Recap - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 40
About This Presentation
Title:

Recap

Description:

We know what cats and trees are like under normal conditions, but what about God? ... of us might find Bob warm and funny, another one might find him meek and ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:62
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 41
Provided by: legacy1
Category:
Tags: cats | funny | god | recap

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Recap


1
Re-cap
  • Types of Religious experience
  • 1. Experience of God/U.R. through a common,
    public sensory object
  • 2. Experience of God/U.R. through an unusual,
    public sensory object
  • 3. Experience of God/U.R. through a private
    sensation that can be described by appeal
    to normal sensory experience.
  • 4. Experience of God/U.R. through a private
    sensation that cannot be described by
    appeal to normal sensory experience.
  • 5. Experience of God/U.R. not through any
    sensations. One is directly and
    immediately aware of the divine presence, but is,
    strictly speaking, not having a sensation.
  • James
  • Religious experience as a special experience
    (feeling)
  • Which of 1-5 is it?
  • Arguments for it? (No science without
    phenomena to be explained. Similarly no
    religion with phenomena to be explained. Rel
    experience must be there and
    psychological study show us it is a
    feeling.)

2
Alston -- Religious Experience as Non-sensory
Perception
  • Some terms
  • i) experience of god direct
    experience/awareness of god
  • ii) mystical experiencenonsensory experience
    of god
  • iii) mystical perceptionform of perception
    involving M.E.
  • We will use n.s. experience and n.s.
    perception
  • Which of 1-5 does Alston advocate?

3
Initial Problems
  • Why focus on direct experience? B/c then we
    know how to assess the claims.
  • Why non-sensory? B/c God is non-sensory
  • Is the notion of nonsensory experience
    incoherent? (pg. 46/47)
  • Why would it be?
  • Alstons response

4
Alstons View
  • What is the structure of (ordinary) perception?
  • Take, e.g I perceive a cat.
  • There is
  • 1. A perceiver (me)
  • 2. Perceived object (the cat)
  • 3. The phenomenon (the appearance of the cat)
  • A is talking about perceptions un-mediated by
    concepts (Theory of Appearing)
  • Argument for the Theory of Appearing
  • Contrast Actually seeing a book vs. Thinking
    about a book
  • Something missing when I think about the book --
    same concepts in play.
  • Concepts can change perception, but there is
    still a perception there to be changed.
  • When I look at my living room, the same
    objects present themselves to my visual
    awareness as when I first saw it. It is
    essential not to confuse what appears with what
    it appears as. (pg. 48)

5
Alstons View (cont.)
  • Vs. James Mystical experience involves purely
    subjective feelings.
  • Problem Misses a large number of cases where
    people describe it as perceptual.
  • Alston does not deny the religious feeling
    account. He just thinks it overlooks a class of
    important (documented) cases.
  • Why is the perceptual account overlooked?
  • Because people question the existence of
    God.

6
Alstons View (cont.)
  • But, the truth of the perceptual model is
    independent of the truth of Gods existence.
  • Why?
  • Distinguish Phenomenological Accnt. of
    Experience
  • vs.
  • Occurrence of a Veridical Perception
  • Whats the difference?

7
Objections/Replies
  • Objection 1 Ordinary perceptual experience is
    common, filled with information, and available to
    all, whereas religious experience is
    rare/unusual, dim/vague, and esoteric.
  • So, it looks like religious/mystical experience
    cannot be captured on the perceptual model.

8
Objections/Replies (cont.)
  • Reply All that is being claimed is that direct
    experience of God has the structure of an
    ordinary perception. (So, the same conditions
    for a veridical perception would apply to both.)
  • To perceive X is for X to appear to me in a
    certain way.
  • (Namely Perceiver, Object,
    Phenomenon)
  • i) X must exist, ii) X must be making a
    causal contribution, and iii) X will
    tend to give rise to beliefs about X
    (the doxastic condition).

9
Objections (cont.)
  • Objection 2 In ordinary perception, the
    perceived qualities are sensory. But, in
    mystical experience the perceived qualities are
    non-sensory. This would make a difference at the
    level of structure.
  • The experience of the number 2. vs. The
    experience of looking at a cat.
  • Similarly, The experience of God vs. The
    experience of looking at a cat.
  • Experience of the number 2 is non-sensory.

10
Objections/Replies (cont.)
  • Response
  • Distinguish between
  • Phenomenal qualities and Objective qualities
  • Mystical and Ordinary perceptions have
    different phenomenal properties, but we express
    both using objective qualities -- (or comparative
    concepts -- mode of appearance in terms of the
    sort of objective thing that typically appears
    that way).
  • So, the structure still seems to be the same.
  • So, the experience of God is more like the
    experience of looking at a
  • cat, just with different phenomenal properties.
    So, when we report
  • religious experience we describe God under
    normal conditions.

11
Objections (cont.)
  • Obj How are we supposed to know what God is like
    under normal conditions?
  • We know what cats and trees are like under normal
    conditions, but what about God?

12
Objections/Replies (cont.)
  • Reply We have some experiences with the
    properties of God in others. (So, its by
    extension.)
  • Our subjects tell us that God presented Himself
    to their experience as a good, powerful,
    compassionate, forgiving being could be expected
    to appear.

13
Objections/Replies (cont.)
  • Obj But, this doesnt answer the question.
    Arent the properties we see in others -- e.g.
    goodness -- based in sense perception?
  • We understand how good people act from sensory
    experience of good people acting.
  • The normal conditions grow out of experience
    with the
  • phenomenal properties.
  • So, in order to know what God would be like
    under normal
  • conditions, we have to have some
    antecedent idea of his
  • phenomenal properties. (Any response? See
    end of lec.)

14
Objections/Replies (cont.)
  • This raises another problem How can we check
    any claim to have had a direct experience with
    God?
  • Ordinary perception I claim to have perceived
    a stain on G.W.s shirt. We can check with
    others, b/c they could confirm it.
  • Perception of God I claim to have experienced
    God.
  • Why is it hard to check that?

15
Proudfoot -- R.E. as Interpretation
  • Consider different ways we can see
  • I perceive a cat. What do we mean?
  • Do we mean to say A cat exists?
  • Case I perceive a cat. -- But, it was
    actually a trash bag.
  • Then you didnt perceive a cat.
  • Normal usage suggests that a perception implies
    that an object is there.

16
Proudfoot (cont.)
  • But, then whether people have religious
    experience (perception) depends on whether God
    exists (Alstons view).
  • This is too narrow. So, its not a perception.
  • P. thinks religious experience should not be
    characterized independent of the concepts we
    bring to the experience.
  • Contra James/Alston Religious experience is a
    highly conceptualized experience. We bring our
    belief system to the experience. Thats
    religious experience.
  • Rel. Experience cannot be understood without
    reference to religious beliefs. (Pg. 59)

17
Proudfoot (cont.)
  • For Proudfoot, what makes an experience a
    religious experience is that one takes the
    experience to be a rel. exp.
  • The description contains an embedded claim that
    God exists.
  • The explanation for the experience need not
    appeal to Gods exist..
  • An experience is a genuine religious experience
    if it is the product of the individuals belief
    system (regardless of the external world).
  • Religious experience is not an objective report
    -- its an expression of a theoretical commitment
    -- a way of seeing the world.

18
Objections
  • According to Proudfoot, is it even possible to
    experience God?
  • That is, our analysis of religious experience
    should not rule out the possibility that genuine
    religious experiences are direct experience with
    god (Alstons view).

19
Reply
  • No its not possible to have direct experience of
    God in Alstons sense. Because you dont
    directly experience anything unmediated by
    concepts.
  • Bear example (pg. 60)
  • Both experiences assume explanations. The first
    is not a pure experience.

20
Proudfoot (cont.)
  • So, how do we understand religious experience.
  • We learn the concepts of a culture and the
    psychological and personal histories of
    individuals who have religious experiences.
  • Once we understand that, we can understand the
    experience. We could, in some sense, see what
    they see.
  • Also, that is all the is involved in explaining
    experience (Proudfoot rejects the causal theory
    of perception -- when I perceive, something out
    there causes it.)

21
Perceptual vs. Interpretive Accnts.
  • Perceptual model We ask What caused the
    perception/appearance? If God/U.R., then it was
    genuine.
  • If not, then some deception.
  • Whats interesting about rel. exp. is the fact
    that, b/c its like perception, we could be
    directly experiencing God. ( We can assess such
    claims.)
  • Interpretive model All appearance is mediated
    by concepts.
  • We dont ask What (out there in the world)
    caused the appearance?, Instead we ask Why
    did so-and-so bring her religious beliefs to bear
    on this occasion or that occasion?
  • Whats interesting about rel. exp. is not
    whether we are experiencing God, but why we take
    ourselves so often to experience God.

22
Martin and the Arg. Based on Rel. Exp.
  • Can religious experience justify religious
    belief?
  • Argument that it can pg. 67
  • The fact that one has a religious experience is
    sometimes used to justify ones belief (that God
    exists, or other beliefs).
  • On the feeling account, can experience justify
    belief?

23
Martin (cont.)
  • Dilemma for the feeling account
  • If religious experience is ineffable, then it
    cannot be used to ground religious belief.
    (Why?)
  • If religious experience is s.t. it could ground
    religious belief, then it is not ineffable.
  • (Why?)
  • Maintaining that its ineffable is supposed to
    make it immune from rational criticism -- so it
    can be the basis for religious systems. But, the
    dilemma shows that you cannot have both.

24
Martin (cont.)
  • On Proudfoots view, can religious experience
    justify religious belief?

25
Martin (cont.)
  • No.
  • Why not?
  • The experience is constituted by the beliefs.
  • The experience Of God is the experience of God
    Existing, but this requires that you bring a
    whole set of beliefs to your interpretation of
    the world.
  • So, experience could not justify belief.

26
Martin (cont.)
  • What about for Alston?
  • Religious Experience is a type of perception.
  • Can it justify belief?

27
Martin (cont.)
  • In principle, yes.
  • Just as we use our ordinary perceptual
    experiences to justify our ordinary beliefs about
    the external world, we could use our religious
    experiences (if they are best understood as
    perceptions) to justify religious beliefs, IF the
    supernatural explanation is the best one.
  • I see a dog in the park.
  • Im justified in believing that there is a dog in
    the park, as long as I have no reason to think
    that somethings not working right or Im being
    tricked, etc.
  • I see God.etc

28
Martin (cont.)
  • Objection to the perceptual model
  • We could be mistaken about our religious
    experience.
  • Response?
  • Leads to The Principle of Credulity
  • (PC) When it seems (epistemically) to a subject
    S that x is present, then probably x is
    present.
  • Only deny what they say if there are mitigating
    considerations.

29
Martin (cont.)
  • The burden of proof is on the one who claims that
    the experience is not genuine.
  • So, if religious experience is a type of
    perception, then we should take it to provide
    good grounds for the belief that God exists.
    Unless there are mitigating circumstances.
  • If Alston is right, religious experience provides
    prima facie evidence for the existence of God.

30
Martin (cont.)
  • How to argue against the Alston-inspired view.
  • Point to mitigating considerations in each case.
  • Reject the principle of credulity in the
    religious case.
  • Martin adopts the second approach.
  • The first is difficult. (see pg. 74)

31
Martin (cont.)
  • Since experiences of God are good grounds for
    the existence of God, are not experiences of the
    absence of God good grounds for the nonexistence
    of God?
  • Negative Principle of Credulity
  • (NPC) If it seems (epistemically) to a subject S
    that x is absent, then probably x is absent.
  • If it seems like a chair is not present, then a
    chair is probably not present.

32
Martin (cont.)
  • Many people have tried to see God, but do not.
    What these people see is his absence.
  • Assuming that many people claim to perceive God
    and that many people claim to perceive his
    absence, where does this leave us?
  • At most, the claims of Gods absence (based on
    experience) and his existence (based on
    experience) are on equal footing.
  • So, people like Alston seem vindicated.
  • Writing assignment What do you think
    Swinburnes argument in response is? Evaluate the
    argument. (see pg. 75)

33
Martin (cont.)
  • For Martin, we should take religious experience
    as unreliable.
  • Because of the common perception of Gods
    absence.
  • Because of the conflicting perceptions of God.
    (Why?)
  • Regarding the second argument The fact of
    differing reports is not enough to generate an
    argument against the reliability of religious
    experience.
  • Two people standing in front of a piece of art
    or architecture, might see different things.
    But, that does not make us question the existence
    of the painting or building.
  • The reports must be conflicting.
  • Even there, though, the conflicts may not cause
    a problem if there is a way to determine which
    claims are more reliable (some may be more
    coherent).

34
Further Objections
  • Further objection 1
  • In order to make justified claims based on
    perceptual experience, the experience must be
    verifiable.
  • Ordinary perception is verifiable.
  • Religious experience (God visited me at 3 a.m.
    9/14/2006) is not.
  • Why wouldnt it be?

35
Further objections (cont.)
  • Response The claims are not verifiable in a
    straightforward way, but thats because
    perception of God is like a perception of a
    person.
  • We perceive people in different ways One of us
    might find Bob warm and funny, another one might
    find him meek and awkward.
  • We cant require everyone to experience God in
    the same way. So, the verifiability requirement
    is altered a bit in the case of Gods qualities.
  • Further there are checks/tests on religious
    experience natural theology (various arguments
    about Gods existence) can help us tell which
    experiences are more likely veridical.

36
Objections (cont.)
  • Objection The tests of religious experience
    will be more indirect than the tests of normal
    perception.
  • I perceive this white board.
  • How do I test/check that?
  • I reach out and touch it.
  • Then I look at it again, etc

37
Objections (cont.)
  • Response Is that really how we test sensory
    perceptions?
  • If so, then there is a big problem
  • If the first perception is unreliable, why arent
    all the others?
  • If we have to check things this way, then we have
    an infinite regress problem (each check will
    require a check, but then that check will require
    a check, on and on and on.)
  • The way out of this problem We have a
    background belief system that we use to help
    confirm our experiences. That system is based in
    experience, but there is no independent check
    (just the framework of beliefs, what other people
    say and our past experiences). Can work this way
    for religion too.

38
Further objections (cont.)
  • Objection 2 Relgious experiences/perceptions are
    claimed to be indubitable. But, then, this turns
    the claims into claims about appearances and not
    about the thing perceived.
  • I perceive a white board.
  • Whats indubitable there?
  • The appearance, not the existence of the board.

39
Objections
  • The perceptual model aims to make religious
    experience more like ordinary perceptual
    experience.
  • So, the indubitability that God exists, will not
    come from the experience. (Maybe from a claim
    about conceptual necessity.)
  • Rather, the experience gives us good prima facie
    evidence for our beliefs. Its just as good as
    the exp. of ordinary objects.

40
Convinced?
  • So, the appeal to religious experience (on the
    perceptual model) can at least put belief in God
    on the same footing as belief in the external
    world.
  • Is the perceptual model the best one?
  • Is the above conclusion justified?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com