughts that tell us
what we ought to do no matter what, under all
conditions, and are universally binding
(categorical imperative). 1st form of
Categorical Imperative Act only on that maxim
which can will as a universal law. This means
that what I consider doing, it must be something
that I can will or accept that all do (universal).
Right Motive
Right Act
59According the first formula
- According to the first formula the agent must
be willing to eliminate all individual reference
from the maxim of her action. The most
significant exclusion from the maxim is oneself.
Therefore, in order to pass the test of the
categorical imperative in the first formulation,
one must be prepared to go on willing even if it
contains no reference to oneself.
60- 6. Thus, whatever I consider doing, it must be
something that I can will or accept all do. - A law by its very nature has a degree of
universality. Act only on that maxim which you
can will as a universal law. -
Maxim is a description of the action that I
will put to the test.
7. How do I know what I can and cannot will
as a universal practice?
As a rational being I can only will what is
non-contradictory
61- 8. First Two Forms of the Categorical Imperative
2nd form of Categorical Imperative Always treat
humanity, whether in your own person or that of
another, never simply as a means but always at
the same time as an end. This means that every
person has intrinsic value that humanity is a
limit or constraint on our action.
1st form of Categorical Imperative Act only on
that maxim which can will as a universal
law. This means that what I consider doing, it
must be something that I can will or accept that
all do (universal) it is replacing individual
preferences with purely universal terms.
621st Categorical Imperative
- 1st Categorical Imperative is a decision
procedure for moral reasoning. 4 Steps - 1. Formulate a maxim that enshrines your
reasoning for acting as you propose. - 2. Recast maxim as universal law of nature
governing all rational agents-all people will
act upon. - 3. Consider whether your maxim is even
conceivable in a world governed by this law of
nature. - 4. Ask whether you would or could rationally
will to act on this maxim in such a world.
63- 9. Second Form of the Categorical Imperatives
Explains how we ought to treat ourselves.
2nd Categorical Imperative Always treat
humanity, whether in your own person or that of
another, never simply as a means but always at
the same time as an end. This means that every
person has intrinsic value that humanity is a
limit or constraint in our action.
Treat ourselves other as ends rather than
merely as means.
The moral conclusions should be the same whether
we use the 1st or 2nd form of the categorical
imperative.
64- 10. Third Formulation of the Categorical
Imperative Hypothetical Kingdom of Ends
All maxims as proceeding from our own
law-making ought to harmonize with a possible
kingdom of ends as a kingdom of
nature." Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals,
4436/104.
- Key Points
- Think of ourselves as members of a society of
beings whose permissible ends are to be
respected. - 2. Test our maxims by asking, whether, supposing
the maxims were natural laws, there would be a
society of that kind. In other words, we are
obligated to act only by maxims which would
harmonize a possible kingdom of ends. - 3. We have a perfect duty not to act by maxims
that create incoherent or impossible states of
natural affairs when we attempt to universalize
them - We have an imperfect duty not to act by maxims
that promote unstable or greatly undesirable
states of affairs. - Kant seems to assume that those who apply the
categorical imperative to their maxims will come
out with answers that agree when the maxims
tested are alike. J.B. Schneewind, Autonomy,
Obligation, Virtue, pg. 338.
65Third Categorical Imperative introduces a social
dimension to Kantian Morality
- The formulation of the CI states that we must
act in accordance with the maxims of a member
giving universal laws for a merely possible
kingdom of ends (4439). - It combines the others in that (i) it requires
that we conform our actions to the maxims of a
legislator of laws (ii) that this lawgiver lays
down universal laws, binding all rational wills
including our own, and (iii) that those laws are
of a merely possible kingdom each of whose
members equally possesses this status as
legislator of universal laws, and hence must be
treated always as an end in itself. - The intuitive idea behind this formulation is
that our fundamental moral obligation is to act
only on principles which could earn acceptance by
a community of fully rational agents each of whom
have an equal share in legislating these
principles for their community.
66Summary of first three categorical imperatives
- The Categorical Imperative requires that I act
only on maxims that I can will as universal law. -
- The categorical imperative is supposed to give us
a test for maxims. -
- Maxim is the is subjective principle of an
action. The principle of an action is that
prescription from which the action follows. - If the maxim meets the test, the action that
follows from it has moral worth if the maxim
does not meet it, the action does not have moral
worth.
671st Categorical Imperative
- 1st Categorical Imperative requires willingness
to continue to the subscription to the maxim of
an action even if all individual or singular
reference is excluded from it. Eliminating
individual or singular reference requires
eliminating reference to me. In other words,
think of replacing individual references with
purely universal terms.
681st Categorical Imperative
- Act in such a way that you always treat
humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, never simply as a means, but
always at the same time as an end. -
- Rather than thinking that humanity is the goal
or proper end of our action, he presupposes that
humanity is a limit or constraint on our action.
- This kind of constraint can be seen mostly
clearly by tracing the connection with the first
formula, the Formula of Universal Law. Remember,
the agent must be willing to eliminate all
individual reference from the maxim of her
action. The most significant exclusion here is
that of herself. Therefore, be prepared go on
willing the maxim even if it contains no
reference to herself. - The constraint that the second formula imposes
is that the maxim of an action must be such that
any other free and rational person can adopt it.
Treating humanity as an end in itself is, for
Kant, respecting our capacity for free and
rational choice in his term, it is respecting
our autonomy. I am constrained, according to
this first formula, by the consideration that is
wrong, other things being equal, to impede the
agency of others. To treat another human being
as merely a means is to ignore the other as a
center of agency. The clearest cases here are
those of coercion and deception. - For example If I take the hand of one of my
students in my class and with it I strike the
neighbouring students face, I have bypassed the
first students agency. I have treated her
merely as a means, as though she were merely an
organic hitting implement. The same is true when
I deceive somebody, because if I conceal the
nature of the situation, I impede her ability to
make a free and rational choice for that
situation. -
691st Categorical Imperative
- The constraint that the second formula imposes
is that the maxim of an action must be such that
any other free and rational person can adopt it.
Treating humanity as an end in itself is, for
Kant, respecting our capacity for free and
rational choice in his term, it is respecting
our autonomy. I am constrained, according to
this first formula, by the consideration that is
wrong, other things being equal, to impede the
agency of others. To treat another human being
as merely a means is to ignore the other as a
center of agency. The clearest cases here are
those of coercion and deception. - For example If I take the hand of one of my
students in my class and with it I strike the
neighbouring students face, I have bypassed the
first students agency. I have treated her
merely as a means, as though she were merely an
organic hitting implement. The same is true
when I deceive somebody, because if I conceal
the nature of the situation, I impede her ability
to make a free and rational choice for that
situation. -
70What is the connection between the categorical
imperative is the following
- If I cannot will maxim X as universal law, then
I am acting for reasons that it is not possible
for everyone to share. But to act toward people
on the basis of reasons they cannot possibly
share is to use them, to treat them as a mere
means to my goals. In fact, all people should
consider themselves both members and heads
because we have a perfect duty not to act in
maxims that create incoherent or impossible
states of natural affairs for it will lead to
unstable or greatly undesirable states of
affairs. See, the truly autonomous will is not
subject to any particular interest. Kants idea
here is that one should not treat others in ways
they couldnt rationally assent to.
71- 10. Perfect and Imperfect Duties
Imperfect Duties Are those duties that dont
whole heartily conform to the categorical
imperative. e.g., If I were an egoist and
concerned only about myself, no one could accuse
me of using other people I would simply leave
them alone. But this attitude practice is
inconsistent with the duty to treat others as
persons. As persons, they also have interests
and plans, and to recognize this I must at least
sometimes and in some ways seek to promote their
ends and goals.
Perfect Duties Perfect duties are absolutes
necessary they conform to the categorical
imperative. eg., We can and should absolutely
refrain from making false or lying promises.
72- The following are 4 examples famously used by
Kant.
731st example Suicide
- Whenever continuing to live will bring more pain
than pleasure, I shall commit suicide out of
self-love. - 1. Suicide cant be a universal law for one cant
will that would be universal will. - 2. Remember, suicide would be morally right if
and only if the person who is thinking about
suicide can consistently will that suicide be a
universal law.
741st Example Suicide
- A man reduced to despair by a series of
misfortunes feels wearied of life, but is still
so far in possession of his reason that he can
ask himself whether it would not be contrary to
his duty to himself to take his own life. Now he
inquires whether the maxim of his action could
become a universal law of nature. His maxim is
'From self-love I adopt it as a principle to
shorten my life when its longer duration is
likely to bring more evil than satisfaction.' It
is asked then simply whether this principle
founded on self-love can become a universal law
of nature. Now we see at once that a system of
nature of which it should be a law to destroy
life by means of the very feeling whose special
nature it is to impel to the improvement of life
would contradict itself and, therefore, could not
exist as a system of nature hence that maxim
cannot possibly exist as a universal law of
nature and, consequently, would be wholly
inconsistent with the supreme principle of all
duty." (Quoted from the Fundamental Principles of
the Metaphysic of Morals, as translated by T.K.
Abbott)
752nd example Lying Not Keeping Promise
- Whenever I need money, then I shall borrow the
money and promise to repay, even though I know I
will not repay. - 1. Lying and not keeping promise cant be a
universal law for one cant will that would be
universal will. - 2. Remember, lying and not repaying would be
morally right if and only if the person who is
thinking about lying and not keeping promise can
consistently will that lying and not keeping
promise be a universal law.
763rd Example Developing Ones Habits
- "A third finds in himself a talent which with the
help of some culture might make him a useful man
in many respects. But he finds himself in
comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge
in pleasure rather than to take pains in
enlarging and improving his happy natural
capacities. He asks, however, whether his maxim
of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing
with his inclination to indulgence, agrees also
with what is called duty. He sees then that a
system of nature could indeed subsist with such a
universal law although men (like the South Sea
islanders) should let their talents rest and
resolve to devote their lives merely to idleness,
amusement, and propagation of their species- in a
word, to enjoyment but he cannot possibly will
that this should be a universal law of nature, or
be implanted in us as such by a natural instinct.
For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills
that his faculties be developed, since they serve
him and have been given him, for all sorts of
possible purposes." (Quoted from the Fundamental
Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals, as
translated by T.K. Abbott)
773rd example Developing Ones Habits
- When Im comfortable as I am, I shall let all my
talents rust. - 1. Everyone necessarily wills that some of his or
her talents be developed. - 2. If everyone necessarily wills that some of his
or her talents be developed, then no one can
consistently will that his non-use of talents to
be a universal law. - 3. Non-use of talents is morally right if and
only if the agent thinking about non-use of
talents can consistently will that non-use of
talents be a universal law. (The Categorical
Imperative) - 4. Therefore, allowing ones talents to rust is
morally wrong.
784th Example Helping Others.
- A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees
that others have to contend with great
wretchedness and that he could help them, thinks
'What concern is it of mine? Let everyone be as
happy as Heaven pleases, or as be can make
himself I will take nothing from him nor even
envy him, only I do not wish to contribute
anything to his welfare or to his assistance in
distress!' Now no doubt if such a mode of
thinking were a universal law, the human race
might very well subsist and doubtless even better
than in a state in which everyone talks of
sympathy and good-will, or even takes care
occasionally to put it into practice, but, on the
other side, also cheats when he can, betrays the
rights of men, or otherwise violates them. But
although it is possible that a universal law of
nature might exist in accordance with that maxim,
it is impossible to will that such a principle
should have the universal validity of a law of
nature. For a will which resolved this would
contradict itself, inasmuch as many cases might
occur in which one would have need of the love
and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a
law of nature, sprung from his own will, he would
deprive himself of all hope of the aid he
desires." (From the Fundamental Principles of the
Metaphysic of Morals, as translated by T.K.
Abbott)
794th example Helping Others
- When I am flourishing and others are in
distress, I shall give nothing to charity. - Everyone necessarily wills that he or she be
helped in desperate circumstances. - 2. If everyone necessarily wills this, then no
one can consistently will that non-help be a
universal law. - 3. Not helping others is morally right if and
only if the agent thinking about not helping
others can consistently will that not helping
others be a universal law. (The Categorical
Imperative) - 4. Therefore, not helping others is not morally
right.
80- 11. Advantages of Kants Moral Theory
Fairness, Consistency, and morally equal
treatment of all people for they are
intrinsically valuable.
Emphasizes the Law of Non-contradiction we would
not will anything that is not rational.
Emphasizes doing what is morally right (it is our
duty).
It is universally binding and Impartial-in order
for an action to be morally permissible, we
should be able to will it for all.
8112. Criticisms against Deontological Ethics
Duty centered ethics stressing obedience to
rules, as opposed to result-centered or
utilitarian ethics.
- 1. No clear way to resolve moral duties when they
come into conflict with each other. - 2. Deontological ethics are consequential moral
systems in disguise enshrined in customs and law
have been known to give the best consequences. - 3. Do not readily allow for gray areas because
they are based on absolutes. - 4. Which duties qualify given time or location
Are old duties still valid? - 5. Human welfare and misery Some principles may
result in a clash with what is best for human
welfare prescribe actions which cause human
misery. - 6. Rule worship The refusal to break a
generously beneficial rule in those areas in
which it is not most beneficial is rule worship. - 7. Exclusive focus on rationality ignores our
relations to with other human beings.
82There is no clear way to deal with moral
conflicts consider the following
- a. Killer comes to the door If a killer comes
to the door and ask for a friend of yours inside
whom he intends to kill, you must tell the truth
(illustration by Kant). - But there is only one exceptionless rule in
Kants philosophy and that is given in the
categorical imperative We are never permitted
to do what we cannot will as a universal law or
what violates the requirement to treat persons as
persons. - Kant may not give us adequate help in deciding
what to do when moral conflicts are involved
because in the above example, both to tell the
truth and preserve life are moral obligations.
83Regarding Impartiality Rationality
- b. Kants moral philosophy is its belief in
impartiality in order for an action to be rally
permissible, we should be able to will it for
all. -
- However, persons do differ in significant ways
(gender, race, age, and talents). In what way
does morality require that everyone be treated
equally and in what does it perhaps require that
different person be treated differently (e.g.,
gender). - c. Kants stress on rationality may be considered
to be too male-oriented, too Westernized. It is
subject to the continental critique of structure
(Foucault).
84Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Kant defines virtue as the moral strength of a
human being's will in fulfilling his duty
(6405) and vice as principled immorality.
(6390) This definition appears to put Kant's
views on virtue at odds with classical views such
as Aristotle's in several important respects. - First, Kant's account of virtue presupposes an
account of moral duty already in place. Thus,
rather than treating admirable character traits
as more basic than the notions of right and wrong
conduct, Kant takes virtues to be explicable only
in terms of a prior account of moral or dutiful
behavior. He does not try to make out what shape
a good character has and then draw conclusions
about how we ought to act on that basis. He sets
out the principles of moral conduct based on his
philosophical account of rational agency, and
then on that basis defines virtue as the trait of
acting according to these principles.
85Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Second, virtue is for Kant a strength of will,
and hence does not arise as the result of
instilling a second nature by a process of
habituating or training ourselves to act and feel
in particular ways. It is indeed a disposition,
but a disposition of one's will, not a
disposition of emotions, feelings, desires or any
other feature of human nature that might be
amenable to habituation. Moreover, the
disposition is to overcome obstacles to moral
behavior that Kant thought were ineradicable
features of human nature. Thus, virtue appears to
be much more like what Aristotle would have
thought of as a lesser trait, viz., continence or
self-control.
86Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Third, in viewing virtue as a trait grounded in
moral principles, and vice as principled
transgression of moral law, Kant thought of
himself as thoroughly rejecting what he took to
be the Aristotelian view that virtue is a mean
between two vices. The Aristotelian view, he
claimed, assumes that virtue differs from vice
only in terms of degree rather than in terms of
the different principles each involves. (6404,
432) But prodigality and avarice, for instance,
do not differ by being too loose or not loose
enough with one's means. They differ in that the
prodigal acts on the principle of acquiring means
with the sole intention of enjoyment, while the
avaricious act on the principle of acquiring
means with the sole intention of possessing them.
87Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Fourth, in classical views the distinction
between moral and non-moral virtues is not
particularly significant. A virtue is some sort
of excellence of the soul , but one finds
classical theorists treating wit and friendliness
along side courage and justice. Since Kant holds
moral virtue to be a trait grounded in moral
principle, the boundary between non-moral and
moral virtues could not be more sharp. Even so,
Kant shows a remarkable interest in non-moral
virtues indeed, much of Anthropology is given
over to discussing the nature and sources of a
variety of character traits, both moral and
non-moral.
88Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Fifth, virtue cannot be a trait of divine beings,
if there are such, since it is the power to
overcome obstacles that would not be present in
them. This is not to say that to be virtuous is
to be the victor in a constant and permanent war
with ineradicable evil impulses. Morality is
duty for human beings because it is possible
(and we recognize that it is possible) for our
desires and interests to run counter to its
demands. Should all of our desires and interests
be trained ever so carefully to comport with what
morality actually requires of us, this would not
change in the least the fact that morality is
still duty for us. For should this come to pass,
it would not change the fact that each and every
desire and interest could have run contrary to
the moral law. And it is the fact that they can
conflict with moral law, not the fact that they
actually do conflict with it, that makes duty a
constraint, and hence virtue essentially a trait
concerned with constraint.
89Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Sixth, virtue, while important, does not hold
pride of place in Kant's system in other
respects. For instance, he holds that the lack of
virtue is compatible with possessing a good will.
(6 408) That one acts from duty, even repeatedly
and reliably can thus be quite compatible with an
absence of the moral strength to overcome
contrary interests and desires. Indeed, it may
often be no challenge at all to do one's duty
from duty alone. Someone with a good will, who is
genuinely committed to duty for its own sake,
might simply fail to encounter any significant
temptation that would reveal the lack of strength
to follow through with that commitment. That
said, he also appeared to hold that if an act is
to be of genuine moral worth, it must be
motivated by the kind of purity of motivation
achievable only through a permanent,
quasi-religious conversion or revolution in the
orientation of the will of the sort described in
Religion.
90Kants View of Virtue/Vice
- Kant here describes the natural human condition
as one in which no decisive priority is given to
the demands of morality over happiness. Until one
achieves a permanent change in the will's
orientation in this respect, a revolution in
which moral righteousness is the nonnegotiable
condition of any of one's pursuits, all of one's
actions that are in accordance with duty are
nevertheless morally worthless, no matter what
else may be said of them. However, even this
revolution in the will must be followed up with a
gradual, lifelong strengthening of one's will to
put this revolution into practice. This suggests
that Kant's considered view is that a good will
is a will in which this revolution of priorities
has been achieved, while a virtuous will is one
with the strength to overcome obstacles to its
manifestation in practice.
91 Criticisms against Deontological Ethics
- How do decide between two principles?
- What about moral conflict between two morally
right principles. - From where or whom do we get our principles?
Nature? God? - If we get our principles from God, who is he and
why doesnt he make himself more obvious?
92Criticisms against Deontological Ethics
- If from nature, that assume what is in nature is
good. - How do we define nature?
- We should follow our conscience? However,
different peoples conscience tell them to do
different things. Ex. If the Bible condemns
divorce, why do people say God told him or her to
divorce his or her spouse? Isnt this a
conflict? -
93Concluding Questions
- Do you thinks ethics is a matter of natural
processes, or is it transcendent (supernaturally
revealed by God)? - Are ethical principles made or discovered?
- Is ethics objective or non-objective?
-
- Are there actual objective facts in ethics, or is
it all just a matter of opinion?
94Concluding Questions
- Can I be completely wrong about one of my ethical
beliefs? - Is ethics a matter or protecting the individual
or enhancing the welfare of all? In other words,
is ethics basically individualistic or in some
way communitarian? - If people from a different culture have different
ethical rules or obligations from our own, must
at least one set of rules be wrong? - Is this known more through reason or by
experience of some sort? - Even those who deny that objective ethical truths
are split on this question?
95(No Transcript)