Title: Anchored Preference Relations
1Anchored Preference Relations
- Jacob Sagi
- Berkeley-Stanford Spring 2003 Finance Workshop
2Outline of Talk
- Reference dependent choice
- Why?
- Primitives of choice
- Naïve anchoring traps
- What to rule out
- Axiom 1 the no anchor cycling property
- Consequences of Axiom 1
- No prospect theory
- Not kinky enough!!
- An alternative to prospect theory
- Risk attitudes and loss aversion
- Accommodating Allais
3Reference dependent choice- why?
- Loss Aversion (Markowitz (1952), Kahneman
Tversky 1979) - Group 1
- Youre given 1000 and
- a choice of 500 sure gain or a 50-50 chance at
1000. - Most choose 1000 500 for sure
- Group 2
- Youre given 2000 and
- a choice of 500 sure loss or a 50-50 chance at
losing 2000. - Most choose 2000 gamble
- Consequences are identical
- Subjects demonstrate higher sensitivity to
losses then gains in arriving at same place. - Try to avoid losses even if it means taking risks
- People prefer not to get something at all then to
get it and then have it taken away tangibility
of ownership.
4Reference dependent choice- why?
- Endowment Effect (Thaler (1980), Samuelson
Zeckhauser (1988)) - Endowment/Status Quo receives preferential
treatment - TIAA CREF
- New plans where the default investment was safe
vs. risky. - WTA-WTP disparity
- Subjects consistently value something more when
they own it. - Status quo bias is ubiquitous.
- Branding
- First mover advantage
5Reference dependent choice- why?
- 1st-order risk aversion Epstein-Zin (1990),
Thaler Benartzi (1995), Rabin (2000),
Barberis-Huang-Santos (2001) - Smooth utility implies 2nd-order RA
- When risk is small relative to endowment, agent
must be nearly risk neutral or exhibit near CARA
(i.e., be pathologically averse to highly
attractive gambles). - Individuals habitually exhibit risk aversion in
the large as well as the small - Kinks in the utility function around the
endowment can cause 1st-order RA in the small - To exhibit this everywhere, utility function must
be pathological or reference dependent.
6Primitives
- X a set of outcomes
- Compact metric space
- P(X) the set of Borel measures on X
- With appropriate topology
- a set of transitive, complete
and continuous binary relations on P(X) - Represented by Ue(.)
- e is the reference point, also called
the anchor - q is preferred to p when anchored
at e - Reference points can be stochastic!
7The dangers of a naïve theory(highly stylized)
1500
A
2000
0.5
B
1000
reference point expected value (portfolio
wealth) B chosen. Wait until new reference point
is incorporated at eB 1500. Before B is
resolved offer A once more. Relative to endowment
face
8One way to avoid cycle is to make the setting
manifestly temporal and impose time consistency
(backward induction)
A
eA
A
B
A
e0
eB
B
B
eA eB implies A is always preferred at second
node Thus, no loss aversion!!
9Moral
- One has to be very careful in constructing a
theory with reference dependence. - Choice
- Ignore relationship between
- Impose ad-hoc inter-temporal assumptions about
the rate of endowment absorption. - Impose time-consistency through backward
induction and risk losing some important effects - Alternatively,
- Impose appealing structure relating
- In the spirit of transitivity
10What to rule out?
- Axiom 1
- If q is better than p when the reference point is
at p, then it is always better than p - Affinity for a prospect is greatest when it is
the reference point - Prevents simple choice cycle
- Prevents more complex cycles
- Set anchor at e, choose p over q p becomes the
new anchor, pay extra to get back q.
11No-cycle Equivalent
- Anchored uc sets are nested within non-anchored
uc sets
12Implications of Axiom 1
- If all the are smooth a.e. and at a.e.
anchor, then there is no reference dependence. - With non-additive , result requires mild
continuity wrt e - CPT with non-additive probabilities (Choquet
integrals) - Requires a certainty equivalent for the anchor
- Structure of the model is smooth a.e. and at
a.e. reference point
13Intuition
If there is reference dependence, the
indifference surfaces of some two relations cross
a.e. in some non-zero measure region. The smooth
a.e. and at a.e. anchor assumption means that at
some crossing point the crossing relations have a
linear approximation and the crossing point
itself is a smooth anchor.
14Zooming in
- Indifference surface of at e is smooth by
assumption. - Can be approximated by flat surface near e.
- Axiom 1 surface has to be nested
PROBLEM cant be both nested and flat
15Implications of Axiom 1
- No linear prospect theory is consistent with
Axiom 1 - A similar result applies to generalized CPT
- Prospect theory is simply not kinky enough!
16Alternatives?
- Explicitly impose Axiom 1
- Add more structure
- Technical
- Anchor continuity
- Convex continuity if uc set is strictly convex
at the anchor, all uc sets in the neighborhood of
the anchor are also convex. - Behavioral
- Independence
17Interpreting Independence
- Editing principle of KT (1979)
- Subject is only interested in the relative
properties of prospects - Cancel out common attributes
- If there is reference dependence, must cancel out
relative attributes - Translation and scale invariance
- Subject only cares about q-e, and does not pay
attention to the scale of the difference between
the distributions. - No anchor is singled out for special treatment
18Interpreting Independence
- Note that
- vNM Independence wrt to mixing with the anchor.
- Counterfactual
- The common consequence version of the Allais
Paradox - Will return to this later
- Independence is just a behavioral assumption
can relax it after examining rep.
19Representation of Ue(p)
- Y is some set of utility functions
- Reduces to EUT if Y is a singleton.
- Subject evaluates the prospect, p, based on a
worst case utility scenario relative to the
anchor. - Note Ue(e) 0
- Ue(p) Ue(e) iff EUT of p exceeds that of e for
EVERY utility function in Y. - Resistance for moving away from the anchor
(status quo bias) - No cycling!
- uc set at anchor is a cone
- Kink at every anchor!!
- Proof is quite technical.
20Risk Attitudes of Repn
- Attributes of Ue(e) correspond to attributes of
the ?s. - All ?s concave, agent will always be RA
- Loss aversion requires Y contain both a risk
averse (concave) and risk seeking utility
(convex) function.
21Examples Applications
- Loss aversion
- Samuelson-Zeckhauser (1988) Endowment Effect
- WTA-WTP disparity
- Affinity is greatest for anchor (Axiom 1)
- The ce of a prospect is greatest when it is the
anchor - Charge more to give anchor than to receive it
22Example Applications
- X L, I, H
- Y ?1, ?2
- Utility vectors
- ?1 (0, 1, 4) ? RL
- ?2 (0, 1, 4/3) ? RA
- p (pL, 1 - pL - pH, pH)
- Let A13, A21/3
- Ue(p)
pH
pL
23(No Transcript)
24(No Transcript)
25Limitations
- Still hard or impossible to get
- All Allais-type behavior
- All cases of Risk aversion in the large small
- Okay if prospect entails both gain and loss
- Not okay otherwise (pure gains/loss prospects)
- The missing attributes are generally present in
non-additive theories (CEUT) - U(p) E?(p)v, where ?(p) are probability
weights - ?(xxi) w( prby(x ? xi) ) - w( prby(x ? xi1)
) - w is a non-linear monotonic transformation
- How to incorporate them here?
26Conclusions
- Reference dependence no-cycling
- Restricts admissibility of representations
- CPT not admissible
- Representation in terms of worst case utility
relative to anchor is okay - Simple worst case EUT
- More comprehensive worst case CEUT
27Berk