Title: CSCE 580 Artificial Intelligence Ch.9: Inference in First-Order Logic
1CSCE 580Artificial IntelligenceCh.9 Inference
in First-Order Logic
- Fall 2008
- Marco Valtorta
- mgv_at_cse.sc.edu
2Acknowledgment
- The slides are based on the textbook AIMA and
other sources, including other fine textbooks and
the accompanying slide sets - The other textbooks I considered are
- David Poole, Alan Mackworth, and Randy Goebel.
Computational Intelligence A Logical Approach.
Oxford, 1998 - A second edition (by Poole and Mackworth) is
under development. Dr. Poole allowed us to use a
draft of it in this course - Ivan Bratko. Prolog Programming for Artificial
Intelligence, Third Edition. Addison-Wesley,
2001 - The fourth edition is under development
- George F. Luger. Artificial Intelligence
Structures and Strategies for Complex Problem
Solving, Sixth Edition. Addison-Welsey, 2009
3Outline
- Reducing first-order inference to propositional
inference - Unification
- Generalized Modus Ponens
- Forward chaining
- Backward chaining
- Resolution
4Universal instantiation (UI)
- Every instantiation of a universally quantified
sentence is entailed by it - ?v aSubst(v/g, a)
- for any variable v and ground term g
- E.g., ?x King(x) ? Greedy(x) ? Evil(x) yields
- King(John) ? Greedy(John) ? Evil(John)
- King(Richard) ? Greedy(Richard) ? Evil(Richard)
- King(Father(John)) ? Greedy(Father(John)) ?
Evil(Father(John)) - .
- .
- .
5Existential instantiation (EI)
- For any sentence a, variable v, and constant
symbol k that does not appear elsewhere in the
knowledge base - ?v a
- Subst(v/k, a)
- E.g., ?x Crown(x) ? OnHead(x,John) yields
- Crown(C1) ? OnHead(C1,John)
- provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a
Skolem constant - Logical equivalence is not preserved, because
skolemization adds new constants to formulas
however, the new KB is satisfiable iff the old
one is satisfiable (s-equivalence) - In general, skolemization adds Skolem function,
as in - ?x ?y Is_Father(y,x), which skolemizes to ?x
Is_Father(Father(x),x)
6Reduction to propositional inference
- Suppose the KB contains just the following
- ?x King(x) ? Greedy(x) ? Evil(x)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- Instantiating the universal sentence in all
possible ways, we have - King(John) ? Greedy(John) ? Evil(John)
- King(Richard) ? Greedy(Richard) ? Evil(Richard)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- The new KB is propositionalized proposition
symbols are -
- King(John), Greedy(John), Evil(John),
King(Richard), etc.
7Reduction ctd.
- Every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to
preserve entailment - (A ground sentence is entailed by new KB iff
entailed by original KB) - Idea propositionalize KB and query, apply
resolution, return result - Problem with function symbols, there are
infinitely many ground terms, - e.g., Father(Father(Father(John)))
8Reduction ctd.
- Theorem Herbrand (1930). If a sentence a is
entailed by an FOL KB, it is entailed by a finite
subset of the propositionalized KB - Note Herbrand showed that no new constants have
to be introduced (so, in the example, the only
constants needed are John and Richard), except
for one in case the KB contains no constants, in
which case one constant must be introduced - Idea For n 0 to 8 do
- create a propositional KB by instantiating
with depth-n terms - see if a is entailed by this KB
- Problem works if a is entailed, may loop forever
if a is not entailed - Theorem Turing (1936), Church (1936) Entailment
for FOL is semidecidable (algorithms exist that
say yes to every entailed sentence, but no
algorithm exists that also says no to every
non-entailed sentence.)
9Problems with propositionalization
- Propositionalization seems to generate lots of
irrelevant sentences. - E.g., from
- ?x King(x) ? Greedy(x) ? Evil(x)
- King(John)
- ?y Greedy(y)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- it seems obvious that Evil(John), but
propositionalization produces lots of facts such
as Greedy(Richard) that are irrelevant - With p k-ary predicates and n constants, there
are pnk instantiations.
10Unification
- We can get the inference immediately if we can
find a substitution ? such that King(x) and
Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) - ? x/John,y/John works
- Unify(a,ß) ? if a? ß?
- p q ?
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of
variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
11Unification
- We can get the inference immediately if we can
find a substitution ? such that King(x) and
Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) - ? x/John,y/John works
- Unify(a,ß) ? if a? ß?
- p q ?
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) x/Jane
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of
variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
12Unification
- We can get the inference immediately if we can
find a substitution ? such that King(x) and
Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) - ? x/John,y/John works
- Unify(a,ß) ? if a? ß?
- p q ?
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) x/Jane
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) x/OJ,y/John
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of
variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
13Unification
- We can get the inference immediately if we can
find a substitution ? such that King(x) and
Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) - ? x/John,y/John works
- Unify(a,ß) ? if a? ß?
- p q ?
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) x/Jane
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) x/OJ,y/John
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) y/John,x/Mothe
r(John) - Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of
variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
14Unification
- We can get the inference immediately if we can
find a substitution ? such that King(x) and
Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) - ? x/John,y/John works
- Unify(a,ß) ? if a? ß?
- p q ?
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) x/Jane
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) x/OJ,y/John
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) y/John,x/Mothe
r(John) - Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ) fail
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of
variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
15Unification
- To unify Knows(John,x) and Knows(y,z),
- ? y/John, x/z or ? y/John, x/John,
z/John - The first unifier is more general than the
second. - There is a single most general unifier (MGU) that
is unique up to renaming of variables. - MGU y/John, x/z
16The unification algorithm
17The unification algorithm
Occurs check when unifying a variable x with a
term T, check whether x occurs in T. Note that
this should be done after the already found
substitutions are applied. For example, unifying
t(x,f(x)) and t(g(y),y) occur checks because
after x\g(y) is applied, one obtains
t(g(y),f(g(y))) and t(g(y),y). Unifying f(g(y))
with y leads to the attempted substitution
y\g(y), which triggers the occurs check, leading
to failure.
18Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP)
- p1', p2', , pn', ( p1 ? p2 ? ? pn ?q)
- q?
- E.g.,
- p1' is King(John) p1 is King(x)
- p2' is Greedy(y) p2 is Greedy(x)
- ? is x/John,y/John q is Evil(x)
- q ? is Evil(John)
- GMP used with KB of definite clauses (exactly one
positive literal) - All variables assumed universally quantified
where pi'? pi ? for all i
19Soundness of GMP
- Need to show that
- p1', , pn', (p1 ? ? pn ? q) q?
- provided that pi'? pi? for all I
- Lemma For any sentence p, we have p p? by UI
- (p1 ? ? pn ? q) (p1 ? ? pn ? q)? (p1? ?
? pn? ? q?) - p1', , pn' p1' ? ? pn' p1'? ? ? pn'?
- From 1 and 2, q? follows by ordinary Modus Ponens
20Example knowledge base
- The law says that it is a crime for an American
to sell weapons to hostile nations. The country
Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles, and
all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel
West, who is American. - Prove that Col. West is a criminal
21Example knowledge base ctd.
- ... it is a crime for an American to sell weapons
to hostile nations - American(x) ? Weapon(y) ? Sells(x,y,z) ?
Hostile(z) ? Criminal(x) - Nono has some missiles, i.e., ?x Owns(Nono,x) ?
Missile(x) - Owns(Nono,M1) and Missile(M1)
- all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel
West - Missile(x) ? Owns(Nono,x) ? Sells(West,x,Nono)
- Missiles are weapons
- Missile(x) ? Weapon(x)
- An enemy of America counts as "hostile
- Enemy(x,America) ? Hostile(x)
- West, who is American
- American(West)
- The country Nono, an enemy of America
- Enemy(Nono,America)
- Note This definite clause KB has no functions.
It is therefore a Datalog KB
22Forward chaining algorithm
23Forward chaining proof
24Forward chaining proof
25Forward chaining proof
26Properties of forward chaining
- Sound and complete for first-order definite
clauses - Datalog first-order definite clauses no
functions - FC terminates for Datalog in finite number of
iterations - May not terminate in general if a is not entailed
- This is unavoidable entailment with definite
clauses is semidecidable
27Efficiency of forward chaining
- Incremental forward chaining no need to match a
rule on iteration k if a premise wasn't added on
iteration k-1 - ? match each rule whose premise contains a newly
added positive literal - The rete algorithm builds a dataflow network to
allow for reuse of matchings it is used in
production system languages such as OPS-5 - Matching itself can be expensive
- Database indexing allows O(1) retrieval of known
facts - e.g., query Missile(x) retrieves Missile(M1)
- Forward chaining is widely used in deductive
databases
28Hard matching example
Diff(wa,nt) ? Diff(wa,sa) ? Diff(nt,q) ?
Diff(nt,sa) ? Diff(q,nsw) ? Diff(q,sa) ?
Diff(nsw,v) ? Diff(nsw,sa) ? Diff(v,sa) ?
Colorable() Diff(Red,Blue) Diff (Red,Green)
Diff(Green,Red) Diff(Green,Blue) Diff(Blue,Red)
Diff(Blue,Green)
- Colorable() is inferred iff the CSP has a
solution - CSPs include 3SAT as a special case, hence
matching is NP-hard
29Backward chaining algorithm
- SUBST(COMPOSE(?1, ?2), p) SUBST(?2, SUBST(?1,
p))
30Backward chaining example
31Backward chaining example
32Backward chaining example
33Backward chaining example
34Backward chaining example
35Backward chaining example
36Backward chaining example
37Backward chaining example
38Properties of backward chaining
- Depth-first recursive proof search space is
linear in size of proof - Incomplete due to infinite loops
- ? fix by checking current goal against every goal
on stack - Inefficient due to repeated subgoals (both
success and failure) - ? fix using caching of previous results (extra
space) - Widely used for logic programming
39Logic programming Prolog
- Algorithm Logic Control
- Basis backward chaining with Horn clauses
bells whistles - Widely used in Europe, Japan (basis of 5th
Generation project) - Compilation techniques ? 60 million LIPS
- Program set of clauses head - literal1,
literaln. - criminal(X) - american(X), weapon(Y),
sells(X,Y,Z), hostile(Z). - Depth-first, left-to-right backward chaining
- Built-in predicates for arithmetic etc., e.g., X
is YZ3 - Built-in predicates that have side effects (e.g.,
input and output predicates, assert/retract
predicates) - Closed-world assumption ("negation as failure")
- e.g., given alive(X) - not dead(X).
- alive(joe) succeeds if dead(joe) fails
40Prolog
- Appending two lists to produce a third
- append(,Y,Y).
- append(XL,Y,XZ) - append(L,Y,Z).
- query ?-append(A,B,1,2)
- answers A B1,2
- A1 B2
- A1,2 B
41Backward chaining is incomplete
- Goal trees are built by backward chaining
- C is true, as shown in the following (natural
deduction) proof by cases (split on D) - It is impossible to prove C by backward chaining
- Two additions make backward chaining complete
- addition of contrapositives (ex C -gt D)
- ancestor checking
42PTTP A Prolog Technology Theorem Prover
- Prolog is not a full theorem prover for three
main reasons - It uses an unsound unification algorithm without
the occurs check - Its inference system is complete for Horn
clauses, but not for more general formulas, as
shown in the previous slide - Its unbounded depth-first search strategy is
incomplete. Also, it cannot display the proofs it
finds - The Prolog Technology Theorem Prover (PTTP)
overcomes these limitations by - transforming clauses so that head literals have
no repeated variables and unification without the
occurs check is valid remaining unification is
done using complete unification with the occurs
check in the body - adding contrapositives of clauses (so that any
literal, not just a distinguished head literal,
can be resolved on) and the model- elimination
procedure reduction rule that matches goals with
the negations of their ancestor goals - using a sequence of bounded depth-first searches
to prove a theorem - retaining information on what formulas are used
for each inference so that the proof can be
printed - Proof of soundness and completeness follows from
the soundness and completeness of resolution
refutation
43Resolution brief summary
- Full first-order version
- l1 ? ? lk, m1 ? ? mn
- (l1 ? ? li-1 ? li1 ? ? lk ? m1 ? ?
mj-1 ? mj1 ? ? mn)? -
- where Unify(li, ?mj) ?.
- The two clauses are assumed to be standardized
apart so that they share no variables. - For example,
- ?Rich(x) ? Unhappy(x)
- Rich(Ken)
- Unhappy(Ken)
- with ? x/Ken
- Apply resolution steps to CNF(KB ? ?a) complete
for FOL
44Conversion to CNF
- Everyone who loves all animals is loved by
someone - ?x ?y Animal(y) ? Loves(x,y) ? ?y Loves(y,x)
- 1. Eliminate biconditionals and implications
- ?x ??y ?Animal(y) ? Loves(x,y) ? ?y
Loves(y,x) - 2. Move ? inwards ??x p ?x ?p, ? ?x p ?x ?p
- ?x ?y ?(?Animal(y) ? Loves(x,y)) ? ?y
Loves(y,x) - ?x ?y ??Animal(y) ? ?Loves(x,y) ? ?y
Loves(y,x) - ?x ?y Animal(y) ? ?Loves(x,y) ? ?y Loves(y,x)
45Conversion to CNF contd.
- Standardize variables each quantifier should use
a different one - ?x ?y Animal(y) ? ?Loves(x,y) ? ?z Loves(z,x)
-
- Skolemize a more general form of existential
instantiation. - Each existential variable is replaced by a Skolem
function of the enclosing universally quantified
variables - ?x Animal(F(x)) ? ?Loves(x,F(x)) ?
Loves(G(x),x) - Drop universal quantifiers
- Animal(F(x)) ? ?Loves(x,F(x)) ? Loves(G(x),x)
- Distribute ? over ?
- Animal(F(x)) ? Loves(G(x),x) ? ?Loves(x,F(x))
? Loves(G(x),x)
46Completeness of Resolution
- Resolution is refutation-complete if S is an
unsatisfiable set of clauses, then the
application of a finite number of resolution
steps to S will yield a contradiction
47Resolution proof definite clauses
- This is an input resolution proof
48Resolution proof general case
- Curiosity killed the cat pp.298-300 AIMA-2
- Not a unit resolution proof not an input
resolution proof
49Resolution Strategies
- Breadth-First Strategy (complete)
- Set-of-Support Strategy (complete)
- At least one parent of each resolvent is selected
from among the clauses resulting from the
negation of the goal or from their descendants
(the set of support) - Unit-Preference Strategy (complete)
- Unit Resolution (complete for Horn clauses
forward chaining) - Each resolvent has a parent that is a unit clause
- Linear-Input Form Strategy (not complete)
- Each resolvent has at least one parent belonging
to the base set (i.e. the set of clauses given as
input) - Complete for Horn clauses
- Called input resolution in AIMA
- Ancestry-Filtered Form Strategy (complete)
- Each resolvent has a parent that is either in the
base set or an ancestor of the other parent - Called linear resolution in AIMA
50Example KB Nilsson, 1980
- Whoever can read is literate
- (1) R(x) ? L(x)
- Dolphins are not literate
- (2) D(x) ? L(x)
- Some dolphins are intelligent
- (3a) D(A)
- (3b) I(A)
- Goal Some who are intelligent cannot read
- (4) I(z) ? L(z)
- Whoever can read is literate
- ?xR(x) ?L(x)
- Dolphins are not literate
- ?xD(x) ?L(x)
- Some dolphins are intelligent
- ?xD(x) ? I(x)
- Goal Some who are intelligent cannot read
- ?xI(x) ? L(x)
51An example proof
- (5) R(A) resolvent of 3b and 4
- (6) L(A) resolvent of 5 and 1
- (7) D(A) resolvent of 6 and 2
- (8) NIL resolvent of 7 and 3a
52Breadth-first strategy
53Set-of-Support Strategy
54Linear-Input Form Strategy
55Ancestry-Filtered Form Strategy
56Four more examples
- Prove by resolution the result of exercise 8.2
AIMA-2 - The goal is a universal formula!
- Group theory axioms and some consequences of them
Schoening, example on pp.94-95 - (a) every dragon is happy if all its children can
fly (b) green dragons can fly (c) a dragon is
green if it is a child of at least on green
dragon show that all green dragons are happy - (a) Every barber shaves all persons who do not
shave themselves (b) no barber shaves any person
who shaves himself or herself show that there
are no barbers - Shows the need for factoring or non-binary
resolution (p.297 AIMA-2)