Course Outline Microeconomics 0 - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 17
About This Presentation
Title:

Course Outline Microeconomics 0

Description:

The state (guarantees protection of property rights) ... people decide only how to allocate time between leisure and picking apples and ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:103
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 18
Provided by: EngE91
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Course Outline Microeconomics 0


1
Course Outline Microeconomics 0
  • 1st week Introduction and Overview (chapter 1
    textbook)
  • Consumers and Preferences (ch. 2)
  • Demand and Behavior in Markets (ch. 3)
  • 2nd week Emergence of Markets and Exchange (ch.
    4)
  • Production, Technology, and Cost Functions
    (chs. 5, 6)
  • Game Theory (ch. 7)
  • 3rd week no lectures
  • 4th week Internal Organization of the Firm (ch.
    8)
  • Monopoly, Natural Monopoly, and Regulation
    (chs. 9, 10)
  • 5th week Midterm Exam
  • Oligopoly (ch. 11)
  • 6th week Market Entry (ch. 12)
  • Perfectly Competitive Markets (ch. 13)
  • 7th week Uncertainty and Insurance (ch. 14)
  • General Equilibrium, Welfare and Equity, Input
    Markets (chs. 15, 19)
  • 8th week Moral Hazard and Adverse Selection (ch.
    16)
  • Externalities, Public Goods and the Role of
    Government (chs. 17, 18)
  • 9th week Final Exam

2
Requirements and Grading
  • Problem Sets 20
  • Midterm Exam 30
  • Final Exam 50
  • Problem sets will be assigned regularly. They
    will be discussed by the teaching assistants in
    the exercise sessions.
  • Readings
  • Textbook Schotter, Andrew Microeconomics A
    Modern Approach. Second/Third Edition, New York,
    Addison Wesley, 1997/2001.
  •  
  • Further Suggested Reading
  • Nyarko, Yaw, 2001 Study Guide to Accompany
    Schotter, A. Microeconomics A Modern Approach.
  •  
  • Varian, Hal R. Intermediate Microeconomics A
    Modern Approach. Fourth Edition, New York,
    Norton, 1996 or Third Edition 1993.

3
Announcements
  • Extra Micro lecture Thursday, June 24th
  • Micro instead of macro lecture on Tuesday, June
    29th
  • Macro instead of micro lecture on Wednesday, July
    7th
  • Teaching Assistants
  • Vitezslav Babicky, Ekaterina Goldfain,
  • Sylvester van Koten

4
1. Overview Economics and Institutions
  • Institutions shape daily life, e.g. conventions
    to drive on the right side, wages including
    particular bonus systems, rules for decision
    making in committees, etc.
  • Definition Institutions can be conventions like
    tipping in a restaurant or sets of rules like the
    political system, more loosely institutions refer
    to large, established organizations
  • Economic Institutions refer to conventions
    developed to solve recurrent economic problems or
    sets of rules that govern economic behavior (and
    organizations that serve an economic purpose)
  • Often these institutions are taken for granted,
    but arrangements could be different, and in
    different societies they often are.

5
  • Microeconomics provides a technical apparatus for
    understanding why specific institutions are the
    way they are, i.e. it asks the question How do
    individuals, in an attempt to maximize their
    self-interest create a set of economic
    institutions that structure their daily lives?
  • Conventional Microeconomics How are scare
    resources allocated by one type of institutions
    markets?
  • allocation problem microeconomics helps to
    understand the question of allocation of scarce
    resources in two ways
  • How should the resources be spent, given certain
    objectives (Normative or welfare economics)
    economics does not prescribe or give advise on
    the objectives, though
  • How will the resources be spent, given a
    description of the decision making process, i.e.
    the institutions (Positive economics)
  • Positive question of institutional economics why
    do we have the set of institutions we have?
  • Normative question of institutional economics
    how can we design (or redesign) economic
    institutions to increase economic welfare?

6
  • Economic models are abstract representations of
    reality, can be in the form of mathematical
    models or analogies (in particular to games, to
    be analyzed by game theory)
  • The model used in Schotters book
  • Starts with primitive state of nature (no
    production)
  • then gradually introduces markets, production,
    firms, market entry, uncertainty (insurance
    companies), asymmetric information, external
    effects, public good problems
  • Three fundamental institutions are assumed to be
    present
  • The state (guarantees protection of property
    rights)
  • property rights (enhance the efficient use of
    resources, avoid tragedy of the commons)
  • economic consulting firms (as a tool to examine
    economic theory)

7
2. Consumers and their Preferences
  • People differ, but there are certain regularities
    of behavior. This part aims at identifying these
    regularities and understanding what they tell us
    about consumer preferences and decision making
  • primitive society without social institutions
  • people decide only how to allocate time between
    leisure and picking apples and raspberries and
    which mixture to consume (everything also works
    for more than 2 goods, but the graphs get ugly)
  • homo economicus (economic man) fictional
    perfectly rational decision maker

8
  • 2.1 The Consumption Possibility Set
  • set of bundles feasible for the agents to consume
  • not bounded from above, no economic restrictions
    incorporated yet
  • assumptions
  • divisibility goods are infinitely divisible
  • additivity if a and b can be consumed, so can
    a b
  • convexity if a and b can be consumed, then for
    any 0? ? ?1, the combination c?a(1- ?)b can be
    consumed as well

9
  • 2.2 Rationality
  • people are assumed to be rational, i.e. that
    they have preferences over available consumption
    bundles (notation aRb a is at least as good as
    b) and that these satisfy specific properties
  • complete binary ordering for all pairs a,b aRb
    or bRa holds. If both aRb and bRa hold, i.e. a is
    exactly as good as b the agent is indifferent
    between a and b, denoted aIb
  • Reflexivity for any bundle a, aRa
  • Transitivity if aRb and bRc, then aRc.
  • Why transitivity is important an intransitive
    agent can be exploited.

10
  • 2.3 The Economically Feasible Set
  • The economically feasible consumption set is
    bounded from above due to
  • time constraints assume that goods are only
    consumed in daylight, 12 hours of daylight are
    available and that it takes 4 hours to consume 1
    unit good 1 and 2 hours to consume 1 unit good 2.
    Due to divisibility and convexity the set of
    economically feasible consumption bundles is
    given by all bundles on or below the line of
    bundles that take exactly 12 hours to consume
    (Fig. 2.3)
  • budget constraints assume the agent has an
    income of 6, the cost for 1 unit of good 1 is 2
    and for 1 unit of good 2 it is 1. This leads to
    the same constraint as above

11
  • 2.4 Rationality and Choice
  • A complete, reflexive, transitive preference
    relation allows an agent to choose an optimal
    bundle from the economically feasible set.
    Without completeness, an optimal bundle might not
    exist since some bundles could not be ranked.
    Without transitivity, cycles can occur.
  • It is useful to express preferences by utility
    functions each bundle is assigned a utility
    number and the higher the number, the better the
    bundle. Choosing the best bundle then amounts to
    choosing the bundle that maximizes utility
  • utility need not be observable, but an agent with
    preferences as above will behave as if he is
    maximizing a utility function
  • required to be continuous, implies that for any
    bundle there is another bundle that is exactly as
    good.
  • counterexample lexicographic preferences (rank
    countries on liberty first and on availability of
    chocolate second)

12
  • examples
  • additive separable utility function U x y,
    enjoyment from good x is independent of level of
    consumption of good y
  • multiplicative utility function U x y, either
    good produces utility only if the other is
    consumed as well.
  • different types of utility function obviously
    imply different behavior
  • cardinal utility not only comparison between
    different utility levels is meaningful (higher
    is better) but also difference (20 is twice as
    good as 10)
  • ordinal utility only ranking meaningful, e.g. if
    there are two objects and a is preferred over b
    then both U1 with U1(a) 1000, U1(b) 0 and U2
    with U2(a) 2, U2(b) 1 represent the same
    preferences.

13
  • 2.5 Psychological Assumptions
  • We make the following assumptions about the
    psychological makeup of the agents
  • Selfishness people judge allocations only in
    terms of what they receive
  • Nonsatiation more of any good is always better,
    i.e. an allocation that contains more of one good
    and not less of the others is preferred. To
    include economic bads (that reduce utility) in
    the analysis, define as a good anything that
    removes or prevents the bad
  • Convexity of Preferences diversifying is always
    good, i.e. if aIb then any mixture such as ?a
    ?b is at least as good as a and at least as good
    as b

14
  • 2.6 Indifference Curves
  • Indifference curve line through all bundles that
    yield equal utility, i.e. through all bundles
    between which agent is indifferent
  • Indifference map diagram that depicts an agents
    indifference curves (Fig 2.7)
  • Each IC corresponds to one utility number, all
    bundles on that curve yield that level of utility
  • Properties
  • ICs dont slope upward (due to nonsatiation)
    (Fig 2.8)
  • ICs cannot cross (due to transitivity and
    nonsatiation) (Fig 2.9)
  • ICs farther from origin represent higher level
    of utility (due to nonsatiation) (Fig 2.10)
  • ICs are bowed to the origin (due to convexity
    and nonsatiation) (Fig 2.11)

15
  • The marginal rate of substitution
  • Assume we take -?x1 of good 1 away from the
    consumer. How much of good 2 do we have to give
    him to keep his utility level the same?
  • Let this be ?x2 . (Fig 2.12)
  • The marginal rate of substitution is - ?x2/ ?x1
    (actually the limit as these go to 0), the rate
    at which the consumer would be willing to trade
    good 1 for good 2.
  • the MRS equals the slope of the indiff. curve
  • convexity of preferences implies diminishing
    marginal rate of substitution, i.e. the MRS falls
    when we move along IC
  • we have MRS (?U / ?x1) / (?U / ?x2)

16
  • Different indifference curves represent different
    tastes (Fig 2.13)
  • flat lines good 1 yields no utility (strict
    nonsatiation violated)
  • straight lines perfect substitutes (constant
    MRS)
  • Right-angled indiff. curves perfect complements
  • Bowed-out indiff. curves non-convex preferences
    (increasing MRS).

17
  • 2.7 Optimal consumption bundles
  • which bundle will an agent choose to maximize her
    utility if she can choose from the economically
    feasible set?
  • the optimal consumption bundle is characterized
    by the indiff. curve being tangent to the budget
    line (Fig 2.15)
  • slope of indiff. curve and budget line are
    identical
  • MRS equals price ratio, i.e. rate at which agent
    is willing to trade good 2 for good 1 is equal to
    the rate at which she can trade good 2 for good 1
  • MRS p 1 / p2 .
  • Example Optimal tipping (violates selfishness
    assumption, this demonstrates that the apparatus
    can be applied to settings outside the basic
    framework) (Fig 2.18)
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com