Title: CPHL406 Contemporary Moral Issues II
1CPHL406Contemporary Moral Issues II
2- We can conceptually distinguish between at least
three vegetarian positions - Compassionate Vegetarianism The view that we
ought to refrain from eating animals due to the
harm it causes animals. -
3- Dietary Vegetarianism The view that we ought to
refrain from eating animals due to its harm to
human health. - It is now well-established that humans can live
quite healthily on a vegetarian (or even vegan)
diet. Indeed multiple studies have found that
vegetarians tend to be healthier than meat
eaters benefits included lower rates of coronary
heart disease, type II diabetes, hypertension and
several forms of cancer. - For example, The Oxford Vegetarian Study, a
12-year study of 6000 vegetarians and 5000
meat-eaters, found a 28 lower incidence of
coronary heart disease mortality among
vegetarians than among matched omnivores.
4- Environmental Vegetarianism The view that we
ought to refrain from eating animals due to its
harm to the environment. - In the U.S., more than half of all water consumed
is used for raising animals for food. It takes
2500 gallons of water to produce a pound of meat,
but only 25 gallons to produce a pound of wheat. - The meat industry is the greatest polluter of
U.S. waters, producing nearly 90 000 pounds of
excrement every second - The worlds cattle consume food equivalent to the
caloric intake that would feed nine billion
people.
5Background facts
- We are directly concerned with position (i), but
the three positions are closely connected. - For example, compassionate vegetarians often
support their view by appealing to the fact that
humans at least do not require meat to be
healthy thus, given the suffering that meat
consumption causes to animals, it is immoral. - And many vegetarians appeal to all three
positions in making their case.
6Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A1 Humans are naturally meat eaters. We have
evolved to eat meat, and we naturally take
pleasure in eating meat. Thus it is morally
permissible to eat meat.
7Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- Objections
- O1A1 First, if the claim Humans are naturally
meat eaters is supposed to mean that humans
are biologically unsuited to a purely
vegetarian diet, then it is surely false. It is
probably true that historically we have largely
been an omnivorous species, and that
biologically we are quite capable of consuming
meat but it is also true that we can survive
quite healthfully on a vegetarian diet.
8Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A1 The mere fact that we are able to do X and
/ or enjoy doing X does not make doing X morally
acceptable. - We have many natural inclinations - such as
those to selfishness, violence and sexual
promiscuity - that we are often morally
obliged to suppress. Meat eating may or may not
be one of those suppression-worthy inclinations,
but we cant simply assume that since it is
natural it need not be suppressed.
9Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A2 Eating meat is part of the Circle of Life,
the cycle of life and death that pervades the
natural world.
10Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O1A2 The Circle of Life in the broad sense
- the interaction of life forms with their
environment and each other, and their coming
into and out of existence - is certainly a
wonderful, mysterious, valuable thing worth
participating in. But - (i) causing animals to suffer and die
seems a lousy way of maintaining a
connection with them and - (ii) we are part of the life cycle (in the
broad sense) whether we want to be or not,
whether we eat animals or not.
11Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A2 The Circle of Life in a narrower sense
seems to mean something like predation. In
this sense it is not clearly in itself a good
thing. In fact it seems prima facie to be a
very bad thing, one that we ought to avoid if
possible. Predation is certainly common
throughout the natural world, but this does not
entail that it is morally acceptable for humans
to participate in it when they have the choice
not to.
12Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A3 Millions of people (e.g. farmers,
slaughterhouse workers) depend for their
livelihood on the meat industry. - O1A3 That a persons sole source of income is
from activity X is clearly not sufficient reason
for us to conclude that activity X is morally
acceptable. Example slave trade
13Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A3 It is not clear that anyone depends, in a
deep sense, on the meat industry for their
livelihood - First of all, in large industrialized societies
it is rarely if ever the case that an individual
has only one means available to him of generating
income. - Second, a societal switch to vegetarianism (if it
were to occur) would involve a gradual loss of
meat industry jobs, probably offset by gains in
related industries (e.g. the processed soy
industry).
14Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A4 We have natural dominion over all other
animals.
15Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O1A4 If this claim is simply an appeal to the
authority of the Bible, then it is weak in the
ways that most such claims are - (i) it is subject to intra-religious conflict
over interpretation (e.g., domination or
stewardship?) - (ii)it is absolutely irrelevant for those who
do not already subscribe to the
Judeo- Christian tradition and - (iii) It seems to involve selective reading of
the Bible, since the Bible commands us to do
many things that Jews and Christians today
ignore and would find morally abhorrent.
16Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A4 It is probably true that we are the most
powerful species on the planet, but might does
not make right we are able to use animals for
our own ends, but that does not show that it is
morally acceptable to do so. - Analogy Imagine a powerful alien species,
whose religion gives them dominion over all
the species of the universe, who raise humans
for meat. Would that be right?
17Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A5 The life of an animal on a farm is better
than it would be in nature so we do not make
it worse off than it would otherwise be by
raising it and killing it for food. - O1A5 If were talking about animals on factory
farms, it is highly unlikely that their life is
better than animal life in the wild.
18Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A5 The farm animals in question wouldnt even
exist if we didnt want them for food nor does
vegetarianism demand that they ought to be
released into the wild. The real issue is
whether we are permitted to bring them into
existence in the first place. - Thus the choice isnt between a wild existence
and domesticated one it is between existence
and non- existence, or perhaps between varying
qualitative levels of domesticated existence. - Well postpone discussion of O2A5 to our
critical analysis of Peter Singers position.
19Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- A6 There is too much human suffering in the
world to waste our time and energy worrying
about animal rights. - O1A6 To end the suffering of farm animals we do
not need to do anything we simply need stop
doing something, namely, eating meat.
20Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O2A6 Vegetarianism is not an alternative to
caring about humans. An increased concern for
animals is a natural expression of ones
increasing sensitivity to suffering in all
forms, part of a pattern of moral development
whose end point is full compassion for all
sentient beings.
21Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- O3A6 Increased vegetarianism helps people
directly by its positive effects on the
environment, human health, and the global
distribution of wealth.
22Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- Isn't man an amazing animal? He kills wildlife
by the millions in order to protect his domestic
animals and their feed. Then he kills domestic
animals by the billions and eats them. This in
turn kills man by the millions, because eating
all those animals leads to degenerative --
and fatal -- health conditions like heart
disease, kidney disease, and cancer. So then man
tortures and kills millions more animals to look
for cures for these diseases. Elsewhere,
millions of other human beings are being killed
by hunger and malnutrition because food they
could eat is being used to fatten domestic
animals. - Meanwhile, some people are dying of sad
laughter at the absurdity of man, who kills so
easily and so violently, and once a year sends
out cards praying for "Peace on Earth." - - C. David Coats
23Common Arguments in Defense of Eating Meat
- "As long as Man continues to be the ruthless
destroyer of lower living beings he will never
know health or peace. For as long as men
massacre animals, they will kill each other.
Indeed, he who sows the seed of murder and pain
cannot reap joy and love." - - Pythagoras
24Kant, Our Duties to Animals
- Kants view on animals is part of a long Western
tradition that excludes animals from the realm of
moral concern - Western philosophy has often tied the moral worth
of a being to its rational capacities, and by
that measure, animals have been thought to fall
short. - Aristotle, in ancient Greece, and Descartes, in
the 17th century, believed that moral worth is
linked to the power of thought, expressed in
language, and that animals, without linguistic
ability, are therefore without intrinsic moral
worth. - For Descartes, animals are mere biological
machines without any sort of consciousness
25Kant, Our Duties to Animals
- According to Kant, we have only indirect duties
to animals our treatment of animals is morally
relevant only insofar as it affects our treatment
of people
26Kant, Our Duties to Animals
- Remember Kants 2nd Categorical Imperative Never
treat a person as a mere means to an end. - People are rational, autonomous beings and
therefore of intrinsic worth, according to Kant.
- They are not mere things to be used, but
independent centres of value . - Since animals are not self-conscious (Kant says)
it is morally permissible to treat them simply as
means to an end. They are, in a sense, mere
things.
27Kant, Our Duties to Animals
- But Kant also argues that animals have
analogies to human nature for example, a dog
can serve its master long and faithfully. - For this reason our interaction with animals is
good training ground for our interaction with
humans for example, by rewarding the dogs
loyalty with kindness, we develop a general
capacity for kindness that we then express in our
dealings with people. - Hogarths Four Stages of Cruelty, to which
Kant refers in the reading, can be seen here - http//bugpowder.com/andy/e.hogarth-cruelty.html
28Kant, Our Duties to Animals
- A couple of potential problems for the Kantian
view - If animals are indeed analogous to humans in what
seem to be morally relevant features (e.g. their
love of their young their loyalty their
capacity for suffering), why do we not have any
direct duties towards them? - 2. Is our treatment of animals really as
influential on our treatment of humans as Kant
argues? Surely there are many slaughterhouse
workers, vivisectionists, deer hunters, and fans
of bull fighting who are compassionate and
respectful in their dealings with humans.
29Singer, Animal Liberation
- Anti-vivisection societies were formed in England
and the U.S. in the at the end of the 19th
century. But the animal welfare and rights
movements more generally are usually thought to
have gained widespread prominence in the 1970s. - One important event in the recent rise to
prominence of the movement was the publication,
in 1975, of Peter Singers book Animal
Liberation, sometimes referred to as the bible of
the animals rights movement.
30Singer, Animal Liberation
- Singers position is in conscious opposition to
that Aristotelian-Kantian Western philosophical
tradition of identifying rationality to be the
hallmark of moral worth. - He is also consciously opposed to any claim,
theologically grounded or otherwise, that makes
membership in the human species a necessary
condition of moral worth. He is thus opposed to
speciesism, which, he claims, is just as
arbitrary and unethical as sexism or racism.
31Singer, Animal Liberation
- For Singer, if a being is conscious in a way that
makes it capable of feeling pleasure and pain, of
suffering and enjoying, then we ought to take
that beings interests into consideration when we
are determining how we ought to act with regard
to it. - With this principle Singer follows Bentham, the
founding father of utilitarianism, who famously
proclaimed - The question is not, Can they reason? nor,
Can they talk? but rather, Can they suffer?
32Singer, Animal Liberation
- Singer elaborates on Benthams dictum as follows
- If a being suffers there can be no moral
justification for refusing to take that suffering
into consideration. No matter what the nature of
the being, the principle of equality requires
that its suffering be counted equally with like
suffering - insofar as rough comparisons can be
made - of any other being. If a being is not
capable of suffering, or of experiencing
enjoyment or happiness, there is nothing to be
taken into account. So the limit of sentienceis
the only defensible boundary of concern for the
interests of others. To mark this boundary by
some other characteristic like intelligence or
rationality would be to mark it in an arbitrary
manner. Animal Liberation, 1975
33Singer, Animal Liberation
- Singers argument is clearly utilitarian.
- In deciding what we ought to do, we must
consider the interests of all those beings who
may be affected by our actions, and then choose
that course of action that brings about the
greatest satisfaction of interests.
34Singer, Animal Liberation
- Let us call the following The Singer/Bentham
Interest Principle - A necessary and sufficient condition of an
individuals having interests is that
individuals capability of suffering or enjoying. - Singer believes that this principle is one
which most of us will intuitively recognize as
plausible, but he gives the following
illustration to make its plausibility vivid
35Singer, Animal Liberation
- It would be nonsense to assert it was not in the
interests of a stone to be kicked along a road by
a schoolboy. - A stone does not have interests because it cant
suffer. Nothing we can do to it could make a
difference to its welfare. - But it would absurd to say that a mouse has no
interest in not being kicked along the road. - It has said interest because it will suffer if it
is kicked along the road.
36Singer, Animal Liberation
- Any animal presumably has an interest in not
suffering and dying so that we can eat it. - We have a competing interest in nourishing
ourselves, and in enjoying the taste of meat and
the traditions surrounding its consumption (e.g.
Christmas ham). - But in this case the utilitarian case seems to be
overwhelmingly against meat consumption. Our
interests in eating meat are trivial in
comparison to the animals interest in not
suffering and dying.
37Singer, Animal Liberation
- Singer argues that the animal liberation
movement is part of our more general moral
evolution that has in recent decades extended
goods and rights to women, non-whites, and
homosexuals. - One might think that the animal liberation
movement is disanalogous with those other
movements because while humans deserve to be
treated equally - since they are in fact
equal to each other - animals are not equal
to humans, and thus we are not obligated to treat
their interests on par with our own.
38Singer, Animal Liberation
- Singer agrees that humans are superior to animals
in a variety of significant ways but so are some
humans superior to other humans in a variety of
attributes such as strength, intelligence and
even moral integrity. - Thus if we give preference to human interests
over animal ones because we are (for example)
more intelligent than them, we should also give
preference to more intelligent humans over less
intelligent humans. But clearly we should not
give preference to more intelligent humans, says
Singer. - The moral imperative to treat beings equally has
nothing to do with the relevant beings
abilities, apart from their abilities to suffer
and enjoy. - The essential aim of morality is the minimization
of suffering and the extension of well-being
thus the only sensible criterion for inclusion in
the realm of moral consideration is a beings
capacity to suffer and enjoy.
39Singer, Animal Liberation
- Thus Singer does not simply claim that animals
are equal to humans his position is more
complex than that. - An animal interest is, taken in isolation, as
equally worthy of moral consideration as a
similar human interest for example, a chimps
pleasure from quenching its thirst is, in itself,
of a moral value equal to a humans equivalent
pleasure. - But because humans generally have a greater
capacity for good-maximizing, it is often morally
preferable to prefer humans over animals for
example a typical human life is usually more
worth saving over a typical animal life. - Of course meat-eating involves giving preference
to trivial human interests over the fundamental
interests of animals, and hence is unjustified.
40Singer, Animal Liberation
- Lets call Singers position AS
- O1AS Utilitarians actually have a duty to consume
meat, so long as the lives of slaughtered
animals are, on the whole, of greater utility
than 0. For without the meat industry they
would never have existed their existence
contributes to the greater happiness more
than their non-existence would. - Something like this objection is advanced by
Roger Crisp in Utilitarianism and
Vegetarianism, International Journal of Applied
Philosophy, 4.1 41-49.
41Singer, Animal Liberation
- R1O1AS One might respond that at present meat
consumption is not justified by this sort of
objection since in modern factory farming
conditions it is very unlikely that the animals
lives are of greater value than 0 their
suffering far outweighs their enjoyment. - Even if their lives are of greater value than
0, we might still have (from a utilitarian
perspective) an obligation to dramatically
improve their condition.
42Singer, Animal Liberation
- R2O1AS By this logic we have a utilitarian
obligation (it at least is morally permitted by
utilitarianism) to bring any beings into
existence whose lives would, on balance, be of
more utility than 0. For example, it would seem
to permit the scenario envisioned in the movie
The Island, where certain humans live
comfortably but only (unbeknownst to them) to
provide organs for others. Thus either - (i) Utilitarianism has morally absurd
implications and should be dropped (Singer
wouldnt argue this way) or - (ii) We have misapplied utilitarianism the
vast amount of time and resources required to
comfortably raise and slaughter billions of
animals could be better spent on improving the
condition of beings already in existence.
43Singer, Animal Liberation
- R3O1AS A hybrid utilitarianism which seeks not
simply to maximize utility but also a good ratio
of happiness to unhappiness, might respond that
meat consumption probably creates a situation
where the overall ratio of happiness to
unhappiness is much worse than it is without
meat consumption, even if it maximizes utility.