Resolution method - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

About This Presentation
Title:

Resolution method

Description:

... is a philosopher who disagrees with all the philosophers, then he disagrees ... interpretation is over the set of individuals, P subset of philosophers, Q ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:49
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 31
Provided by: Marie3
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Resolution method


1
Lesson 9
  • Resolution method
  • (continuing, examples)

2
Verifying an argument
  • (Anybody) who knows Paul and Mary is sorry for
    Mary. ?x ( Z(x, P) ? Z(x, M) ? L(x, M) )
  • Some are not sorry for Mary, though they know
    her. ?x ?L(x, M) ? Z(x, M)
  • Somebody knows Mary, but does not know Paul. ?x
    Z(x, M) ? ?Z(x, P)
  • ?x ?Z(x, P) ? ?Z(x, M) ? L(x, M) implication
    elimination (1. assumption)
  • ?L(a, M) ? Z(a, M) Scolemising (2.
    assumption)
  • ?y ?Z(y, M) ? Z(y, P) negation of conclusion
    (and renaming x)
  • Clauses
  • 1. ?Z(x, P) ? ?Z(x, M) ? L(x, M)
  • 2. ?L(a, M) (2. assumption is a
    conjunction
  • 3. Z(a, M) two clauses arise!)
  • 4. ?Z(y, M) ? Z(y, P)
  • 5. ?Z(a, P) ? ?Z(a, M) resolution 1., 2.,
    substitution a/x
  • 6. ?Z(a, P) resolution 3., 5.
  • 7. ?Z(a, M) resolution 4., 6., substitution
    a/y
  • 8. resolution 3., 7.
  • We obtained an empty clause, i.e., the negated
    conclusion contradicts the premises thus the
    non-negated original conclusion logically follows
    from the premises.
  • The argument is valid.

3
Remark Compare the proof of this argument with
the semantic proof (lesson 6, slides 22, 23)
  • We demonstrate the truth-conditions of the
    premises first the predicates Z and L are
    interpreted as the relations ZU and LU,
    respectively
  • ZU , ?i1,m?, ? i1,k?, ?i2,m?,
    ?i2,k?,,??,m?,
  • 1. premise 2. premise
  • LU , ?i1,m?, ...., ?i2,m?,.........,
    ??,m?,
  • and so on, by the method of an indirect proof

4
Indirect proof of the validity of an argument
  • We make use of the following equivalence valid
    for closed formulas
  • P1,...,Pn Z iff (P1 ?...? Pn) ? Z
  • Moreover (P1 ?...? Pn) ? Z iff the negated
    formula is a contradiction (P1 ?...? Pn ? ?Z)
  • Hence, the argument is valid iff the negated
    conclusion Z contradicts the conjunction of
    premises. Indeed, compare with the definition of
    the validity of an argument
  • P1,...,Pn Z iff Z is true in every model
    of the set of premises P1,...,Pn iff
  • ?Z is true in no model of the set of premises.

5
Proofs of the validity
  • Prove, that the following statement
  • If there is a philosopher who disagrees with all
    the philosophers, then he disagrees with himself
    as well
  • is logically true.
  • We analyse this sentence in following
    way(intended interpretation is over the set
    of individuals, P ? subset of philosophers, Q ?
    relation the couples of individuals where the
    first member disagrees with the second)
  • We prove the logical validity of the formula
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y (P(y) ? Q(x,y)) ? Q(x,x)
  • First, negate the formula and transform it into
    clausul form
  • ?x ?y P(x) ? ?P(y) ? Q(x,y) ? ?Q(x,x).
  • The set of clauses1. P(x) 2. ?P(y) ? Q(x,y)3.
    ?Q(x,x) the substitution y/x is the most
    general unifier
  • 4. Q(x,x) resolution 1. and 2.5.
    resolution 3. and 4.

6
Proofs of the validity
  • Prove the logical validity of following
    statement
  • There is somebody such that if he\she is a
    genius, then everybody is a genius.
  • Formula ?x G(x) ? ?x G(x) (mind the
    brackets!)
  • We prove, that the negated formula is a
    contradiction
  • ?x G(x) ? ?x ?G(x), renaming variables gives
  • ?x G(x) ? ?y ?G(y), step 6 ?x G(x) ? ?y
    ?G(y) and by Scolemizing we have
  • ?x G(x) ? ?G(a).
  • G(x)
  • ?G(a)
  • resolution 1. and 2., substitution a/x
  • We obtained an empty clause, i.e., the negated
    formula is a contradiction so the original
    formula is a tautology.

7
  • Every member of the management is an obligation
    owner or a shareholder.
  • No member of the management is an obligation
    owner and also a shareholder.
  • Every obligation owner is a member of the
    management.
  • 4. No obligation owner is a shareholder.
  • ?x V(x) ? (O(x) ? A(x))
  • ?x V(x) ? ?(O(x) ? A(x))
  • ?x O(x) ? V(x)
  • ?x O(x) ? ?A(x)
  • Clauses 1. ?V(x) ? O(x) ? A(x) 1. premise
  • 2. ?V(y) ? ?O(y) ? ?A(y) 2. premise
  • 3. ?O(z) ? V(z) 3. premise
  • 4. O(k) negated conclusion
  • 5. A(k) (after Scolemization)
  • 6. ?O(y) ? ?A(y) resolution 2., 3.,
    substitution z/y
  • 7. ?A(k) resolution 4., 6., substitution
    y/k
  • 8. resolution 5., 7.
  • Note that we do not use the first clause in the
    proof sequence. So conclusion is a consequent of
    the second and the third premise (the first one
    is superfluous for infering the conclusion).

8
  • Everybody who likes George will collaborate
    with Michael.
  • Michael is a friend of nobody who is a friend of
    Luke.
  • Peter will collaborate only with the friends of
    Charles.
  • If Charles is a friend of Luke, then Peter does
    not like George.
  • ?x L(x, G) ? C(x, M)
  • ?x F(x, L) ? ?F(M, x)
  • ?x C(P, x) ? F(x, Cr)
  • F(Cr, L) ? ?L(P, G)
  • Clauses
  • 1. ?L(x, G) ? C(x, M) 1. premise
  • 2. ?F(y, L) ? ?F(M, y) 2. premise
  • 3. ?C(P, z) ? F(z, Cr) 3. premise
  • 4. F(Cr, L) negated
  • 5. L(P, G) conclusion
  • 6. ?F(M, Cr) resolution 4., 2., substitution
    y/Cr
  • 7. ?C(P, M) resolution 3., 6., substitution
    z/M
  • 8. ?L(P, G) resolution 1., 7., substitution
    x/P

9
What are the logical consequences of premises?
  • Variant of the preceding example. Premises do
    not contain existential statement.
  • Everybody who likes George will collaborate
    with Michael.
  • Michael is a friend of nobody who is a friend of
    Luke.
  • Peter will collaborate only with the friends of
    Charles.
  • Charles is a friend of Luke.
  • ???
  • Clauses
  • 1. ?L(x, G) ? C(x, M) 1. premise
  • 2. ?F(y, L) ? ?F(M, y) 2. premise
  • 3. ?C(P, z) ? F(z, Cr) 3. premise
  • 4. F(Cr, L) 4. premise
  • 5. ?F(M, Cr) inference, resolution 2,4, y/Cr
  • 6. ?L(P, G) ? F(M, Cr) inference, resolution
    1,3, x/P, z/M
  • 7. ?L(P, G) inference, resolution 5,6
  • 8. ?C(P, M) inference, resolution 3,5, z/M

10
Indirect proof of the validity of an argument
  • All men like football and beer.
  • Xaver likes only those who like football and
    beer.
  • There is somebody who likes football but does not
    like beer.
  • Anybody who is not a man is a woman. (we must
    not omit tacit premises)
  • Some women are not liked by Xaver.
  • ?x M(x) ? (R(x,f) ? R(x,p)) 1. premise
  • ?x R(Xa,x) ? (R(x,f) ? R(x,p)) 2. premise
  • ?x R(x,f) ? ?R(x,p) 3. premise
  • ?x ?M(x) ? Z(x) 4. premise
  • ? ?x Z(x) ? ?R(Xa,x) negated conclusion

11
Indirect proof of the argument
  • Clauses
  • 1. ?M(x) ? R(x,f) first
  • 2. ?M(x) ? R(x,p) premise
  • 3. ?R(Xa,y) ? R(y,f) second
  • 4. ?R(Xa,y) ? R(y,p) premise
  • 5. R(k,f) third premise
  • 6. ?R(k,p) after Scolemization x/k
  • 7. M(z) ? Z(z) 4. premise
  • 8. ?Z(u) ? R(Xa,u) negated conclusion
  • 9. ?R(Xa,k) resolution 4., 6. (y/k)
  • 10. ?Z(k) resolution 8., 9. (u/k)
  • 11. M(k) resolution 7., 10. (z/k)
  • 12. R(k,p) resolution 2., 11. (x/k)
  • 13. resolution 6., 12.
  • We have found out again that the negated
    conclusion contradicts the premises, so that the
    argument is valid.
  • Do you know which premises were not necessary for
    inferring the conclusion?

12
Proof by the resolution method
  • If a number is even then its second power is
    even .
  • If a number is even then its fourth power is
    even .
  • ?y P(y) ? P?f(y)?
  • ?x P(x) ? P(f(f(x))) negate it
  • ?x P(x) ? ?P(f(f(x))) Scolemise
  • P(a) ? ?P(f(f(a))) write down the clauses
  • ?P(y) ? P?f(y)? premise
  • P(a) negated
  • ?P(f(f(a))) conclusion
  • P(f(a)) resolution 1-2, substitution y/a
  • P(f(f(a))) resolution 1-4, substitution y/f(a)
  • resolution 3-5, contradiction
  • The argument is valid.

13
Mathematical induction
  • P(a), ?y P(y) ? P?f(y)? ? ?x P(x)
  • Is the derived formula a logicall consequence of
    the premises? In other words, is the
    mathematical-induction rule correct, i.e., does
    it preserve truth?
  • Clauses
  • P(a)
  • ?P(y) ? P(f(y))
  • P(f(a)) inference 2.1., subst. y/a
  • P(f(f(a))) inference 2.3., subst. y/f(a)
  • P(f(f(f(a)))) inference 2.4., subst. y/f(f(a))
  • and so on, ad infinitum.
  • We cannot prove it by the indirect proof as well,
    because the negated conclusion is (after
    scolemising) ?P(b) and the terms b, a, f(a),
    f(f(a)), are not unifiable. We never prove that
    ?x P(x) the case of the actual infinity. We can
    only reach the potential infinity potentially
    we can go ad infinitum but not really.

14
Verifying the consistence
  • There is a barber who shaves just all those who
    do not shave themselves.
  • Does this barber shave himself?
  • ?x ?y ?H(y,y) ? H(x,y) ? H(x,x)
  • In Lesson 7 we have seen that the premise is a
    contradiction so such a barber does not exist.
    We prove it by the resolution method. We add the
    negated conclusion to the premise and write down
    the clauses.
  • ?x ?y ?H(y,y) ? H(x,y) ? H(x,x)
  • H(y,y) ? H(a,y) ? H(a,a) substitution y/a
  • ?H(y,y) ? ?H(a,y) ? ?H(a,a) substitution y/a
  • ?H(x,x)
  • resolution 1., 2., substitution y/a
  • We dont need the third clause (negated
    conclusion) in order to infer the contradiction.
    So the premise is contradictory.
  • Such a barber does not exist.

15
Note
  • Robinsons algorithm of the general resolution
    and unification operates also on particular
    literals of a clause. For instance, from the
    clauses
  • 1. P(x,y) ? ?Q(a,f(y)) ? P(x,a) ? ?Q(y,x) ?
    P(f(a),a) ? ?Q(a,f(a))
  • 2. ?P(f(z),z) ? ?P(v,a) ? ?P(f(a),a)
  • we derive the resolvent ?Q(a,f(a)),
  • after the unification x/f(a), y/a, z/a,
    v/f(a),
  • because the first clause is unified into
    P(f(a),a) ? ?Q(a,f(a)) and the second into
    ?P(f(a),a).

16
Note Pay attention to equivalences
  • Formula A ? B is not contradictory, it is
    satisfiable
  • Formula A ? ?A is contradictory
  • Clauses ad a)
  • ?A ? B
  • A ? ?B
  • now in each step we can generate the resolvent
    by the resolution of only one pair of literals,
    so no empty clause is derived
  • 3. B ? ?B
  • 4. A ? ?A
  • Clauses ad b)
  • ?A ? ?A ? ?A
  • A ? A ? A
  • 1. and 2. resolve into the empty clause

17
Checking the consistence
  • Mr X changed his job and got a more qualified one
    (K).
  • Mr X knows the wage-payment system very well (M).
  • If Mr X changed his job for the more qualified
    one, then it is right to discuss his case (P).
  • If is it right to discuss his case, then he
    should not be a member of the commission (C).
  • If he knows the wage-payment system very well,
    then he should be a member of the commission.
  • What are the logical consequences?
  • We check the consistence of the set of statements
    first.
  • K ? M ? (K ? P) ? (P ? ?C) ? (M ? C)
  • K
  • M
  • ?K ? P
  • ?P ? ?C
  • ?M ? C
  • P resolution 1, 3
  • ?C resolution 4, 6
  • C resolution 2, 5
  • contradiction resolution 7, 8
  • The given set of statements is contradictory so
    anything follows.

18
Checking the validness of a formula
  • ? ?x P(x) ? ?y ?x (?Q(x,y) ? ?z R(a,x,y)) ?
    ?z (P(b) ? Q(f(z), z)) ? R(a, f(b), z)
  • We transform the antecedent to the clause form
  • By the method of Skolem algorithm
  • We transform it to the prenex form at first and
    then we scolemise it.

19
Checking the validness of a formula vs step 6
  • Antecedent transformation to the clause form,
    procedure a)
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?x (?Q(x,y) ? ?z R(a,x,y))
  • Steps 2., 5. Renaming variable x and eliminating
    ?z
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?u (?Q(u,y) ? R(a,u,y))
  • Step 3. Elimination of the implication
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?u (Q(u,y) ? R(a,u,y))
  • Step 6. Moving the quantifier ?x to the left
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?u (Q(u,y) ? R(a,u,y))
  • Step 7. Skolemization (i.e., substituting g(y)
    for the varible u the symbol f is used in the
    conclusion, so we have to use a new one)
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y (Q(g(y), y) ? R(a, g(y), y))
  • Step 8. moving the quantifier to the left
  • SK1 ?x ?y P(x) ? (Q(g(y), y) ? R(a, g(y),
    y)).

20
Checking the validness of a formula vs step 6
  • Antecedent transformation to the clause form,
  • procedure b) without step 6
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?x (?Q(x,y) ? ?z R(a,x,y))
  • Steps 2,5 Renaming variable x and eliminating
    ?z
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?u (?Q(u,y) ? R(a,u,y))
  • Step 3. Elimination of the implication
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y ?u (Q(u,y) ? R(a,u,y))
  • Step 7. Skolemization (i.e., substituting g(x,y),
    for the varible u, because the variable u is at
    the scope of ?x)
  • ?x P(x) ? ?y (Q(g(x,y), y) ? R(a, g(x,y), y))
  • Step 8. removing the quantifier to the left
  • SK2 ?x ?y P(x) ? (Q(g(x,y), y) ? R(a, g(x,y),
    y)).

21
Checking the validness of a formula vs step 6
  • The negated conclusion (is in the clausal form
    already)
  • ?z (?P(b) ? ?Q(f(z), z)) ? ?R(a, f(b), z).
  • We attempt to prove a contradiction with SK1
    (clausal form of the antecedent)
  • We write the clauses down, procedure a)
  • P(x) premise
  • Q(g(y), y) ? R(a, g(y), y) premise
  • ?P(b) ? ?Q(f(z), z) negated conclusion
  • ?R(a, f(b), z) negated conclusion
  • ?Q(f(z), z) resolution 1., 3., substitution x /
    b
  • ???
  • We cannot derive any more resolvents, because
    terms g(y) a f(z), or g(y) and f(b) are not
    unifiable.
  • The Formula is not a tautology.

22
Checking the validness of a formula vs step 6
  • We are not able to prove the contradiction with
    SK2 (procedure b) with the negated conclusion
    either
  • P(x)
  • Q(g(x,y), y) ? R(a, g(x,y), y)
  • ?P(b) ? ?Q(f(z), z)
  • ?R(a, f(b), z)
  • ?Q(f(z), z) resolution 1., 3., substitution x / b
  • However, we cant procede further, because the
    terms g(x,y) and f(z), possibly g(x,y) and f(b),
    are not unifiable.
  • Conclusion The Formula is not a tautology.

23
Exercise, a puzzle
  • Tom, Peter and John are members of a sport club.
    Every member of the club is a skier or a climber.
    No climber likes raining. All skiers like snow.
    Peter does not like what Tom likes, and does like
    what Tom does not like. Tom likes snow and
    raining.
  • Question Is there in the club a sportsman who
    is a climber but not a skier?
  • Solution Knowledge base ( query 11)
  • SC(t)
  • SC(p)
  • SC(j)
  • ?x SC(x) ? (SKI(x) ? CLIMB(x))
  • ?x CLIMB(x) ? ?LIKE(x,r)
  • ?x SKI(x) ? LIKE(x,s)
  • ?x LIKE(t,x) ? ?LIKE(p,x)
  • ?x ?LIKE(t,x) ? LIKE(p,x)
  • LIKE(t,s)
  • LIKE(t,r)
  • ? ?x SC(x) ? CLIMB(x) ? ?SKI(x)

24
Exercise, a puzzle
  • Knowledge base (in Clausal form negated query
    11)
  • SC(t) sport-club(tom).
  • SC(p) sport-club(peter).
  • SC(j) sport-club(john).
  • ?SC(y) ? SKI(y) ? CLIMB(y) each club member is
    a skier or a climber
  • ?CLIMB(z) ? ?LIKE(z,r) each climber does not
    like raining
  • ?SKI(v) ? LIKE(v,s) each skier does not like
    snowing
  • ?LIKE(t,x1) ? ?LIKE(p,x1) Tom and Peter have
    opposite
  • LIKE(t,x2) ? LIKE(p,x2) tastes
  • LIKE(t,s) like(tom, snow).
  • LIKE(t,r) like(tom, raining).
  • ?SC(x) ? ?CLIMB(x) ? SKI(x) Query
  • Proof by resolution that 1-11 is inconsistent. In
    other words, we are looking for an instantiation
    of the variable x, that leads to a contradiction.
  • ?LIKE(p,s) res. 9, 7 by substituting s for x1
  • ?SKI(p) res. 12, 6 by substituting p for v
  • ?SC(p) ? CLIMB(p) res. 13, 4 by substituting p
    for y
  • CLIMB(p) res. 14, 2
  • Resolution 11 2 13 15 by substituting
    p for x.
  • (Obviously, the solution is p Peter)

25
Checking the validness of an argument
  • Situation A couple of friends met a priest A,
    who said The first man whom I confessed was a
    murder. After a while Mr B came, looked at the
    priest and said I was the first man whom the
    priest A confessed.
  • Question Did the priest offend against the
    confessional secrecy?
  • Reení ?x (x f(A)) ? V(x)
  • B f(A)
  • ???
  • (Intended interpretation Let f be a function
    that assigns to the priest the only man confessed
    by the priest as the first one)
  • Clauses 1. ?(x f(A)) ? M(x) 1. premise
  • 2. B f(A) 2. premise
  • 3. M(B) inference resolution (B is a
    murder) 1.,2., substitution x/B
  • Solution The priest offended against the
    confessional secrecy.

26
Prolog foundations (the logic)
  • Method of (pure) logic programming is a special
    case of the general resolution method. Compared
    to the general resolution method, it has the
    following restrictions
  • it works just with Horns clauses (they have one
    positive literal at most),
  • it uses the linear strategy of generating
    resolvents together with the process of
    backtracking

27
Prolog foundations (the logic)
  • In logic programming we use the following
    terminology
  • Notation P- Q1, Q2,..,Qn. (is equivalent to
    ?Q1 ? ?Q2 ? ? ?Qn ? P,
  • or to (Q1 ? Q2 ? ? Qn) ? P ) conditional
    statement (rule)
  • Notation P. unconditional statement (fact)
  • Notation?- Q1, Q2,..,Qn.(is equivalent to ?Q1 ?
    ?Q2 ? ? ?Qn) targets /target clauses,
    queries/
  • Notation, YES contradiction /an empty clause /

28
Prolog foundations (the logic)
  • Logic program is a sequence of conditional
    statements (rules) and unconditional statements
    (facts). Target clause set queries that the
    program tries to reply.
  • Note Commands are understood as being declared
    by stating the rules and facts. So logic programs
    are declarative (not imperative). We only specify
    what is to be done and do not determine in
    which way to do it.

29
Prolog foundations (the logic)
  • Example
  • All students are younger than Peters mother.
    Charles and Mary are students. Who is younger
    than Peters mother?
  • Notation in PL1 ?x St(x) ? Ml?x,matka(p?),
    St(k), St(m) ?
  • Program in Prolog (Notice variables - capitals,
    constants - small letters)
  • younger(X, mother(peter))- student(X). rule
  • student(charles). fact
  • student(mary). fact
  • ?- younger(Y, mother(peter)). Query, target
    goal
  • The interpreter performs unification and
    resolution following the linear strategy driven
    by target
  • Target ?- younger(Y, mother(peter)) is unificated
    with younger (X, mother(peter)), YX
  • New target is generated ?- student(Y)
  • This target is unificated with the 2. fact in the
    database success with Ycharles
  • Itll figure out the reply YES, Y charles
  • We can enter semicolon which means that we
    are asking Who next?. It envokes backtracking,
    i.e., the process of returning to the last target
    and attempting to execute it again ?-
    student(Y). Now the interpreter cannot use the
    2. clause again (it remembers the place that has
    been used already) but it can use 3. clause
  • e) Itll figure out the reply YES, Y Mary
  • NO

30
Prolog foundations (the logic)
  • As stated above, logic programs are declarative
    (not imperative). We specify what is to be done
    and do not determine in which way it is to be
    done.
  • The interpreter finds the way how to reply the
    queries, i.e., it deduces which are the logical
    consequences of the specified knowledge base and
    which values have to be substitutiated for
    variables by unification (answers).
  • However, the restriction to Horn clauses can
    cause troubles. See the example of a puzzle
    (slides 19, 20)
  • Try to formulate this puzzle in Prolog!
  • Summary of the restrictions
  • one positive literal at most (no disjunction in
    the consequent),
  • we are not able to specify negative facts
    directly.
  • Negation as failure of inferring!
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com