Title: Issues in Contemporary Metaphysics
1Issues in Contemporary Metaphysics
2Recap
- Last lecture I introduced what ontology consists
in finding out what things exist, namely
numbers, works of music, properties etc. - I tried to give you some idea of why people think
these kinds of questions are open questions. - Importantly I introduced the notion of Quinean
ontological commitment and paraphrase. - Quine says that to find out the commitments of
sentences, we figure out the logical form (in
first order predicate logic) of the proposition
that sentence expresses.
3Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
4Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
5Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
6Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
7Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
8Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
9Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
10Recap
- So the sentence The average man has 2.4
children might be thought, due to its surface
grammar, to express the proposition - The average man exists, and stands in the is a
parent of relation to 2.4 children. - That sentence has the logical form
- ? x ? y1 ? y2 ? y3 ( x average man y1 is a
child y2 is a child y3 is 40 of a child
xRy1 xRy2 xRy3 ) - Where R is the relation of being a parent of
11Recap
- But thats nuts, so you might offer a paraphrase.
- The surface grammar might make it sound like it
commits to 40 of a child, but we can instead say
it actually expresses a different proposition. - Say
- The number of men divided by the number of
children equals the 2.4 - ? x ? y ? z ( x the number of men y the
number of children z 2.4 Rxyz ) - Where R is the three-place relation __ divided
by __ equals __
12Recap
- So hopefully that goes someway to explaining what
a paraphrase is meant to be. - The sentence has a surface grammar, but expresses
a different proposition that doesnt commit us to
the existence of unwanted things. - Is that the correct paraphrase?
- Maybe not, after all it still commits us to
numbers
13On with the show
- So, with that all in mind, lets move on to doing
some ontology. - Along the way, well see other facets of how
ontology is studied and practised. - Today well look at properties.
- Do they exist? (i.e. should we be realists or
anti-realists with regards to properties) - If they do exist, what are they like?
14On with the show
- So, with that all in mind, lets move on to doing
some ontology. - Along the way, well see how other facets to how
ontology is studied and practised. - Today well look at properties.
- Do they exist? (i.e. should we be realists or
anti-realists with regards to properties) - If they do exist, what are they like?
15Realism vs. Anti-realism of Properties
- Well look at two reasons to believe in
properties Abstract reference and the problem
of universals - This isnt exhaustive. For instance, David Lewis
has more to say in New Work for a Theory of
Universals.
16Abstract Reference
- Before turning to the motivation for properties,
lets just look at some simple sentences. - All footballs are round
- ? x ( Fx ? Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is a football and
G is the predicate __ is round. - The prime minister is Scottish
- ? x ( Fx Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is the prime
minister and G is the predicate __ is Scottish - Theres something over there, and its either
blue or pink - ? x ( Fx v Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is pink and G is
the predicate __ is blue
17Abstract Reference
- Before turning to the motivation for properties,
lets just look at some simple sentences. - All footballs are round
- ? x ( Fx ? Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is a football and
G is the predicate __ is round. - The prime minister is Scottish
- ? x ( Fx Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is the prime
minister and G is the predicate __ is Scottish - Theres something over there, and its either
blue or pink - ? x ( Fx v Gx )
- Where F is the predicate __ is pink and G is
the predicate __ is blue
18Abstract Reference
- So simple sentences like that dont (under the
Quinean theory of ontological commitment) commit
us to the existence of properties. - Well see, when we turn to the problem of
universals, that not everyone agrees this is
true. - But for now, lets just examine things from the
Quinean point of view. - Given those sentences there is no commitment to
properties. - All we commit to are material objects, and then
say how they are. Theres no commitment to
properties as well.
19Abstract Reference
- This was the view of Goodman and (the early)
Quine. - No properties, just things being one way rather
than another.
20Abstract Reference
- But if only things were so simple.
- As you might remember from last lecture, not
every sentence is so easy. - Lets try some harder ones.
21Abstract Reference
- (1) Your car and my car are both blue
- Slightly harder, but still pretty easy. Let F be
__ is blue - (1) ? x ? y ( x my car y your car Fx
Fy) - But now try
- (2) Our cars are the same colour
- Cant use (1), as (2) could be true even though
our cars arent blue. - They could both be yellow.
22Abstract Reference
- Perhaps make it a disjunctive paraphrase?
- ( x is blue y is blue ) v ( x is red y is red
) v ( x is yellow y is yellow ) - Of course, even this wont work!
- Imagine I asked you to paint some cars.
- You paint one azure, and the other Alice Blue.
- Thats pretty different, but theyre both blue.
- Clearly two cars painted like that wont, in most
contexts, be the same colour.
23Abstract Reference
- So the paraphrase must be extended even more! A
disjunct for every shade of blue (and red! And
yellow! And green!) - And of course, even then there will be different
hues of Azure that differ. - There are infinitely many different hues of
colour! - (2) ? x ? y ( x my car y your car ( x
is colour 1 y is colour1 ) v ( x is colour 2
y is colour2 ) v ( x is colour 3 y is
colour3 ) v ( x is colour 4 y is colour4 ) v
( x is colour 5 y is colour5 ) v ( x is
colour 6 y is colour6 ) v ( x is colour 7
y is colour7 ) v ( x is colour 8 y is
colour8 ) v ( x is colour 9 y is colour9 ) v
( x is colour 10 y is colour10 ) v
24Austere Nominalism
- This attempt to live without properties, and
instead offer paraphrases, is called austere
nominalism - (sometimes ostrich or mirage nominalism)
- So austere nominalists can give a paraphrase for
that sentence. - But its infinitely long, and contains an
infinite number of colour predicates. - This is one of the facts that makes people wonder
whether austere nominalism is true and whether we
can live without properties.
25Austere Nominalism
- So far weve looked at figuring out the
commitments of theories. - But we havent discussed how to weigh up those
theories in light of those commitments. - Lets talk about that to see why austere
nominalism appears to have negatives.
26Comparing Theories
- What criteria do we use?
- Well, thats not settled.
- We look at the costs and the benefits and then do
the cost/benefit analysis. - Heres some examples
- Avoid paradoxes and cohere with our beliefs.
- Offer an explanation.
- Parsimony.
- Simplicity.
27Criterion One Avoid Paradoxes and Problems
- If P and Q entail a contradiction, you need a
theory that either misses out P or Q, or explains
how they dont entail a contradiction. - Such paradoxes (the NSE paradox) plague those who
believe in properties, and there are alleged
paradoxes about material objects (statue/clay).
28Criterion One Avoid Paradoxes and Problems
- A good theory will also cohere with things we
know to be true (by necessity). - And its generally better for it to cohere with
things we intuitively think to be true. - 224 should be true!
- Pockets should have holes!
- Some things are cars, or are blue!
- Blue is a colour!
- Of course, we can make sacrifices this is
philosophy after all. - And some things are always up for grabs
- (Spoils to the victor as Lewis puts it)
29Criterion One Avoid Paradoxes and Problems
- Compare with ethics.
- A theory is awful if it says torturing five year
olds for pleasure is fun. - A theory has issues (but still believable) if it
says you have to give up on some minor ethical
belief say that speeding drivers are morally on
a par with those who run over people. - Sometimes we take these issues to be big enough
to think the theory unbelievable. - Alternatively we might take those issues as
generating results. - So we might take that issue as being a result of
the theory.
30Criterion One Avoid Paradoxes and Problems
- Similarly in metaphysics.
- Theories that cohere with intuition are better
than those that dont. - And some intuitions are more deeply held than
others. - So contradicting certain intuitions is more
costly than contradicting certain other
intuitions.
31Criterion Two Explanatory Power
- Not only should your theory cohere with things we
generally think to be true, it should explain
other truths. - For instance, there is a law concerning how fast
objects that fall accelerate towards the planet
Earth. - Similarly, the are other laws concerning how fast
objects accelerate on other planets. - But all of those laws are explained by a single,
more general, law concerning gravitation in
general. - So one truth (the general law concerning
gravitation) explains other truths (the specific
laws concerning gravitation on other planets).
32Criterion Two Explanatory Power
- But some truths will be inexplicable.
- They will not be explained by other truths in
your theory they are brute truths. - Its generally thought to be a virtue for your
theory to have as few brute truths as possible. - In having less brute truths it has more
explanatory power, and offers explanations where
weaker theories just state things as inexplicable
fact.
33Criterion Three Parsimony about entities
- Sometimes called Ockhams Razor.
- Its a benefit to have less things in your
theory. - If youve got two exactly equivalent theories,
say they both explain exactly the same things,
but one has more things in it than the other,
its clear you should choose the more
parsimonious theory.
34Criterion Three Parsimony about entities
- Example The dead body, me and the bloody axe.
- Theory A says I did it.
- Theory B says an invisible alien spacecraft did
it. - Example Physics.
- If there are two theories whereby theory one
says one type of entity is responsible for some
phenomena, and the other theory says fifty eight
types of entity working in combination are
responsible, its a bonus to pick theory one. - Of course there might be a reason to favour a
less parsimonious theory, say if youd seen the
58 entities. Or you were the alien in the
spacecraft. - But then those theories wouldnt have equal
explanatory power. - More importantly, whilst the lack of parsimony is
a cost it might not be a cost that outweighs
certain other benefits.
35Criterion Four Theoretical Simplicity
- Not only do we favour theories which are
economical and have explanatory power we favour
theories which are simple. - Usually, this simplicity is captured by having
few primitives. - A primitive of a theory is a undefinable
predicate. - Lets have some examples.
36Criterion Four Theoretical Simplicity
- Example one
- Maths.
- You could take __ is a triangle, __ is a
square etc. as primitive predicates. - As there are an infinite number of shapes, there
would be an infinite number of primitives - But most dont. We can explain what it is to be a
triangle and a square - x is a triangle df x has three sides which are
connected at all and only their endpoints. - x is a square df x has four sides which are
connected at all and only their endpoints - That would then explain all shape predicates in
terms of three primitives (__ having n sides
__ is an endpoint _is connected to __) - Indeed these definitions and primitives can be
supplanted by better definitions with a superior
stock of primitives.
37Criterion Four Theoretical Simplicity
- Example two
- You could take __ knows that P as primitive.
- But many people try to analyse it.
- So you might analyse it in terms of being a
justified true belief. - Think back to Gettier.
38Criterion Four Theoretical Simplicity
- The consensus is that having less primitives is a
good thing. - In the same way that taking brute truths is a
cost, taking on primitives is a cost. - It means your theory is more complex.
39The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- The idea is that once you figure out how a theory
scores on these sorts of criterion (those listed
are not exhaustive!) you can evaluate it. - Where it does well on a criterion you have a
benefit. - Where it doesnt do well you have a cost.
40The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- So the realists about properties score well on
certain criteria. - Their theory has one primitive __ instantiates
__ - So it provides the benefit of theoretical
simplicity. - But it populates your ontology with lots of
entities namely the properties. - So it has issues with ontological parsimony.
41The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- The nominalist, however, has no properties.
- They have a theory that is very ontologically
parsimonious. - But now we can return back to where we were
before we went off on this tangent.
42Austere Nominalism
- This attempt to live without properties, and
instead offer paraphrases, is called austere
nominalism - (sometimes ostrich or mirage nominalism)
- So austere nominalists can give a paraphrase for
that sentence. - But its infinitely long, and contains an
infinite number of colour predicates. - Its that fact that makes people wonder whether
austere nominalism is true and whether we can
live without properties.
43The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- The nominalist, however, has no properties.
- They have a theory that is very ontologically
parsimonious. - But now we can return back to where we were
before we went off on this tangent. - Their theory is very complicated.
- So much so, many people favour realism.
44The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- Moreover, even if you are happy with that amount
of primitives, there are other problems ahead. - They might be able to paraphrase
- (2) Our cars are the same colour
- at the expense of theoretical simplicity. But
some sentences look even more resilient to
paraphrase.
45The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- Try
- (3) Blue is a colour.
- Thats a bugger to paraphrase.
- It appears to assert ? x (x blue x is a
colour) - But thats to quantify over a property!
- Could paraphrase it as Everything that is blue
is coloured - Problematic in that if, by chance, all the blue
objects were, say, whales then that would mean
that Everything that is blue is a whale - (3) Blue is a water borne mammal (?)
46The Cost/Benefit Analysis
- Or try
- (4) There are as yet undiscovered physical
properties. - (5) Red resembles orange more than it resembles
blue - If we cant paraphrase these sentences at all,
wed have a problem. - I leave you to look at the literature concerning
such paraphrases - Although it was concerns like this that drove
Quine to accept the existence of properties.
47The Problem of Universals
- In the literature there is often said to be The
Problem of Universals - It is often advanced as a reason to believe in
properties. - Armstrong is the most famous contemporary
proponent. - There are lots of different interpretations of
the Problem of Universals - Everyone agrees on one thing it is poorly named.
- Its not a problem about universals at all! Its
meant to be an argument for them! - NB Sometimes called the One Over Many.
48The Argument from Resemblance
- The interpretation Ill examine (which isnt the
only one!) is to think its a problem about
resemblance - Universals are introduced to explain (or
ground, or analyse) how two things can have
something in common. - We might also take this to mean how things can
resemble one another. - Is there a difference between those two?
- Well, thats just part of the problem of getting
to grips with what the Problem of Universals is
meant to be.
49The Argument from Resemblance
- We arrange things into similarity classes.
- Example All the blue things are similar all the
purple things all the men all the women. - Some classes arent similarity classes.
- Example A class with you, me, a Burmese farmer,
the left hands of the entire cast of Eastenders,
Brad Pitts toilet, and the black hole Cygnus
X-1.
50The Argument from Resemblance
- Its not enough that things fall under the same
predicate to be similar. - Example x is F y is G, define H as being the
predicate of being F v G. - x is H and y is H, but they dont have anything
in common (surely!) - Its not a real resemblance.
- So we could make up a predicate that those
dissimilar classes of entities fell under.
51The Argument from Resemblance
- Properties would come to our rescue.
- Say Not every predicate is a property.
- Got to say that anyway because of NSE paradoxes.
- Things exactly resemble one another if and only
if they have all their properties in common. - Varying degrees of resemblance are matched by
having varying numbers of properties in common. - So whilst two objects both fall under the
predicate H they may not resemble as they may
still fail to have properties in common.
52Recap
- So weve looked at some reasons to believe in
properties. - Weve looked at the basics of cost/benefit
analysis, and how we weigh up which theories are
better than other theories. - Weve seen that living without properties
allegedly gives you a complex theory. - Moreover, we might have difficulty finding a
suitable paraphrase at all - Ive mentioned the Problem of Universals, and
given you Armstrongs interpretation of it that
we need properties to explain how objects
resemble on another. - Were done today for the motivations for
believing in properties.
53On with the show
- So, with that all in mind, lets move on to doing
some ontology. - Along the way, well see how other facets to how
ontology is studied and practised. - Today well look at properties.
- Do they exist? (i.e. should we be realists or
anti-realists with regards to properties) - If they do exist, what are they like?
54Varieties of Realism
- This is where the terminology becomes rather
confusing. - Lots of people believe properties exist but
they dont call themselves realists. - In fact, they often go on to call themselves
nominalists. - Realism, with regards to properties, is usually
to endorse the existence of properties as
universals - Whereas nominalism is taken to refer both to not
believing in properties and to believing in
properties but not as these universals
55Varieties of Realism
- The term universal is normally reserved for
properties that exist as sui generis entities. - A sui generis entity is an entity in a category
of its own - That is, that things from that category cant be
identified with things from other categories you
already accept. - Well come back to that notion in a bit.
56Varieties of Realism
- There are divisions amongst those who believe in
universals. - They are divided along two dimensions
- Where are the properties?
- Which predicates correspond to properties?
- Connected Are there uninstantiated properties?
57Varieties of Realism
- There are divisions amongst those who believe in
universals. - They are divided along two dimensions
- Where are the properties?
- Which predicates correspond to properties?
- Connected Are there uninstantiated properties?
58Varieties of Realism
- If properties exist, where are they?
- Platonists think that the properties arent
located anywhere. - Theyre abstract and outside space and time.
- We saw some problems with that last week.
- Others say theyre in space and time.
- Locate them where their instances are located.
- So being a human is located where I am.
- And where you are.
- And where every other human is.
59Varieties of Realism
- Heres the twist. Usually, such realists say the
universal is entirely located at each instance. - So whereas I am only entirely located at one
place (a man shaped region), universals get to be
multiply located - Which is a bit weird (how can all of something be
in exactly one place?) - Example Red being 5m away from itself.
- Ill leave you to look into why they say these
things.
60Further Reading
- Parsons, J. 2007. Theories of Location, Oxford
Studies in Metaphysics 3. - Hudson, H. 2005. The Metaphysics of Hyperspace
ch. 4. - Gilmore, C. 2006. Where in the relativistic world
are we? Philosophical Perspectives - Armstrong, D. Various.
61Varieties of Realism
- There are divisions amongst those who believe in
universals. - They are divided along two dimensions
- Where are the properties?
- Which predicates correspond to properties?
- Connected Are there uninstantiated properties?
62Varieties of Realism
- Do uninstantiated properties exist?
- Platonists say yes, theyre all there in Platonic
heaven. - Aristotelians disagree somehow the universals
depend on their being instantiated. - If they do exist, where are they?
- If they dont exist, does that mean truths about
uninstantiated properties turn out to be false? - Example How can this be true
- (5) Red resembles orange more than it resembles
blue - If nothing is red, orange or blue and
uninstantiated universals dont exist?
63Varieties of Realism
- But there are other problems. Not every predicate
can correspond to a property. - Example There can be no property of not self
exemplifying - So which predicates correspond to a property?
What universals/properties are there? - Being a human? Being a monkey?
- Happy, Sad
- Depressed about being dumped by a crap
significant other who then went on to run away to
Barbardos with some girl called Julie? - Red, Blue, Green?
- Crimson, Scarlet, Puce, Amaranth?
64Varieties of Realism
- Also concerns about conjunctive, disjunctive and
negation properties. - If being a sword exists and being rusty exists is
there a separate universal of being a rusty
sword? - If being a human exists and being a dog exists is
there a separate universal of being either a dog
or a human? - If being a human exists is there a universal of
not being a human as well? - What are the conditions for a universal/property
existing?
65Varieties of Realism
- One answer is Armstrongs.
- He believes in sparse universals.
- The only way to find out what universals there
are is a posteriori. - The universals that exist are those posited by
our best scientific theory. - So the only universals will be things like having
spin up, or being charged or having mass of 0.511
MeV.
66Varieties of Realism
- But if the universals are sparse, how does that
deal with the motivations? - Being annoyed is worse than being happy is
true, but apparently being annoyed isnt a
property. - So youll need a paraphrase!
- Wasnt avoiding that what realism was meant to
help with?
67Varieties of Realism
- Or the argument from resemblance, which is
Armstrongs favourite motivation. - If being a human isnt a universal, we cant
resemble one another by sharing that universal. - We could resemble one another by being charged,
or having the same mass in MeV, but other than
that, we dont. - You should go off and read how Armstrong tries to
deal with this by using structured universals
68Recap
- So weve
- Looked at motivations to believe in properties
- If we do believe in properties they are either
sui generis (universals) or not. Again, more
on this notion to come - What properties are like i.e. what ones there
are? Where are they? - Whilst most people talk about these solely in
connection with universals, it applies to all
those who think properties exist.
69Properties without universals
- I said universals were sui generis in a
category of their own. - Perhaps theyre not.
- Why should one care? What does it even mean?
- Well, recall one of the principles of choosing
theories.
70Comparing Theories
- What criteria do we use?
- Well, thats not settled.
- We look at the costs and the benefits and then do
the cost/benefit analysis. - Heres some examples
- Avoid paradoxes and cohere with our beliefs.
- Offer an explanation.
- Parsimony.
- Simplicity.
71Comparing Theories
- What criteria do we use?
- Well, thats not settled.
- We look at the costs and the benefits and then do
the cost/benefit analysis. - Heres some examples
- Avoid paradoxes and cohere with our beliefs.
- Offer an explanation.
- Parsimony.
- Simplicity.
72Properties without universals
- Austere nominalists achieved parsimony by not
believing in universals at all. - The realist thus far discussed takes a hit on
parsimony by introducing properties as a new
category of entities. - So, say, they have objects and properties.
73Properties without universals
- But theres another way to be parsimonious
without eliminating properties entirely. - We can identify (alternatively, reduce which
may or may not be the same thing) properties to
things we already believe in. - For instance, to preserve various conservation
principles physicists believed in neutrinos
tiny little, hard to detect particles. - Its also the case that theres a lot of
unaccounted for matter in the universe dark
matter. Its very hard to detect, but must exist
for various calculations to make any sense. - A proposed theory might say that a whole new
category of entity exists dark matter. - A more parsimonious theory would say that the
dark matter exists, but its just the neutrinos. - Theory one has two distinct categories of
entities (neutrinos/dark matter) whilst the other
theory still has those categories, but theyre
just not distinct.
74Properties without universals
- In ontology, we might do the same.
- For instance, if you start by believing in
objects you might be a realist about properties
but exact parsimony by saying that properties
really are just objects property is a
sub-category of object - And, as its a sub-category, property isnt sui
generis its not in a category of its own - However this would be a whacky reduction. Surely
properties arent objects! - Exception mereological nominalism / exploded
object nominalism
75Properties without universals
- But maybe if our ontology had more categories of
things, we could do better. - For instance, if you believed in concepts we
might be on a winner. - So you have objects and then, in addition, you
believe in concepts. - You might then identify the property red with the
concept red. - And say that an object instantiates red if and
only if it falls under that concept.
76Properties without universals
- These realists about properties would be often
called nominalists (so they believe in properties
but not universals, as universals have to be sui
generis). - There are serious problems with concept
nominalism Im using it as an example to
demonstrate parsimony not suggesting its
perfect. - Well see another example of nominalism next week
when we introduce sets.
77Recap
- Weve
- Looked at the motivations for properties
- Looked at different versions of theories that
believe in universals. - Explained what sui generis means and given
examples of theories with properties that arent
sui generis
78Next Lecture